You are on page 1of 32

The Ethics of the "Lettres Morales" and Rousseau's Philosophical Project Author(s): Marco Di Palma Source: Modern Philology,

Vol. 100, No. 2 (Nov., 2002), pp. 227-257 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1215731 Accessed: 09/11/2010 07:01
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpress. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Modern Philology.

http://www.jstor.org

The Ethics of the Lettresmoralesand Rousseau's Philosophical Project


MARCO DI PALMA London, England

During the winter of 1757-58, Jean-Jacques Rousseau composed the six letters known as the Lettresmorales,which were never sent to their intended addressee, Elisabeth-Sophie-Franeoise Lalive de Bellegarde, the comtesse d'Houdetot.' Setting out, in Rousseau's own words, the principles or rules of his moral teaching,2 these letters disclose a vision of spiritual progress toward a unifying state of happiness and wellbeing which, Rousseau affirms, constitutes the proper end of human life ("l'object de la vie est la f6licite de l'homme," 4:1087). Despite such authorial declarations, the letters have not only failed to attract the critical scrutiny they deserve, they have also been largely misunderstood when attended to. Commentators may frequently allude to them en passant, but such references serve principally to chart the destiny of metaphysical and theistic positions elaborated beyond the text in question. The ancillary status widely conferred on these writings stems from the long-standing view that they represent a set of gestating, incomplete religious and philosophical positions still too "naive" in themselves, which must await re-embodiment in the meditations of the Professiondefoi in Emile (1762) to emerge as coherent and mature theses. 3
1. Rousseau refers to these letters as "lettres morales" in his correspondence. See 51 Correspondance compklte, vols., ed. Ralph A. Leigh (Oxford: Institut et Musee Voltaire and Geneva: Les D61ices, 1965-71; Oxford: The Voltaire Foundation, 1972-95), 5:21. 2. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Lettresmorales, (Euvrescompletes, vols., ed. Bernard in 5 Gagnebin and Marcel Raymond (Paris: Pliade, 1959-95), 4:1081-1118, esp. 4:1081; see also Rousseau, Correspondance, 4:384. All references to the Pliade edition of Rousseau's complete works appear parenthetically in the text by volume and page number. I have modernized the spelling throughout. 3. See Henri Gouhier's critical introduction in Rousseau, (Euvres 4:cxci-cxcii. completes,

? 2002 by The Universityof Chicago. All rights reserved. 0026-8232/2003/10002-0003$10.00

227

228

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

Deviating from the nearly universal practice of simply acknowledging in these letters a source for Emile, meanwhile, a second class of readings no less reductive than the first challenges the designation of the letters as "moral" letters. Scholars point to Rousseau's justifications of morality through pleasure and aesthetic self-realization, which, they claim, problematize or even obliterate the intended ethical meaningfulness and value of these writings. For Paul de Man, the Lettresmorales entangle themselves in conceptual circularity by advocating a "eudaemonic valorization" of virtue through the "narcissistic economy of well-being" that ushers back the very self-conceit that Rousseau attempts to overcome.4 This view ignores, however, the inherent paradox that every moral reeducation must start by appealing to the corrupted nature of those it seeks to reform. More recently, Laurence D. Cooper cites the letters to support the argument that Rousseau "never proposes either a code of conduct, or a set of principles of action, or even a catalogue of virtues. He has written no Ethics. Rather than provide guidance for conduct, he addresses the sources of good conduct-which is to say, the circumstances favouring the development of a healthy soul." Instead of practical recommendations about how one should live, Rousseau generally restricts himself to the issue of "what one should be and how one might become what one should be" and the "education of the soul."5 The limitations of the Lettres morales exemplify this presumed insufficiency. Instead of providing principles, as they claim to do, they are concerned with nothing more than the achievement of a correct "setting" for the good life, and the measures they prescribe "have more to do with where to place oneself than with what to do."6 Skeptical of their moral content and destination, Cooper dismisses them as little more than "a handbook for enjoying rustic simplicity."7 These conclusions diminish the merit of the letters by masking from view a creative response-the earliest of its kind in the Rousseauian corpus-to the social and moral predicaments of modernity previously diagnosed in Rousseau's Discours sur les sciences et les arts (1750) and Discours sur l'originede l'inigaliti (1755). Their central objective, I wish to argue, lies in offering a practical vision of the moral life conceived as unfolding within the framework of society-as-it-is. This vision addresses the individual deprived of the assistance of a
4. Paul de Man, Allegoriesof Reading:Figural Language in Rousseau, Nietzsche,Rilke, and Proust (London: Yale University Press, 1979), p. 243. 5. Laurence D. Cooper, Rousseau, Nature, and the Problemof the GoodLife (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1999), p. 3. 6. Ibid., p. 3, n. 1. 7. Ibid., p. 3.

MarcoDi Palma o TheEthicsof theLettres morales

229

fully ethical community who, furthermore, cannot count on the resources of a natural education. Like Rousseau's political writings on Poland and Corsica (Projetde constitutionpour la Corse[ 1765, published in 1825] and Considerationssur le gouvernementde Pologne [1772, published in 1782]), the Lettres moralesillustrate Rousseau's underestimated capacity to formulate realistic, concrete solutions to circumscribed problems by attending to the possibility of personal reform and profitable engagement with an imperfect society. To vindicate this interpretation requires a reading sensitive to the inescapable sociological dimension of Rousseau's moral reflections, one that ties his ethics firmly to the reality from which they arise. Examining the first in isolation from the second risks a mistaken interpretation of both.8 Only by so contextualizing the letters may we proceed further and show that they outline a practical ethics attained through a combination of correct settings or postures and disciplined efforts directed toward the good life on the part of the moral agent. The letters are not short on detail about how one ought to live; their prescriptions about what one ought to be issue into considerations on the formative practices toward, and the acts that define and advance, the moral life as Rousseau envisages it. In addition to restoring prominence to an unfairly neglected text, this essay also seeks to advance a position, against established readings, on the wider question of interpreting Rousseau. I have already hinted that a common thread connects the early Discours and the Lettres morales.I want to suggest further that this continuity extends forward, in turn, to Emile-not simply because the letters anticipate the conception of conscience that eventually finds its way into the Profession de foi, nor because they signpost the subtle shift in philosophical allegiances that appears in the doctrines defended by the Savoyard Vicar. Rather, the social and ethical reflections formulated for the benefit of Sophie d'Houdetot exemplify the reconstructive side of Rousseau's thinking prior to Emile and provide a protocol for interpreting the malaise of modern Europeans diagnosed in the work on education. By illustrating how individuals might recapture spiritual unity through ordinary but enlightened endeavors, the letters eliminate the contradictions later depicted in Emile and, in so doing, question the validity of the sacrifice which those contradictions seem to necessitate as the purported price of future harmony. The Lettres moralesdemand a formulation of Rousseau's philosophical project in
8. Rousseau issues this warning in Emile: faut 6tudier la soci&t6 par les hommes, et "II les hommes par la soci6te: ceux qui voudront traiter s6par6ment la politique et la morale, n'entenderontjamais rien a aucune des deux" (4:524).

230

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

terms quite unlike those that have come to characterize it in some critical quarters. Viewed from this new perspective, the project ought to be defined neither by a fundamental duality of conflicting ideals, nor a devastating yet essentially sterile Utopian critique, but by a redemptive synthesis able to respond to the many-sided challenges of modernity.

Rousseau's project emerges more clearly when set against the background of the central crisis of modernity as he perceives it. In the opening pages of Emile (4:249-50), Rousseau draws a portrait of the bourgeois, the alienated and self-concerned being that henceforth represents modern man, torn between inclination and duty, and agonized by the combined disadvantages of two imperfectly embraced conditions. This everyman represents the stuttering victim of history, its arts and its sciences. He stands poised between the demands of a private but deeply unsatisfactory existence that no longer reflects an original self-sufficiency and the pressures generated by a pernicious community that abjectly fails to embody, let alone nurture, the human potential. With this predicament in mind, the question that subtends the Lettresmoralesmay be formulated thus: in the absence of an encompassing polis or an extended, autarkic oikos,and equally setting aside the Natural Man like Emile educated to withstand corruption, how might it be possible to enjoy psychic unity and happiness in a private sphere and yet still act virtuously with public and exemplary success? In other words, short of the support afforded by an unlikely ideal Republic, the dream world of Clarens and the miracles worked by the tutor through natural education, where can we find a fulcrum to reconcile the natural self with the demands of morality amid a decadent society? Of course, to speculate on this possibility involves rejecting in principle-or so it seems-the stark choice Emile subsequently proceeds to place before its readers, not to mention contradicting a good deal of well-informed secondary literature treating that choice as inescapable for Rousseau. Bringing an end to self-division appears to demand a choice between two incompatible ideals: an individualist philosophy of existence, essentially sentimental, aesthetic or Romantic in temper; and the virtuous, patriotic, and democratic collectivism of republics. We must either refuse history and retreat into nature where we may shelter innocent and good natural men or else hasten the progress of corruption toward a fuller, socialized but inevitably "denatured" condition to fashion moral, virtuous citizens. Taking this framework as

MarcoDi Palma o TheEthicsof theLettres morales

231

basic, Bernard Groethuysen accordingly identified in Rousseau a "duality of ideals."9 The widespread acceptance of this reading may be demonstrated by the fact that commentators hostile and sympathetic to Rousseau's reconstructive thought both endorse its underlying assumption of the mutual exclusivity of natural and civil freedoms. 10 Groethuysen's duality also bolsters a further influential reading that characterizes the Rousseauian project as an essentially critical exercise organized around a series of provocative antinomies. These serve to unmask our present crisis and to underline the significant restrictions we face if future prospects for regeneration are to rank as a possibility. Seeing in the two choices forwarded by Emile not a call for a decision-for one will never, can never, be made-but a castigation of actuality, Judith N. Shklar pursues this reading by denying that Rousseau ever proposes any end to the spiritual dissonance he so eloquently exposes. I Yet the Lettresmoraleshold out a rather different prospect. The letters reveal that the malaise Rousseau describes does not simply arise between the impulses of nature and the imperatives of morality. These demands collide when the inclinations of the human personality prove unequal to the onerous duties generated by an iniquitous society, which overwhelm the individual who strives to be moral. Without choosing between them, however, the letters elaborate a position that reconciles human nature and morality by making the self's duty to and productive coexistence with others a condition for its ultimate, natural fulfillment. This ambition might sound like little more than a restatement of the familiar moral psychology and politics that various eighteenth-century thinkers deduce from the empirical study of human needs, desires, and interests. Like many French philosophes,Rousseau indeed supports the response of Anthony Ashley Cooper, Earl of Shaftesbury, and Alexander Pope to the pessimists and detractors of human nature like Thomas Hobbes and Bernard Mandeville. And yet, he is far from
9. Bernard Groethuysen, J-J Rousseau (Paris: Gallimard, 1949), pp. 140-69. 10. Speaking for Rousseau's detractors, Lester G. Crocker insists that access to the civil state demands the axiomatic elimination of natural freedom and independence; see his Rousseau's "SocialContract": Interpretative An Essay (Cleveland: Press of Case Western Reserve University, 1968), p. 137. For Rousseau's supporters, Iain Hampsher-Monk similarly argues that the theoretical basis of freedom in Rousseau rests on the explicit opposition of "the natural" to "the political," in "Rousseau and Totalitarianism-with Hindsight?" in Rousseau and Liberty,ed. Robert Wokler (Manchester University Press, 1995), pp. 267-88, quotation on p. 278. 11. "Solitude is not the answer, but neither is society. In fact there simply is no solution"; Judith N. Shklar, Men and Citizens:A Study of Rousseau's Social Theory(Cambridge University Press, 1969), p. 159.

232

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

echoing the comforting reconciliation of self-interest and virtue often heard among leading philosophesof the period.12 Rousseau disturbs this cozy alliance by insisting that the philosophers have got it wrong concerning self-love, which is not the simple, basic element of the human psyche they think it is. Human nature, he holds, has undergone profound changes, to the point of dividing itself into two distinct and opposing orientations. To describe these competing motivations, Rousseau evokes the well-known polarity of the two loves: legitimate selflove (amour de soi) or the spontaneous, attractive force of nature that affirms and extends our sympathy to others and constitutes the basis of all the social virtues; and negative, self-enclosed love of self (amourpropre),which constricts and impedes these natural impulses (1:8056). This philosophical anthropology bears enormous consequences, not least of which is the impossibility of standard eighteenth-century vindications of self-love. Travestied by society, our fundamental propensities are for Rousseau no longer conducive to our own immediate happiness or prosperity, let alone able to lend themselves to the ends of collective utility and social peace. To "follow" or to "act in accordance with nature," once Rousseau has finished with this overused imperative, means something different from the same prescription advocated in the rationalist projects of Denis Diderot and Paul Henri Dietrich d'Holbach. Furthermore, the progressive excrescence of amourproprefrom the social thwarting of amour de soi signifies that authenticity and moral truth are available to very few. The transformation of morality, by which we become capable of judging competently of moral matters and ordering our desires, requires not an increase in rational or scientific knowledge, as Rene Descartes's Enlightened followers believed, but a profound reeducation of the human personality that calls for the renunciation of one condition and training for another. Central to this reeducation, as its condition of possibility, is the preexisting moral spontaneity of human nature that counterbalances the adverse accretions of its history. Modifying the arguments of those who appealed to natural law, Rousseau claims that we have inborn feelings and emotions deriving from an instinctive need of the human heart that, when eventually enlightened by reason, give us notions of justice and goodness (4:522-23). For this reason, he echoes Platonic and Stoic calls for a return to the true self where one meets, for Rousseau, not a set of decisive rational arguments, but a standard that any plain person adequately reflecting on his or her own moral experience can immediately grasp, the divine instinct of conscience acting
12. For an account of this debate, see Mark Hulliung, Autocritiqueof theEnlightenment: Rousseauand thePhilosophes (Cambridge, Mass.:Harvard University Press, 1994), pp. 19-26.

MarcoDi Palma o TheEthicsof theLettres morales

233

as infallible judge of good and evil ("instinct divin ... juge infaillible du bien et du mal" [4:1111]). We "possess" in advance the moral truth we search for, as Plato argued in the Meno, one that Rousseau characterizes as the dictate of conscience. The project of morality thereby consists in eliminating those obstacles that subdue this truth and prevent us from fully articulating it to ourselves as a principle of action. To conclude these preliminary reflections, the condition for the reconciliation of interest and virtue rests on the proper cultivation of the inner life. Only then can self-governing individuals prosper by placing themselves in the service of their fellows. The reconciliation also depends on gaining correct insights into what constitutes our true self-interest or happiness. Any genuine happiness, Rousseau argues, ought to be immune from the frustration and pain attendant on the loss of those fragile possessions we usually think of as goods. We need a principle that will unify morality and self-interest by making a desire for personal happiness both the motive that impels us toward, and the reward attendant on, genuinely virtuous behavior. The search for this to a release from the contradictions endured by principle-leading the bourgeois and allowing individuals to recapture and live authentic lives at one with their essence within, not outside or beyond, a corrupt the ambitious task of the Lettresmorales. society-defines II That Rousseau never produced an Ethics in no way indicates that he failed to come up with guidance for the good life. Far from being unsatisfactory on this count, as some commentators suggest, the Lettres moralesare concerned with the principle of morality from which all considerations about the good life must proceed. Yet to characterize the ethics of the letters properly, we must set aside some of our usual modern assumptions about formal ethical methods and enquiries. Rousseau's interests inevitably appear para-ethical if the education of the soul and its correlate, a sound milieu in which that education must unfold, are sidelined. When these interests are seen as essential rather than peripheral to the question of the good life, a different picture of Rousseau's intentions emerges. Seeking to innovate a way out of the crisis of modernity, Rousseau revisits the premodern ethical project. He does so not to rediscover a set of virtues by the light of reason, but rather to recover, as a religious thinker and a psychologist, a motivational principle deep within the human personality that can serve as a secure basis of morality. Full access and sensitivity to this principle depend on the excellence achieved by dint of exercise and self-discipline sponsored by a carefully orchestrated, benign environment.

234

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

The Lettresmoralesstick closely to the well-known, original meaning of 'ethics' (ithikos), indicating what relates to "character" (ithos) on the one hand, and what is ultimately good or desirable as an end in itself on the other. Where modern deontological ethics asks "which rules ought I to follow?" ancient virtue ethics asks "what kind of person should I become?" The first question typically involves an investigation into right conduct and duty, while references to the agent's own interests or happiness are usually considered of subsidiary importance. The second, by contrast, places these interests at the center of its enquiries to discover the ultimate or sovereign human good. So conceived, this good represents a practical end attained through the excellence of character comprising those dispositions which lead a person to live a particular kind of life in a particular context or milieu. Crucially, however, the aims of private interest or happiness do not exclude rule following or duty; rather, the former imply the latter, which are intrinsic to the good being sought. It is with the summum bonum ("souverain bien" [4:1087]), determined by human nature and which the good life seeks to realize, that Rousseau is concerned in his letters. Explicit too is the intrinsic goal of all human endeavors: the happiness Rousseau calls filiciti, an inward fulfillment that brings inner well-being and wisdom ("elle remon devient plit l'ame de tout ce qui fait le bonheur de l'homme... en dedans et heureux pour soi" [4:1088]). Having identified the sage supreme good, the Lettresmoralesturn to the perfection of their addressee's nature and the virtues most conducive to achieving that good. Distinguishing what we are from what we should be, the ethical judgment implicit in the second letter takes a hypothetical form, expressed in terms of what Sophie ought to do if she does not want her natural desire for happiness to be frustrated. Given that this well-being represents the proper goal of the intrinsically good human life ("l'object de la vie est la f6licite de l'homme" [4:1087]), Rousseau naturally addresses the means by which one might attain it. Rousseau's project demands an initial transformation of the moral personality-the education of the soul, will, or character--leading to recommendations of practical forms of behavior and social duties, as we will observe later on. But, given that securing private happiness and performing duties constitute the same order of excellence, those recommendations possess a categorical force by virtue of belonging to an overall view of the good life, rather than as rules or injunctions abstracted from it. The Lettres moralesseek to refashion Sophie into a member of an immediate community and someone capable of establishing new social relationships in which some localized justice may find expression. This practical ideal can be deduced from generic considerations of

Marco Di Palma o

The Ethics of the Lettres morales

235

the text as much as from a close examination of its fundamental philosophical submissions. Rousseau is working within an identifiable ethical genre. The letters to Sophie communicate on several levels. Their themes are typical of philosophical, moralist, and autobiographical literature, their tone alternating among discursive, polemic, apologetic, and hortative registers. As with other instances of Rousseau's considerable correspondence-notably, the reply to Voltaire on Providence (4:1059-78) and the polemical defense of Emile sent to the elucidate or problematize Archbishop of Paris (4:925-1030)--they central aspects of eighteenth-century thought by recalling the philosophical epistolography of Plato, Aristotle, Epicurus, and especially Seneca. 13 As always, strong moral impulses inform Rousseau's mode of writing. The resources of philosophical epistolography serve the directeur de conscience when advising those like the young Franquieres (4:113347), who addressed him in a state of moral doubt. Philosophical letters and those providing spiritual guidance tend to overlap. Indeed, as their title indicates, the Lettres morales belong to the genre of the "moral letter," even though this has been disputed by those who would annex them to the productions of literary confession. Charles William Hendel views them as a spiritual testament of value only to Rousseau himself as he considers his soul in the face of impending death brought on by serious ill health. Hendel detects an overly personal, confessional style that compromises the soundness of the moralist's recommendations and deprives them of the reassurance needed to encourage Sophie to adopt them. Rousseau, it seems, cannot extricate himself from the incidents that occurred during his sojourn at L'Ermitage and an obsession with "the shadows of guilty passion, and imputations of disloyalty, ingratitude, and misanthropy."'4 In a similar vein and for the reasons outlined earlier, Cooper concludes that the Lettresmoralesare "not what we might normally expect from 'moral letters.' "15 What should we expect, then? Seneca's Epistulae morales,whose title Rousseau's work echoes, provide one obvious important model. A reader and translator of Seneca, Rousseau was well acquainted with the Stoic's epistles.'6 Indeed, resemblances to Rousseau's own philosophy
13. Other epistles written to lesser-known contemporaries similarly provide substantial considerations of ethics, education, and politics. See Rousseau, (n. Correspondance 1 above), 9:143-47; 19:197-200; 18:115-24; and 33:238- 41. 14. Charles William Hendel, Jean-Jacques Rousseau:Moralist, 2 vols. (London: Oxford University Press, 1934), 1:315. 15. Cooper, p. 3. 16. Gisele Bretonneau, Stoicisme valeurs et chezj-J. Rousseau(Paris: Sedes, 1977), p. 152.

236

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

are clearly visible throughout the Senecan letters.17 Seneca gave the epistolary genre its most accomplished expression as a vehicle for promoting the moral progress of an aspiring protege. Taking the formation of character as the framework for a comparison, it is possible to identify several formal features which the Lettresmoralesshare with the Epistulae moralesand other instances of classical philosophic letter writing. Ancient theorists of the letter writing tradition held that maintaining friendships was the fundamental function of the letter. Is Friends remain present in heart and mind even though absent to one another, but the letter offers more than simply a vehicle for sharing affections. A pedagogical dimension of the exchange of letters makes explicit the connection between the interests of friendship and those of virtue. Letter writing enshrines the moral life in a rapport between individuals who, to a greater or lesser extent, stand apart from society. Recourse to so confidential a medium as the letter of friendship appears perfectly intelligible once the Stoic horizons in Seneca and Rousseau are reinstated to reflect the fragmented sociopolitical reality exerting its influence on the transmission and cultivation of ethics. Subject to these restricted horizons, the focus of the moral life returns to a private, subjective dimension in which wider external conditions make it incumbent on the individual will, not the community, to bring about and sustain an inevitably localized good. Grounded in friendship, the moral letter typically involves an invitation to the philosophical life and a progressive transformation of self to ensconce the principles of that life in the beliefs and actions of the recipient. Sensitive to the changing psychological dispositions involved in this undertaking, classical writers tailored their letters to take account of the dynamics of moral progress. Stanley Stowers identifies two kinds of letters that meet the demands of such progress, the protrepticor "conversion" letter and the paranaetic or "confirmation" letter.19 Protreptic letters (after Aristotle's Protrepticus)call on the recipient to accept a new way of life unlike that ordinarily pursued in society. While obviously stating in positive terms the ends the correspondent ought to seek, the protreptic letter refutes possible objections or doctrines deemed erroneous. Epicurus, for instance, takes
17. Uncovering the Stoic inspiration of Rousseau's ethical and political thought, Kennedy E Roche suggested that we might "by an almost random dipping into the Epistles to Lucilius, meet some of the salient features common to Seneca and Rousseau"; see his Rousseau:Stoic and Romantic (London: Methuen, 1974), p. x. 18. Stanley K. Stowers, Letter Writing in Greco-Roman Antiquity (Philadelphia: Westminster, 1986), p. 58. 19. Ibid., p. 92.

Marco Di Palma o

The Ethics of the Lettres morales

237

issue with what he deems mistaken views on the gods, death, and the nature of pleasure.20 In his letters, Rousseau similarly excludes as false those forms of happiness that emphasize ownership of material goods (commoditis),money, luxury, and the refinement of manners (4:1089). Philosophical protreptic also highlights a deficiency in the recipient's character which he or she is encouraged to overcome through selfknowledge. Paraenetic letters (paraenesis,moral exhortation or advice), meanwhile, encourage and guide correspondents to persevere in the life they have chosen. Originating with Epicurus and receiving its most comprehensive treatment from Seneca, the paraenetic letter promotes the formation of character. The writer enjoins his correspondent to adopt good habits that conform to a model character, typically the writer's own, and which the correspondent is invited to imitate. Uniting two absent friends in spirit is the desideratum of Rousseau's first letter ("cet &crit n'aurait d'autre usage que celui de nous rapprocher quelquefois et de renouveller dans l'Floignement ces doux entretiens" [1:1085]). Letters generate the illusion of spontaneous conversation by recreating the "living voice" [viva voce] and the intimacy of the "common life" [convictus] that is so fundamental to the teacher-student relationship between Seneca and Lucilius.21 Though he expressly denies that his aim is to give Sophie lessons, Rousseau draws on the same illusion. Overcoming the destructive effects of time and physical separation, a spiritual presence acts as the medium to nourish and perpetuate the memory of special moments in the past during which the friends exhorted each other to virtue ("deux aimes sensibles s'encourager mutuellement tala vertu" [1:1085]). The epistolary genre also possesses a second virtue, one capable of directly furthering ethical objectives within the restricted confines of a privileged friendship. Letters, as the Greek rhetorician Demetrius observed, excel in giving expression to the writer's character as well as in maintaining friendships.22 By nurturing friendship, ancient epistolography presented philosophy with an effective framework for moral education. Borrowing from the psychological rhetorical proofs set out by Aristotle in his Rhetoric(2.1), its success rests on the recognition of hthosor the persuasive force of model characters. An exemplary character that embodies wisdom in living delivers a powerful invitation to,
20. Epicurus's letter to Monoeceus, cited in Stowers, pp. 116-18. 21. Seneca, Ad Lucilium epistulae morales(Lettersto Lucilius) 6.3-5, 75.1, ed. and trans. Richard C. Gummere, 3 vols. (London: Heinemann, 1935, reprint, 1958), 1:27, 2.137. All subsequent citations of this work (hereafter abbreviated as Ep. mor) will be given parenthetically in the text. 22. Demetrius, On Style,trans. W. Rhys Roberts (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1932), p. 227; cited in Stowers, p. 38.

238

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

and encouragement to persist in, the philosophical life. For this reason, Seneca insists that examples (exempla) are more beneficial than mere "precepts" (praecepta)for impressing his Stoic teaching on the mind of Lucilius (Ep. mor.,6.5). Yet persuading others to accept the life of wisdom and sponsoring their progress to reach its goals only partially captures the significance of character. The fundamental equality and reciprocity of benefits enshrined by the institution of friendship points much further. Both the Epistulae moralesand the Lettresmoralesattempt to bring about the moral transformation of their respective addressees through friendship, but in neither case does this mean that the letters' effect is destined for the benefit of the correspondent alone. Letter writing bears a dual effect: obviously, on the recipient who receives advice and exhortation, but equally on the writer of the letter who offers these. The improvement of both lies at the heart of the moral letter. Advancing and sustaining the commitment to the life of philosophical wisdom falls to the writer as much as his addressee, mirroring the inescapable openness of self-improvement. Authors benefit from their own moral discourse since letter writing simultaneously exercises and rehearses the principles it advocates. The reality and necessity of mutual self-improvement, underwritten by the basic equality of author and addressee, arise repeatedly in the Epistulae morales.Rather than posing as a sage who has fully achieved the wisdom he imparts to Lucilius, Seneca has merely traveled further down the road that continues to stretch before him. He considers himself an invalid, not a doctor (Ep. mor., 27.1, 68.8), and feels the continuing need to take himself to task, presenting himself as the addressee of his own advice (Ep. mor., 26.7, 27.1). The work of selfimprovement denotes an ongoing experience common to both writer and recipient, who enter into ajoint act of self-transformation: "Welcome those whom you yourself can improve. The process is mutual; for men learn while they teach" (Ep. mor, 7.8-9). In training the excellence of another, they train their own: "The wise man also needs to have his virtues kept in action; and as he prompts himself to do things, so is he prompted by another wise man" (Ep. mor.,109.2). Reciprocal self-improvement, expressed by the didactic and hortatory intentions behind the representation of character, provides the ostensible justification for Rousseau's letters. But Rousseau's apologetic anxieties are never far away from the central questions of the moral letter. Indeed, these anxieties find an appropriate outlet for expression in the disclosure of character and its moral principles. The Lettresmorales,in actual fact, exploit the opportunity for self-scrutiny and self-revelation to pursue a complex strategy that operates by way

Marco Di Palma o

The Ethics of the Lettres morales

239

of superimposing both the mimetic ends tied to the exhibition of character and the introspective discovery of the true foundations of ethics onto concerns arising from personal apologetics. I will examine each of these superimpositions in turn. The desire to make his conduct speak as eloquently as his writings defines Rousseau's relationship to his contemporaries at this time. Some eighteen months earlier, he had taken his leave of Paris and the philosophesin a highly public move designed to set an example of how to live the principles proclaimed in his works. But unlike the voluntaristic personal reform undertaken in 1751, described in the Confessions (1:362), and in relation to which the decision to abandon the capital and its seductions signaled the latest development, the Lettres morales construe Rousseau's character as the outcome of the spontaneous goodness of Sophie's personality, from which his own efforts to nurture her moral progress spring. Each offsets the deficiencies of the other: while he is experienced in wisdom but subject to weakness, she is naturally predisposed to virtue but lacking the necessary instruction and training that would enable her to be fully what she is only potentially. Recognition that each owes their transformation to the other establishes their equality. For Sophie, this transformation involves an initiation into an authentic way of living; for Rousseau, a sublimation of his passion and a recognition of this young woman as a dutiful wife and mother, much as St. Preux in La nouvelle Hiloise (1761) will later perceive Julie on his return to the Wolmar household. Rousseau considers Sophie's transformation as coextensive with his own redemption. His letters on morality will improve him because, in offering himself as a model for her to imitate, he will need to give the example of his teaching ("ce que j'aurais fait pour vous rachetera l'inutilit6 de ma vie entiere ...j'en deviendrais meilleur moi-mime, en m'6fforpant de vous donner l'exemple des vertus dont je veux vous inspirer l'amour" [4:1084]). But this example is not the outcome of any independent efforts on his part. At the end of a strikingly confessional passage in the fourth letter, Rousseau acknowledges that his force has derived from Sophie, who has helped him to master himself, holding him to virtue, to the duty of friendship, and to his own principles: "Tel est l'1tat d'une ame qui s'osant proposer tavous pour exemple ne vous offre en cela que le fruit de vos soins" (4:1104). The guide has proven himself a good pupil and the letters serve to invite further reflections from which their writer hopes to profit: "Examinez, discernez, choississez, daignez m'expliquer les raisons de votre choix, et puissiez-vous tirer autant de profit de ces lettres que l'auteur en attend de vos refl xions" (4:1085). The effect and recognition of an ongoing transformation, the Lettresmoraleshope to occasion a further transformation

240

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

in the subject for whom they are destined. Inspired by her native goodness, Rousseau's example confronts Sophie as the catalyst for her own improvement. The self-intensifying nature of these exchanges reminds one of Aristotle's ideal of friendship, based on advancing moral excellence by sharing and amplifying virtuous activity through mutual recognition and admiration of the other's virtues. Although the Lettres morales never explicitly refer to this ideal, the joint task of friends who advance virtue as a common interest recalls both Seneca and the private ethics of friendship that Aristotle articulates in books 8 and 9 of the Nicomachean Ethics. But friendship and the moral letter also express an unavoidable fact of private ethics. The forum of friendship constitutes a necessary condition of the self's improvement since the inner life is incapable of being fully "interiorized," to use Catherine Edwards's phrase.23 Communication with the other is essential to maintaining one's moral identity and the discursive reflection generated by the medium of writing prevents it from atrophying. It is precisely the ethopoetic role of writing, whose importance for the art of living has been emphasized by Michel Foucault, that we are concerned with here.24 Writing offers a concrete, objective substratum in which thought exercises itself and reactivates what it knows, calling to mind a principle, rule, or example on which it reflects and subsequently assimilates into action in advance of circumstances that call for that knowledge to be summoned in practice. Seneca conceives his letters as so many opportunities for personal exercise, and he deliberately commits to paper salutares admonitiones,prescriptions he offers to others because he has found them efficacious for his own ills (Ep. mor, 8.2). Reaffirming his principles, Rousseau strives to demonstrate that they and the man who espouses them are all of a piece. This unity had been questioned by the recent fiasco of his personal dealings with Diderot, Fr6d6ric-Melchior Grimm, Louise-Florence-Petronille Lalive Epinay, and Jean-Frangois, Marquis de St Lambert. Setting forth his views on how Sophie ought to live, Rousseau claims not to be delivering lessons as such but to be making a profession of faith (1:1085). No hiatus intervenes between spiritual autobiography and the moralist's central message about the true foundations of morality. The profession is delivered in a confessional passage (4:1102-4) that coincides with the letters' enquiry into the basis for morality. Self-scrutiny reveals that certain moral dispositions, identified with the working of con23. Catherine Edwards, "Self-Scrutiny and Self-Transformation in Seneca's Letters," Greece and Rome44 (1997): 23-38 (quotation on 27). 24. Michel Foucault, "L'6criture de soi," in Dits et icrits (1954-1988), 4 vols. (198088), ed. Daniel Defert and Frangois Ewald (Paris: Gallimard, 1994), 4:415-30 (quotation on p. 417).

Marco Di Palma o

The Ethics of the Lettres morales

241

science at the end of the fifth letter, remain intact despite the vicissitudes of good and evil. These act by way of a secret judgment that directs our present actions equally by self-prescribed rules and by those of our past, blaming or approving them as if they belonged to the present. Retracing this profession of faith for Sophie enables Rousseau to reexpress the principles of his moral self in a characteristic practice of rassemblement performed in the autobiographies.25 Situated in biographical context, the Lettresmoralesrehearse and renew the deliberations that motivated the personal reform. The practical advice Sophie will receive, meanwhile, is identical to that which the author of the letters has already followed, their recommendations mirroring and affirming his prior endeavors. Literary confession is essential to the methods of the moral letter. Introspection and self-scrutiny represent an exemplary spiritual act that cannot be divorced from the reflexive, experiential morality Seneca and Rousseau strive to impart. What both search for and discover within is conceived as of use to themselves, their proteges who are fellow travelers and, implicitly, the uninitiated majority ignorant of the philosophical life.26 Addressing a specific individual, her moral makeup, status, and place within a given social milieu, Rousseau's letters exhort Sophie to cultivate specific virtues and accept specific duties appropriate to her condition. A successful outcome will depend on Sophie's conversion to the life of wisdom made possible by overcoming the character deficiencies that obstruct her self-knowledge and, subsequently, confirming this insight by acquiring ethical habits that prevent her from falling away from the path of wisdom. It remains to be shown how these endeavors, belonging to the aims of the protreptic and paranaetic letter outlined earlier, translate into practical advice on how to overcome a defective personality and attain self-knowledge and virtue. III The moral letter concerns itself with the pursuit of well-being, understood as the highest good, through self-knowledge and the progressive cultivation of the soul. It also presupposes a view of human nature and the conditions of its flourishing (eudaimonia) in which actions or moral aims on the one hand, and living well on the other, cannot be
25. Compare the passage in the third "Promenade" of Les Rlveries du promeneursolitaire (posthumously published in 1782) that begins: "Fixons une bonne fois mes opinions" (1:1016). 26. For Georg Misch (A History of Autobiography Antiquity, 2 vols. [London: Routin ledge & Kegan Paul, 1950], 2:421), retreating into solitary conscience is common to Seneca, Augustine, and Rousseau.

242

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

separated. States of character, as Aristotle taught (NicomacheanEthics 2.1), arise from like activities. Rousseau's letters, like Seneca's, are "moral letters" in the sense that they involve the practice of ethics understood as a concern with the qualities or virtues of character (ithos) and those settled dispositions, acquired through habit, to act in a certain way and in certain circumstances in relation to the supreme good. But Rousseau's letters also convey wisdom in living as a pursuit of virtue as well as happiness. Seen from the predicament of man and citizen highlighted earlier, this pursuit signifies that the solution to modernity's dilemmas is not to destroy the residue of natural goodness but to build on and strengthen it. We are, Rousseau holds, creatures estranged from our essential good, our moral ills the result of competing motivations whereby the accretions of a decadent society incessantly war with the promptings of a residual, natural goodness at once irreducible and incapable of bringing the inner conflict to a successful end. The possibility of uniting happiness with virtue lies not in the eradication of nature, but rather in the successful elimination of recalcitrant motivations that obstruct self-knowledge and stifle the good instincts we should nurture. Of course, the continuity I am proposing between the natural (inclination) and the ethical (virtue) contradicts a fundamental tenet familiar to all readers of Rousseau. This tenet insists on the agonist character of virtue as a hard-fought victory against nature, an overcoming of self beyond the capacity of most to achieve.27 Yet the letters challenge precisely this view. Addressing Sophie in the very first letter, Rousseau promises: "Je m'occuperai de vous, de vos devoirs, des vertus qui vous conviennent, des moyens de perfectionner votre heureux naturel" (4:1082). This ambition is significant. Setting the well-known tableau of inner conflict (vertu-combat) one side, Rousseau conceives to Sophie's progress in relation to her discharging appropriate obligations and virtues. But the duties of the social life and the virtues are in no way divorced from a perfectionist concern with Sophie's most important natural capacities and potentialities. On the contrary, they contribute to the flourishing of the distinctive human excellence and, I will argue, represent the apotheosis of nature realized through the progressive efforts of the ethical will working through the habits of moral freedom. Sophie, we learn, is favorably inclined to moral beauty (4:1083) but this intuition remains inoperative in the absence of full self-knowledge
27. "I1n'y a point de ... vertu sans combat. Le mot de vertu vient de force; la force est la base de tout vertu" (4:817). La Nouvelle Hiloise expresses a similar view: "La vertu est un 6tat de guerre... pour y vivre on a toujours quelque combat Arendre contre soi" (2:682).

MarcoDi Palma o TheEthicsof theLettres morales

243

or knowledge about human nature and its end. Access to these crucial insights, the first letter states, depends on the will: "Ce qui vous manque encore ne depend plus que de votre volonte" (4:1083). As the subsequent letters make clear, the problem of the bad will (amourpropre) operates on two interrelated levels. First, it thwarts personal happiness and beneficial human relations by enslaving individuals to a narrow self-interest indifferent to public welfare. Artificial desires created by vanity and incapable of being satisfied create frustration and the nurturing of feelings incompatible with peaceful coexistence with others. Second, this state of affairs also coalesces with the absence of self-knowledge, which proves elusive for those whose unregenerate impulses impel them to exist outside themselves. For the letters, the task of recapturing this knowledge is of primary importance and precedes the restoration of harmonious social relations. At this juncture, however, Rousseau introduces a familiar critique designed to disqualify a rival candidate to truth. Rather than providing a reliable source for the knowledge Sophie is encouraged to seek, traditional and vain philosophical endeavors, as the second and third letters understand them, only lead us astray. Rationalists, for instance, erect shaky systems which empiricists then simply restrict or undo completely (4:1090-91); the empiricists' appeal to the senses, meanwhile, relativizes and confines all knowledge to the sphere of utility (4:1092-93). Neither proves capable of capturing moral truth, but then virtually all purely intellectual efforts are sustained by a defective will that clamors for an outward distinction inimical to the truth found only in the inward self. Only there can the individual discover his true frame, duty, or end ("sa nature, ses devoirs et sa fin" [Discours sur les scienceset les arts, 3:6]). Taking the problem of self-knowledge as fundamental, Rousseau's idea of spiritual progress involves two key moments in which the will figures centrally. In the first instance, a residual ethical will allows the individual to assume the correct spirit for conducting the search for an intellectual and moral guide that sweeps away the errors and absurdities of philosophical conceit to establish contact with the "inner voice" (voix int&ieure [4:1104]). In the second, that same will works toward the "art of happiness" (l'art d'tre heureux [4:1115]), a settled disposition for right choices achieved through exercise and training, able to unite personal fulfillment with virtue. A reorientation of the will, therefore, constitutes the condition for moral truth delivered by self-knowledge. Thereafter, Rousseau calls on Sophie to sustain and preserve the awareness of this truth as a new identity or motivation of the will through the transforming power of repeated, habitual acts. The principle of askesisprovides an ideal way of articulating the mood and practices of the transformation Rousseau outlines. In Hellenistic

244

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

and Roman schools of philosophy, askesisdesignates the sum of "spiritual exercises" necessary for the art of living, consisting in a return to the original core of self and leading to a universality beyond private desires and attachments through practical forms of behavior.28 Two key moments define the progressive askesisin the Lettresmorales.The first endeavors to achieve spiritual self-possession. Rousseau often reThe second emphasizes training and fers to this state as recueillement. deliberately exercised dispositions that foster practical habits. To illuminate this distinction further, we may turn to two very different French thinkers from the twentieth century who interpreted askesisas a divestment and a perseverance of the will, respectively. For Gabriel Marcel, acise involves a purification that vouchsafes genuine insight into truth only when fully deserved. Detached or purely speculative thought, which considers knowledge a merely technical operation leaving the knower wholly unaffected, cannot hope to seize it. The act of knowing binds knowledge to a mode of participation.29 Rousseau echoes this in the Third "Promenade" of Les Rovenies produ meneursolitaire (posthumously published in 1782) when he faults his contemporaries for seeking to investigate human nature and cosmology through dispassionate philosophizing while neglecting to ascertain their relation to the knowledge they sought to establish (1:1012-13). That which we seek, in other words, is indistinguishable from that which enables us to seek it. The circularity of this statement will not pass unnoticed. Indeed, it points to a necessary condition of moral progress in Rousseau, as we shall soon see. The later Foucault, meanwhile, highlighted the aspect of askesis concerned with exercise or drill, the self-discipline achieved by progressively assimilating learned truths into permanent principles of action. Through askesis, aletheia becomes Nthos, truth a motive for the will.30 Before turning to the positive recommendations of the Lettresmorales, I would like to explore this twin-sided askesis, starting with the methods by which Sophie achieves self-knowledge and regains contact with her moral sources. The Rousseauian search after truth, the infallible guide provided by conscience, demands a propaedeutics propelled by an intense self-involvement. Far from simple introspeca discition, access to the core of self-one's conscience-represents
28. On askesisin ancient and contemporary thought, see Pierre Hadot, Exercisesspirituels (Paris: Etudes Augustiniennes, 1981). 29. Gabriel Marcel, Etre et avoir (Paris: Aubier, 1935; reprint, Editions Universitaires, du 1991), p. 138, and Position et approchesconcretes mystereontologique(Paris: Desclee de Brouver, 1933; reprint, Vrin, 1949), p. 57. 30. See Michel Foucault, "Les Techniques de soi," in Dits et icrits, 1954-1988, 4:783813, esp. p. 800.

MarcoDi Palma o TheEthicsof theLettres morales

245

plined mode of apprehending that exercises what Rousseau, in his first published work, Discours sur les sciences et les arts, calls an "inner sense" (sens intrieur [3:196]) and by which we become morally selfcritical. What we seek relates entirely to how we seek it. Rousseau insists we must first secure the conditions through which the truth of conscience emerges. Its reception by consciousness may be likened, as Paul Ricoeur holds, to a form of hospitality in which the individual acts as host to the values received in a private space qualified by oneself.31 Genuine philosophy accordingly requires adopting the perspective of inwardness ("il faut commencer par rentrer en soi pour apprendre a philosopher" [4:1113]). However, the inward journey to self-illumination proves too difficult for the self-enclosed, alienated consciousness without a reorientation that divests the will of its amourpropreand redirects its attention away from a fascination with outward things. The receptivity of consciousness and the subsequent response of the will jointly determine the destiny of moral impulses. Central to the first is the quality or intensity of apperceptions: the clarity with which the voice of conscience speaks, for instance, or the distinctiveness of the traces it writes on the heart, to borrow two of Rousseau's favorite metaphors. In the second, we are free to heed or turn a deaf ear to this voice and direct our inward gaze toward or away from the soul, thereby strengthening or weakening our moral sources. While we must render ourselves fit for truth, it is also true to say that the self already houses that truth. The reorientation and subsequent reeducation of the human personality indicate, as I have suggested, two moments that characterize spiritual progress. In order to get to the heart of Rousseau's message, a comparison of the Lettresmorales with Platonic and Stoic doctrines of moral education will prove useful. In Platonic anamnesis, the soul rediscovers its original nature, uncovering and disclosing the truth within and making itself, in turn, the place where that truth may take up residence. For Stoicism, truth belongs not in oneself but in the logoi, the true discourses or teachings of the master that imparts it, and which the pupil subjectivizes as abiding principles of action.32 It is this pedagogical relationship that Rousseau transposes into the Platonic relation of the soul to itself. The soul appropriates a truth from within that it then internalizes as consubstantial with itself as a subjective grounding (habitus) for the will. A relation between inward values and their conscious perception
31. Paul Ricoeur, Philosophiede la volonti, 2 vols. (Paris: Aubier, 1950; reprint, 1988), 1:76. 32. Foucault has dealt with this pedagogical aspect of Stoicism in "L'Hermeneutique du sujet," Dits et &crits, 1954-1988, 4:353-65 (esp. pp. 359-60); and "Les Techniques de soi," 4:799.

246

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

may eventually yield a new, superior unity. A synthesis of the Platonic and the Stoic, the Rousseauian self is thus causa sui, both master and pupil, an apprentice of itself able to become fully in act what it was merely potentially. Rousseauian moral perfectibility demands the development of an interior, dialogic relationship of the soul to itself mediated, as we have seen, by communication with others. Although an innate given of the human personality, the full realization of this capacity for dialogue is not automatic but further represents an achievement won through effort and training. The recovery and possession of insights that provide the starting point for the moral life remain provisional, their continuity depending on subsequent cultivation. Modifying Platonic and Stoic sources, the Lettresmoralescombine the work of recovering moral truth with that of subjectivizing it as a motive for the will. In the first instance, they affirm the autonomy of one's soul, the enduring inner dispositions of which do not correspond to the destiny of one's fortune or the world of external vicissitudes ("ces dispositions interieures ind6pendantes du sort et des ev&nements" [4:1102]). Beyond the wellspring of desires and sensations continually succeeding one another, Rousseau claims that individuals are also gifted with an irreducible and persisting moral anchor unmoved by the momentary states of their phenomenal self, which it holds up to scrutiny. Rousseau elsewhere refers to this hegemonic capacity as the constant will (volonti constante [4:65152]), a sovereign ethical will that stands over inferior, contingent wills and that also characterizes the general will expressed by the political community (Du contratsocial [1762], 3:440). Fully capturing this capacity-the sensitivity to injustice and moral beauty, the voice that intrudes involuntarily to judge the phenomenal self-represents the second, Stoic ambition of the letters. They teach that the discontinuous and intermittently perceived awareness of moral truth, such as one feels during remorse or, positively, in the satisfaction of doing good, may emerge from within to reassimilate and permanently embed itself as a disposition for future action. It is this grounding for the constant, but intermittently present, ethical will that Sophie is encouraged to acquire. Thus, Sophie must first alleviate the tension between a residual good will and the counterwill of amour-propre fostered by life in society, and then annul the distance between knowledge and action by contracting a disposition for virtue through habit. To understand how she enters a condition characterized by the full internalization of new values as motives of the will, readers need to recall an extraordinary work which Rousseau was contemplating at this time. The spiritual progress at the heart of the letters relies on the abandoned project for La Moralesensitive, ou le matrialisme du sage (ca. 1756) (1:408-9). Its cardinal idea is

Marco Di Palma o

The Ethics of the Lettres morales

247

brilliantly simple: identifying in the external environment and in our own physiology the seat of dispositions at odds with the imperatives of reason and virtue, Rousseau sees that these same material conditions offer us an opportunity to favor the moral order they so frequently disturb.33 Set in the context of the Lettresmorales,the insights of the Morale sensitive provide initial support for fostering an environment and a material regimen conducive to reorienting the will so that it may then begin to contract dispositions to support moral reform. The first task of unifying the will requires askesis to provide the proper mood and spirit for inwardness. To know the self, for Rousseau, signifies discovering its moral source in the wellspring of conscience. Through introspection, and by progressively recovering an authentic selfhood from routine dissipation and projection into the external world of people and objects, Sophie must strive for an awareness that acquaints her with the "voice" of conscience (4:1104), the innate "principle" of moral truth (4:1108). To bring this voice within audible range, Rousseau urges a circumscription that detaches the self from everything artificial or nonessential to it. This concentration of self is achieved by an "art"of divestment rendered difficult because of a deficient will rather than insufficient knowledge: "Cet art n'est pas si difficile qu'on pourrait croire, ou du moins la difficulte n'est pas oi on la croit, il depend plus de la volont6 que des lumieres, il ne faut point un appareil d'etudes et de recherches pour y parvenir. Le jour nous eclaire, et le miroir est devant nous; mais pour le voir il fautjeter les yeux et le moyen de les y fixer est d'&carter les objects qui nous en detournent" (4:1113). The metaphor of the mirror, used on two contrasting occasions in the letters, proves instructive. For Rousseau as for Plato (Alcibiades1, 132b-133b), the mirror relation of the soul to itself creates the possibility of dialogue and self-knowledge. Unlike the miroir intellectuel (4:1092), a reliable epistemological capacity denied to me as a fallible creature of sense, a mirror for self-cognition through introspection already lies at my disposal. I possess, moreover, sufficient light for my soul to contemplate the divine part of itself connected to wisdom and knowledge but, Rousseau suggests, this does not mean that I automatically behold myself. Obstacles turn my gaze away so that I cannot attend to my inner self and discern my nature, my legitimate aspirations and duties, unless I remove these. How can I remove such obstacles and obtain an untrammelled vision? In Republic 518-19, Plato invokes an "artof conversion" acquired
33. For an assessment of the significance of the Morale sensitive to Rousseau's moral philosophy and its place in eighteenth-century thought, see my "Rousseau's Enlightenment Ethics: The Synthesis of Materialism and Morals," Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century5 (2000): 73-227.

248

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

through education to turn the soul around and make it behold the immaterial, eternal truth. There is no need to implant vision into the instrument of sight, says Socrates; it is already there, but turned in the wrong direction and not looking where it ought to. Although it is not feeble, encumbrances that stand in its way force the soul's vision to serve evil. All of this accords with Rousseau's view of corruption since, at the origins of human nature, the will inclines toward the cosmic design to which it belongs and which it loves spontaneously but, given the dual ontological condition we inherit as immortal creatures provisionally cloaked in flesh and blood, we sense competing urges for both moral e'lvation and abaissement.34 Yet, unlike the Platonic account, Rousseau's qualified materialism unambiguously accepts a correlation between moral virtues, belonging to the soul, and virtues of the body, implanted by habit and exercise.35 Rousseau's account adds to the Platonic view of the soul's inclination toward the lower, sensible world a further obstacle, a defective will promoted and sustained by the material self and its routine choices and habits. Thus, while Sophie's concentration of self consists in nothing more dramatic than solitary retirement ("recueillez-vous, cherchez la solitude, voilt d'abord tout le secret" [4:1113]), retreat proves difficult to accomplish. Impelled in our motives and behavior we by amour-propre, flee from ourselves and persist in perceiving everythe eyes of others. Disclosing to ourselves the truth thing through within depends on overcoming a long-standing resistance to an initiative for solitude, but this takes time ("ce n'est pas l'affaire d'un jour de savoir etre seule au milieu du monde ... apres une si longue habitude d'exister dans tout ce qui vous entourne" [4:1113]) and a certain expertise or art. Environmental factors and the invisible resistance posed by existing psychological and vital habits hinder the self's interior dialogue, but
34. The following conjecture in the Professiondefoi concerning the will-soul, whose imprisonment in the body constitutes a condition of morality, illustrates this Platonism: "Si l'esprit de l'homme ffit reste libre et pur, quel merite aurait-il d'aimer et suivre l'ordre qu'il verrait &tabli et qu'il n'aurait nul interet a troubler? Il serait heureux, il est vrai; mais il manquerait a son bonheur le degre le plus sublime, la gloire de la vertu et le bon temoignage de soi ... le soin de la conservation de ce corps excite l'Fme a rapporter tout a lui, et lui donne un interit contraire l'ordre general qu'elle est pourtant capable de voir et d'aimer; c'est alors que le bon usage de sa liberte devient a la fois le merite et la r&compense, et qu'elle se prepare un bonheur inalterable en combattant ses passions terrestres et se maintenant dans sa premiere volont&" (4:603). 35. From the very start, Emile identifies education with habituation: "L'Vducation n'est certainement qu'une habitude" (4:248). Later, the emergence of natural bodily habits paves the way for a strong ethical will and the child's reign of freedom ("le regne de sa liberte" [4:282]).

MarcoDi Palma o TheEthicsof theLettres morales

249

to understand this is to grasp how one might change one's motivations through instrumental reason. The dispositions of the Rousseauian will originate in and exist through an accustomed sensibility that provides incentives for the will: "La sensibilite est le principe de toute action. Un &tre, quoiqu'anime, qui ne sentirait rien, n'agirait point: car oui serait pour lui le motif d'agir?" (Rousseaujuge dejeanJacques[1776; published in 1780], 1:805). The tenor of sensibility, meanwhile, rests with the immediate sensations present to consciousness, either directly as perceptions or indirectly as memory and imagination, through cues provided by the environment. Modify the environment and one consequently begins to modify the tenor of sensibility and the dispositions of the will. Targeting sensibility through a discrimination of sensations represents the start of a progressive divestment undertaken in order to incline the will to turn inward. Sophie's spiritual recollection begins by reining in the senses: "Le recueillement de votre coeur doit commencer par celui de vos sens" (4:1113). The voice of conscience will not speak unless freed from the disruptions concomitant with a social environment hostile to the inner life, in a state such as one might obtain by shutting one's eyes and ears-as well as one's door-to society.36 Withdrawing to one's room, however, does little to contain the imagination and eradicate a symbolic presence that generates the very social pressures that render withdrawal from the crowd difficult. In towns, Rousseau tells us, one experiences solitude as an oppressive isolation, the human presence striking the imagination all the more for its absence. For this reason, he does not intend to shut Sophie away within the confines of four walls: "Je n'ai pas dessein de vous relkguer dans un cloitre et d'imposer 'i une femme du monde une vie d'anachorete" (4:1113). While Sophie's retirement may not be that of the anchorite, it does recall the anakhoresisof Stoicism, the spiritualized principle of retreat that consists in the general attitude and regular practice for remembering rules of action and behavior.37 This retreat forms part of a larger mood of askesis, both as a progressive consideration of self and as a dipouillementachieved through exercise or drill. In anakhoresis,a rural retreat is of some importance because nature helps put one in contact with oneself. For the Lettresmorales, this retreat brings expansive impressions of freedom, not personal sequestration from others, and a continual renewal of sensory stimuli
36. In the sixth Lettre,Rousseau writes: "La conscience est timide et craintive, elle cherche la solitude, le monde et le bruit l'pouvantent, les prejuges dont on la dit &tre l'ouvrage sont ses plus cruels ennemis, elle fuit ou se tait devant eux, leur voix bruyante etouffe la sienne et l'emp&che de se faire entendre" (4:1112). 37. Foucault, "Les Techniques de soi," 4:799.

250

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

which dissipate residual feelings of melancholy to foster a regathering (recueillement)of the dispersed strands of the self (4:1114). A well-arranged environment assists this task, but the residual resistance exercised by rival psychological and vital habits persists. In prescribing solitude, Rousseau further asks Sophie to overcome a sense of ennui (4:1113), the discomfort deriving from dispositions that do not welcome unaccustomed practices with which we attempt to oppose them. The Morale sensitive underlines that the mind's perceptual intake and the fortunes of l'Vconomie animale, the panoply of organic factors that determine dispositions, often hinder but may and ought to assist the "moral order" (1:409). Rousseau understands that a particular lifestyle increases the receptivity of the mind to inward values and truths, and therefore seeks both to modify the outward manifestations of personality and to address the material seat of dispositions associated with an inauspicious moral psychology. To this psychology belong the trappings of an elevated social status, particularly the superficial acts that sustain personal and intellectual vanity, and disordered organic habits at odds with the simple life lived according to nature that Sophie ought to adopt in their stead: "Couchez-vous de bonne heure, levez-vous matin, suivez ta peu pres la marche du soleil et de la nature; point de toilette, point de lecture, prenez des repas simples aux heures du peuple" (4:1117). This regimen or cura sui bolsters the solitary, contemplative life. If the first office of askesisconsists in modifying the direction of the will's gaze, the second demands that we train this gaze and accustom it in its new direction. Exercise (l'exercice[4:1113]) by short but frequent retreats implants in Sophie a capacity to disengage and withdraw into her self independently of the environment as a result of an immunity acquired through conditioning ("Eloignez les objets qui doivent vous distrairejusqu'a ce que leur presence ne vous distraise plus" [4:1113]). The sixth letter culminates with considerations tied to the habits at the fore of Sophie's spiritual progress. The scope of such habits extends beyond simply contracting a disposition for retreating into the self to an initiation that opens the way for what the eighteenth century calls bienfaisance.Conscience impels us outwardly to embrace I'artd tre heureux (4:1115), thereby accomplishing a crucial synthesis in which there is no happiness without virtue, no virtue without happiness. Individuals accustomed to their self-enclosed, alienating amour-propre experience the prospect of making themselves available to others with deep-seated unease. Merely willing that this be otherwise is of no use. The first version of Du contratsocial states that the will cannot will itself ("la volont . .. n'a point d'empire sur elle-mame" [3:315]). Yet the will can indirectly will itself thanks to a disposition which it acquires

MarcoDi Palma o TheEthicsof theLettres morales

251

over time. Through rehearsed acts leading to a fully implanted disposition, the ethical will forges a lever for itself to produce uniform patterns of activity, stable choices that routinely accomplish the good that the constant will recognizes and wishes to promote. A propitious environment alone, therefore, is not enough. To regularly discharge its intentions, the will must also have recourse to a material substrate which shares a vital interest in its enterprises. Though the will cannot will itself, and merely to want to be a useful member of the community is not enough, the will can and must solicit the efficient and beneficial influence of habit. At the outset, therefore, a categorical, self-imposed restriction proves valid until this yields a new moral spontaneity. For this reason, Rousseau encourages Sophie to suspend her normal routine for two to three days at monthly intervals during which she will decree to herself ("faites-vous une loi" [4:1114]) to live privately by herself. Sophie's duty to herself implicates wider social duties. Equally categorical is the need to put her leisure and privileges to practical use by attenuating existing social ills ("imposez-vous cette fonction si noble de faire qu'il existe quelques maux de moins" [4:1117]). Sophie will thus keep herself informed of the sick, the poor, and the downtrodden of the village, obliging herself to provide genuine relief and assistance ("faites-vous un devoir de porter partout avec une assistance reelle l'int&ret et les consolations qui la font valoir" [4:1118]) rather than simply reaching for her purse. All of this depends on overcoming the resistance of ennui and, one imagines, the fastidious, prudish distaste of afemme de qualitias she does her rounds in unpleasant dwellings among the striking, visible realities of poverty and the coarse, uncultured people whose simplicity is devoid of etiquette and elegance. But a tenacity for the good, Rousseau promises, eventually yields a moral disposition: "Songez que se plaire a bien faire est le prix d'avoir bien fait, et qu'on ne l'obtient pas avant de l'avoir merit6. Rien n'est plus aimable que la vertu mais elle ne se montre ainsi qu'a ceux qui la possedent; quand on la veut embrasser, semblable au Protee de la fable elle prend d'abord mille formes effrayantes et ne se montre enfin sous la sienne qu'd ceux qui n'ont point lch6 prise" (4:111718). Virtue stands in a fundamental relationship to the will or sensibility as a love or an aversion, the character of the desire indicating one's merit or demerit. A love for and possession of virtue come with exercise and effort, although, strictly speaking, self-willed imperatives and the habits that flow from them do not create virtue but merely introduce it. The ethical will can only facilitate a disposition for choice by continually lowering the threshold at which antagonistic forces militate against a reorientation of personality. Instruction and the creative

252

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

forces of exercise are necessary but not sufficient conditions for this disposition. While continuity and repetition render moral activity easier and more secure, habit (consuetudo) also entails an appropriation and interiorization by the subject of the force acting upon it. This, Aristotle tells us, presupposes a special receptivity on the part of that subject (NicomacheanEthics 1103a 19-23). In other words, Sophie must already possess a potential or aptitude for virtue prior to its possession. This capacity or predisposition-heralded at the start of the Lettres moraleswith the announcement of a felicitous nature (heureux naturel [4:1082]) -offers, in part, the grounding for Sophie's moral progress. In an important sense, a spontaneous inclination for the good equally precedes and follows the categorical attempts of the ethical will to bring it into the open through repetition. Willed efforts of perseverance would not otherwise prove efficacious. We can characterize this grounding with reference to two intrinsic aspects of the Rousseauian ethical self. The first, a self-intensifying circulus sanus that supports Rousseau's wider ethical and social vision for human redemption, exhibits itself in two ways: (1) a disposition for inwardness creates, and is created by, habitual self-reflection that reacquaints the self with its intermittent (but virtually constant) moral source in conscience; and (2) a disposition for virtuous action engenders, and is engendered by, repeated acts of virtue. This double reciprocity generates a characteristic Rousseauian dialectic that can be expressed as the relay between dispositions of the first kind (one's being) and those of the second (one's actions). In other words, the performance of good acts finds its reward in the untrammelled inward retreat that appreciates and enjoys them as private satisfactions. A desire to increase this happiness, meanwhile, impels one, in turn, to further the interests of benevolence so that one may earn what the Professiondefoi calls "la supreme jouissance ... dans le contentement de soi-meme" (4:587). The Lettresmoralesthereby revisit a theme familiar to Stoicism: do good and a good examination of conscience follows (compare Seneca, De ira 3.36). A further circularity, more fundamental than the first, also nestles in Rousseau's advice. While the inner life represents a given possibility shared by all, it is equally the construct of patient and meritorious effort attendant on, and encouraged by, self-knowledge. One must know how to cultivate this realm of experience. And yet, one cannot cultivate what one does not know. Rousseau is aware that Sophie's undertaking calls on her to possess, prior to moral illumination, those aptitudes and inclinations which she acquires only as a result of having them. He admits: "I1ne faut point commencer un trait&de morale par la fin ni donner pour premier pricepte la pratique de ce qu'on

MarcoDi Palma o TheEthicsof theLettres morales

253

veut enseigner" (4:1116). A second, more fundamental grounding for the moral life is given in the capacity for inward moral satisfactions, the only inalienable form of happiness available to unstable creatures like ourselves. Invoking a neo-Platonic view of the soul as essentially drawn to moral beauty, Rousseau identifies in our inalterable attraction to the good and its ensuing contentement intirieur (4:1115) the distinctive human excellence and a meta-ethical fact that anchors the moral life: "Dans quelque &tatqu'une Ame puisse &treil reste un sentiment de plaisir a bien faire qui ne s'efface jamais et qui sert de premiere prise a toutes les autres vertus, c'est par ce sentiment cultiv6 qu'on parvient I s'aimer et a se plaire avec soi" (4:1116). The virtues emanate from the cultivation of this irreducible and spontaneous proclivity for the good. One taps into this moral source by reawakening conscience ("reveiller ... le sentiment interieur" [4:1115]) and recalling to oneself the good performed in the past. Rousseau asks Sophie to nurture this memory and take continual stock of its contents because it encourages the reorientation that gradually accustoms her to retreating within. Thereafter, he equally invites her to add to the storehouse of deposited treasures in order to transform the practice of self-reflection into a regular disposition of the will: "Voila les moyens de travailler dans le monde a vous plaire dans la retraite en vous y menageant des souvenirs agr ables ... Parez-vous pour vous presenter a votre miroir, vous vous en regarderez plus volontiers" (4:1116). Dependent on the condition of retiring into self, the mutually inclusive demands of inward contentment and the altruism arising from the duties of the social life nourish one another. Experiential yield and acts of virtue become self-intensifying, each providing an incentive for the other. The attitude and practice of inwardness harmonizes two central imperatives that the crisis outlined in Emile rhetorically sets at loggerheads: personal happiness or the commitment to oneself and morality or the commitment to others. One's ultimate good and happiness, the Lettresmoralessuggest, coincides with, and is advanced by, the good and happiness of others. A fundamental unity binds self-concern with concern about the community. One must establish a proper relationship to oneself before one can establish ajust and ordered relationship to others. Only the self-possessed and fully autonomous individual, prompted by amour de soi and conscious of her genuine needs satisfied through cooperation rather than disruption, proves herself a useful member of the community. The letters involve more than the simple access to nature and conscience. A state of inwardness and self-knowledge does not in itself go far enough. The disciplined, inward gaze must turn back and reenter the world. Self-communion impels us outward to the

254

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

benefit of the community. Virtue-of being and actions-constantly rounds on itself, or, to use another metaphor, oscillates between self and other, existential concentration and expansion, solitude and participation. Although Rousseau proclaims the self-sufficiency of individuals in the sense that their personal happiness derives from their own efforts rather than public opinion, the Lettresmoralesalso insist that there exists no genuine self-fulfillment or morality outside the community and its system of mutual obligation and assistance. Legitimate self-interest and virtue are not merely reconciled: the possibility of one is the condition of the other. IV In addressing the problems of alienation and self-division, the Lettres moralestake their place alongside the masterpieces of reconstruction Rousseau produced between 1759 and 1762. To the spiritual dissonance provoked by modernity, Rousseau offers a set of diversified solutions whose coherence and unity utterly depend on instating the sociopolitical horizons to which the varying terms and conditions of his speculations are tied. The ensuing representative figures resulting from these speculations-fully integrated individuals who benefit themselves and the general good-assume the form of the citizen (Du contratsocial), the husband and wife, masters of the oikos (La Nouvelle Hiloise) and the sage (Emile). The letters propose an alternative path for those who cannot count on the support of the polis or a sheltered enclave of beautiful souls, while directly answering the question of how one should and can live in society-as-it-is without the guide of natural education. The good life they outline rests on bringing to the fore and subsequently cultivating those irreducibly moral instincts that turn us into genuinely fulfilled and productive members of the community. Much of this gets lost if we interpret the Lettresmoralesas a manual for self-realization outside the context of a social existence and the practices through which it unfolds. Nowhere does the work separate the re-education of the self from the attitude and practices that sustain its vocation for unity. Rousseau neither restricts himself to advising the correct setting for this unity, nor does he simply recommend how one might become what one should be without clarifying the ends such an imperative ought to serve. A concern with psychological states and intentions isolated from actions and their problematic consequences certainly captures something of Rousseau's self-representation in the late autobiographies. Yet it cannot be claimed of Rousseau, juge de Jean-Jacquesor the Riveries, still less of the Lettresmorales,that

MarcoDi Palma o TheEthicsof theLettres morales

255

dispositions persist independently of action or practices. Throughout his writings, Rousseau advances a long-standing ethical truth, highlighted early by Aristotle, reiterated by Aquinas and later reformulated by Hegel, that one cannot separate what an individual is from what he or she does. The project for La Morale sensitiveis designed to demonstrate this. One's being announces and is announced by the character of one's praxis. This is formally true of the moral letter which chooses to operate at the level of exemplary ithos. It is also true, in a more substantive sense, of the agent whose actions have the power to transform, and are transformed in turn, by the level of her self-understanding and the quality of her motives. It consequently becomes impossible to divorce what one should be from either how one should live or what one ought to do. To argue that the Lettresmorales merely indicate where to situate the self rather than prescribe how it ought to act, and that Rousseau merely identifies the sources of the healthy soul but forgets to provide it with principles or rules of conduct, is therefore an unacceptably hollow view of his aims in these writings. Underlying the reality and survival of such sources is the fact that they vitally depend on continuous deeds. Rather than simply transmitting a passion for rusticity, Rousseau strives to implant in his aristocratic correspondent a practical ethics that combines a customary, stable mode of being for the self with a highly visible, exemplary demeanor for others. The student of wisdom, in turn, becomes a model for others. Herein lies the central ethical significance of the Lettresmorales. This conclusion also allows us to challenge the eudaimonic verdict that Rousseau only values virtue for its "experiential yield" and not as an end in itself.38 Isolating the inner satisfaction that accompanies those who are morally pleased with themselves fails to capture what it means to cultivate the pleasurable feeling of doing good which, by definition, requires gravitating outward toward an active, practical relation to society. A love of virtue may create a disposition for virtue. To be sure, there exists a constant relay between the rewards of personal happiness experienced psychologically and the moral ends of living well which that experience affirms and encourages. The Lettresmorales depict an existential rhythm between spiritual recollection and participation with others who multiply our happiness, between the practice of good acts and the interior satisfactions of a good conscience that recalls and reviews them. So, too, rather than affirming some Nietzschean "will-to-power morality" wholly at odds with their author's intentions, as de Man claims,
38. Cooper (see n. 4 above), pp. 26-27.

256

MODERN

PHILOLOGY

the Lettresmoralesculminate in a rhetorical strategy characteristic of Rousseau's art of persuasion.39 If Rousseau concedes that the practice of virtue naturally flatters one's self-conceit (amour-propre) an idea by of superiority (4:1116), he does so in order to draw in readers highly sensitive to, and in need of, such flattery-those of noble rank like Mme d'Houdetot, for instance-by meeting them on their own terms with incentives they might find psychologically acceptable. Rousseau initially turns to an unexpected motivational source to assist individuals, whose better nature responds to the moral life but cannot sufficiently incline them to embrace it, in advance of an entirely new and genuinely ethical condition which, it is hoped, will eventually replace bad faith with superior motives intrinsic to a new way of perceiving and acting. The sixth and final letter culminates in a synthesis of self-interest and duty in which demands for personal fulfillment become fully compatible with the demands of the community. Bringing together his ethical and social theories, Rousseau conceives the individual's prosperity as synonymous with his or her ideal existence in society. This existence also expresses the rhythm of moral progress, a positive dialectic between retreat and participation, privacy and communion, the contemplative and active lives. Oscillating between such complementary poles reverses the kind of dichotomy lamented in Rousseau's Discourssur les richesses (1759; posthumously published in 1853) (5:469in which private goodness conflicts with public success. Reciproc81), ity of being and action, of practice in thought and thought in practice, produces a fully enlightened self capable of beneficial relations with others and leads to the integration of the individual within himself and within society. The implications of this synthesis for interpretations of Rousseau's thinking are wide-ranging. Within this framework, the need to choose between one's self-interest and one's duty, like the often alluded choice between innocent goodness and the perpetual internecine state of vertu-combat, no longer meaningful. The desire for happiis ness obtains its highest fulfillment precisely in the attitude and practice of morality. Only the actively moral person is truly happy. Virtue and happiness do not constitute radically separate orders of human pursuit. In offering a vision that grounds the moral and social ethic in the fullest realization of the resources of human nature shorn of all that obstructs its original goodness, and not in some denatured counterwill hostile to it, the Lettresmoralesdeny any discontinuity between the natural and ethical selves. On the contrary, the capture of virtue
39. De Man (see n. 3 above), p. 244.

Marco Di Palma o

The Ethics of the Lettres morales

257

through progressive habituation points to an important continuity. More than this, an innate inclination toward the good or a spontaneous appreciation of moral beauty, like the gift of conscience alive to remorse and the irreducible moral satisfactions even the most corrupt are capable of experiencing, represents the natural inheritance that founds the possibility of morality. Removing the supposed gulf between the natural and ethical self should lead us, in turn, to reassess the polarity between natural goodness and virtue set up in Emile.That conflict may, in fact, represent the rhetorical prelude to a synthesis of the kind already sketched in the Lettres morales.Rousseau rehearses the dilemma anew prior to overcoming it in more ample, systematic fashion. A fuller exploration of this question would, of course, require a more extended study. Proviindicate that, short of an impossible sionally at least, the Lettresmorales to nature or the improbable full civic life of the republican regression polity, a realistic and eminently practical third way exists beyond the stark alternatives set out in Emile. Neither men nor citizens, Sophie d'Houdetot and the future adult Emile will lead exemplary lives in the hope that others may imitate their betters.

You might also like