You are on page 1of 19

A Visual Introduction to the Musical Structure of Platos Symposium (For Reference Only, Not Publication)

May 15, 2008

Abstract The musical structure of Platos Symposium is illustrated with a series of pictures, diagrams, and graphs. Various, easily measurable kinds of evidence for the existence of a musical scale embedded in the dialogue are presented visually, so that patterns that stretch over the course of the dialogue can be surveyed at a glance.

Since a picture is worth a thousand words, the following series of pictures and diagrams illustrates the arguments of a companion essay,1 and is an expanded version of some slides prepared for a talk on its central ndings. The diagrams aim to convey the sometimes subtle evidence of the essay in a concise and readily accessible way. The essay laid out the textual and historical evidence for the surprising claim that Platos dialogues were organised around a musical scale, and that certain symbols and keywords were introduced into his narratives to mark out the regular intervals of that scale. Platos Symposium is particularly suitable for introducing and displaying these musical structures. The series of speeches, from Phaedrus to Alcibiades, breaks the text into discrete and objectively distinguished parts whose lengths reveal further evidence for the underlying musical scale. To say that Plato organised his dialogue around a twelve-part scale is, in the rst place, to say no more than that he made a twelve-part outline of this text and allocated the same number of lines to each part. The essay reviewed evidence that the lines in classical texts were counted in ways perhaps similar to the way we count words or pages. As before, this essay concentrates on exhibiting the evidence and avoids references to later theories of allegory and literary symbolism. It is important to make a clean case for the existence of the musical organisation before entering into debates about its ideology. It is clear, however, that the notion of forms beneath appearances is a thoroughly Platonic idea, and that the notion of an imperceptible musical and mathematical structure comports well with the kind of Pythagoreanism on display in the Timaeus.
Draft. Comments and criticism but not quotes are welcome. Prepared for blind review. I would like to thank .... I would like to acknowledge the support of ... This is an expanded version of illustrations prepared for a seminar at the University of ....

Figure 1: Pythagorass Slate in the Foreground of Raphaels School of Athens (left, detail) Bears a Diagram of the Pythagorean, Six-to-Twelve Musical Scale (right)

The Twelve-Note Scale

The historical background of a scale with twelve, regularly spaced notes was surveyed in the companion essay. The diagram above illustrates the Pythagorean association between the principle notes in a musical scale and the integers up to twelve. This was known to the Renaissance through works like Ficinos translation of Theons On the Mathematics Useful for Understanding Plato. [In this draft, some large gaps have been left at the bottom of pages.]

12 11 10 Octave, a 6:12 or 1:2 ratio 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1

End of the dialogue.

At the centre of the Symposium, the climax of Agathons speech: lyrical praise of Eros, a procession, loud approval; Socrates begins to speak.

Beginning of the dialogue.

Figure 2: The Symposium is Divided into Twelve Parts, Corresponding to a TwelveNote Musical Scale As the above gure shows, the scale divides the text of the dialogues into twelve equal parts, with Note 1 near the beginning of the text. The centre of the Symposium is emphatically marked. In a dialogue devoted to love, the conclusion of Agathons speech with its rousing rhetorical reworks in praise of Eros anks one side of the centre. Socrates, the philosophical hero of the dialogue, begins to speak at the centre.

6 Agathons speech lls the fth twelfth. 5 Aristophanes speech lls the fourth twelfth. 4 Eryximachus speech lls the third twelfth. 3 Pausanias speech lls the second twelfth. 2

Figure 3: Lengths of Speeches, Measured End to End The lengths of the speeches in the rst half of the Symposium strikingly show how the underlying musical scale has been used to organise the dialogue. The gure shows simple and objective measurements of the interval from the end of one speech to the end of the following speech. The speeches are surrounded by comments, repartee, or short cross-examinations, and this gure treats all such banter as part of the following speech. A later section explores the ne structure of this banter, and shows that it too has lengths determined by the underlying musical scale. The location of each note is marked by a passage with certain key, symbolic terms (see below). A speech, therefore, tends to stop just before or just after a note, depending upon whether it contains the marking passage or not. The speeches after the centre of the dialogue have lengths longer than one-twelfth (see below). The lengths of speeches can be easily and objectively measured, and therefore are the focus here. A careful reading of the dialogues will show that many of their features, from narrative and argument to key symbols and denitions, have been organised around the musical scale.

Harmonic and Disharmonic Notes

Measurements of length provide some evidence that Plato was counting lines when composing his dialogues, but do not in themselves show that the twelve-part structure is a musical scale. Another form of evidence shows a consistent connection between the stichometric organisation and a musical scale.

Figure 4: Two Strings Struck to Test Harmony Some pairs of notes sound better together than other pairs. Two notes an octave apart, for example, harmonise with each other. The Pythagoreans noticed that pairs of notes which sound well together are produced by pairs of strings whose lengths stand in simple, whole-number ratios like one-to-two or three-to-four. A pair of notes an octave apart, for example, are produced by strings whose lengths have a one-to-two ratio. The Pythagoreans went further and found ways to rank notes according to whether they were more or less harmonious when paired with some xed note. The series of notes on a twelve-note scale can all be separated into two classes as follows: Harmonious Notes: 2, 3, 4, 6, 8, 9 Disharmonious Notes: 1, 5, 7, 10, 11 Here, the twelfth note is used as a xed standard of comparison, and each note is played together with this standard. The successive pairs 1 and 12, 2 and 12, and so on are ranked according to whether they are more or less harmonious.

12 11 10 The top of Diotimas ladder at note: her vision of the Form of the One Diotima describes the Form of Beauty in itself at the note 9 8 7 Agathons peroration: praise of Eros, procession, loud approval, Socrates Aristophanes begins with praise of Eros: philanthropic, healing powers Pausaniass concluding praise of heavenly Eros: leads to virtue Pausanias: all gods must be praised, heavenly vs. common Eros 6 5 4 3 2 1

Harmonic Notes

Figure 5: Harmonious Passages at Harmonious Notes The twelve-note musical scale and the theory of relative harmony provide a key to the structure of Platos dialogues. Platos dialogues are full of value-judgements: philosophy is valued over other pursuits, the soul over the body, truth over falsity, dialectics over mere disputatiousness, and so on. As a general tendency, the locations of harmonious notes contain passages with positively valued concepts. This gure shows that important concepts or passages within the dialogue are carefully lodged at the locations of notes (at 1/12, 2/12, etc.), and that more harmonious concepts are located at more harmonious notes. The coloured bars show the locations of the harmonious notes: the longer the bar, the more harmonious the note. The top of Diotimas Ladder where the Form of the One is described is a philosophically key passage in the Symposium. It is located at a note: the harmonious ninth note. The harmonious notes are marked either by descriptions of the forms, perhaps the most highly valued concepts in Platonism, or by praise of the god of love.

12 11 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Hangovers from the previous night; Eryximachus condemns drunkenness. Aristophanes asks not to be mocked: Socrates fear and aporia before speaking. Diotimas elenchus of the young Socrates: Eros is not a god. Alcibiades shame and anguish after being rejected and dishonoured by Socrates Alcibiades calls Socrates an hubristees; compares him to an ugly, pipe-playing Satyr

Disharmonic Notes

Figure 6: Disharmonious Passages at Disharmonic Notes There is a dramatic contrast between the passages at the locations of the harmonic and disharmonic notes. Instead of the forms or praise of Eros, the disharmonic notes are marked by shame, insults, contradictions, mockery, and hangovers. As will be discussed below, the positive concepts at harmonic notes are part of passages in which language is used to promote social harmony: agreements, praise, etc. The negative concepts at disharmonic notes are, in contrast, associated with language which produces social disharmony. These instances of verbal or social harmony and disharmony mark the notes.

12

Alcibiades: rejected, war Alcibiades: Satyr, seduction


9 8

11 10

Diotima: Ladder, Form of One Diotima: Form of Beauty


7

Diotima: elenchus, myth of sex and seduction among gods


6

Socrates: the nature of eros Agathons peroration


5

Agathon: arty rhetoric


4 3 2

Aristophanes: myth of true love Eryximachus: erotic harmony Puasanias: love and pederasty
1

Phaedrus: myths, shame ethics Disharmonic Intervals

Harmonic Intervals

Figure 7: Regions near Harmonic Notes have Positive Themes, and Regions near Disharmonic Notes have Negative Themes The over-arching structures of Platos dialogues have been much debated. They sometimes seem meandering or disjointed. They do not follow common shapes like development, crisis, resolution, nor build slowly to a concluding climax. Remarkably, however, the sequence of topics in his dialogues does conform to this Pythagorean theory of relative harmony. Careful study of the dialogues shows that a region in the musical scale near a harmonic note is dominated by more positive concepts and, similarly, a region near a disharmonic note is more negative. More specically, the region stretching from a little before a note in the scale almost to the next note generally shares the earlier notes degree of harmony. (For example, Socrates elenchus of Agathon occurs as the disharmonic, seventh note is approached.) This is strikingly illustrated by the Symposium. The speech of the notorious Alcibiades lies in the most disharmonic region of the dialogue. Similarly, Agathons suspect speech, which Socrates criticised for lacking truth, lies in the next most disharmonic region. On the other hand, the philosophical peaks of Diotimas speech and the marvelous mirth of Aristophanes speech occupy harmonic regions.

12

Tartarus, River Styx Geography of the Underworld


9 8

11 10

Forms, soul is immortal Form of Beauty, hypotheses


7

Disharmony, soul is not a harmony


6

Socrates equanimity
5

Vices, evil, doubt


4 3 2

Proof of immortality, forms Recollection, forms Death as liberation, virtues


1

Suicide, body Disharmonic Intervals

Harmonic Intervals

Figure 8: In the Phaedo, Regions near Harmonic Notes have Positive Themes, and Regions near Disharmonic Notes have Negative Themes Study of the other dialogues conrms this correlation between positive or negative concepts and the series of regions between the notes. In the Phaedo, the regions after the eighth and ninth notes, as in the Symposium, describe the forms. On the other hand, the region around the last two disharmonic notes describes Hell and the lthy River Styx. The argument that the soul is not a harmony, which explicitly mentions disharmony, follows the disharmonic seventh note. Similarly, in the Symposium, Eryximachus discussion of erotic harmony followed a harmonic note. This pattern is remarkably consistent across the dialogues. Although there may be some uncertainty about the precise locations of the notes, studying the harmonic character of these longer passages in the regions between notes does not depend upon any precise measurement of locations within the text.

12 11 10 9 8

12 11 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1

12 11 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1

0.618

7 6 5 4 3 2 1

Rep.

Symp.

Parm.

Figure 9: Passages Alluding to the Golden Mean One way of conrming the relevance of the Pythagorean theory of harmony is to show that other Pythagorean concepts appear in the Symposium. The Golden Mean, a mathematically signicant number approximately equal to 0.618, has been a theme in later Pythagoreanism as well as among cranks and numerologists up to the present day. Several scholars have interpreted the Divided Line passage in the Republic as an allusion to the Golden Mean. Remarkably, this passages begins 61.7% of the way through that dialogue. Even more remarkably, the other dialogues also seem to allude to the Golden Mean at the same point. In the Symposium, Socrates asserts that neither the ignorant nor the wise are philosophers, since both are perhaps content with their condition. In contrast, he says at 61.6% of the way through the text that the philosopher is at the mean or in the middle between ignorance and wisdom. This associates the notion of a philosophical or ethical mean with the mathematical notion of a mean, just as explicitly occurs in Aristotle. At the parallel location in the Parmenides, a passage echoes Euclids geometric denition of the Golden Mean. This is quite strong evidence for the underlying musical scale. On the one hand, a number of scholars have argued for the possible or probable link between the Divided Line and the Golden Mean. It is surprising to nd the passage in the Republic near 61.7%. On the other hand, the passages at similar locations in other dialogues consistently refer to mathematical or ethical means.

10

Figure 10: A Classical Symposium (from the Tomb of the Diver, Paestum, c. 470 B.C.E.)

The Quarternote Structure

This section introduces a further, musical concept and shows how it gives the speeches a more ne-grained structure. One theme in the debates over musical theory in Platos time and long afterwards was the question of whether there were quarternotes or smaller intervals between the usual notes of a musical scale.2 The concept of a quarternote was discussed by Plato, Aristotle, Aristoxenus, and others, and was sometimes understood to be the smallest unit by which musical scales should be measured. The intervals between the twelve whole notes in the Symposium are further organised around a structure of quarternotes. That is, shifts between speakers, major turns in arguments, and central concepts are often lodged one, two, or three fourths of the way between the whole notes. The internal organisation of the speeches, both shorter and longer, in this dialogue reveals this further, ne-grained structure.

11

1q Note 9 3q 2q 1q Note 8 3q 2q 1q Note 6 3q 2q 1q Note 5 Agathons Speech, Length: 3/4 Note 7 3q 2q 1q Note 6 Banter, Length: 1/4 Socrates Speech, Length: 3

Banter, Length: 1/4

Figure 11: Some Speeches Stop and Start at Quarter-Intervals This gure shows two sorts of simple evidence for the role of quarternotes. The lengths of Agathons speech is a multiple of the quarter-interval, and the lengths of the banter before the two speeches extend through one-quarter interval. This suggests that the distance of one-quarter of the length between successive whole notes plays a role in the organisation of the Symposium. Moreover, these speeches as well as the banter and repartee before them stop and start at quarternotes. Thus both the lengths and the locations are evidence for the role of quarternotes.

12

Note 9

3q ... the Pythagoreans ... [measure] audible concords and sounds one against each other ... [Others] talk of groups of quarter-tones ... [each is] a note in between, giving the smallest possible interval, which ought to be taken as the unit of measurement. (Cornfords translation: 530d8 531a7)

Republic

2q

1q

Note 8

Note 5

3q

Symposium

2q

Aristophanes makes Zeus say: And if they still appear licentious and will not behave quietly, then I will cut them in two all over again [i.e., into quarters], so that they will go about hopping on one leg [instead of four]. (190d4-6)

1q

Note 4

Figure 12: Passages Alluding to Quarters at the Locations of Quarternotes The gure above gives two examples of a kind of punning reference in Platos dialogues to the musical structure. The Republic refers to quarternotes at the location of a quarternote on its embedded scale.3 The Symposium refers to cutting into quarters at the location a quarternote. This limited evidence cannot in itself be convincing, but such puns are common in the dialogues. For example, the dialogues sometimes refer to three near the third note, or four near the fourth note, and so on. The passages in the gure show at least that Plato discussed smaller intervals between the main notes in a musical scale and add another kind of evidence, however limited here, for the role of quarternotes. Their brevity makes puns hard to interpret in rigourous ways. The scholarship on 13

puns in classical or later literatures generally depends upon an argument from coherence. That is, by examining many examples and drawing on explicit discussions of punning, etymology, and allegory in related writings, secure interpretation of puns in individual cases can be reached. During the last generation, a substantial literature on puns in Homer, Aristophanes, Ovid, and Virgil has claried the various motivations for punning in classical literature.4 Sedley, in particular has argued that Platos Cratylus should be read as evidence for a serious interest on Platos part in etymological puns. The following gure introduces yet another kind of evidence for quarternotes and requires some introduction. Plato uses a subtle scheme for marking the locations of musical notes at regular whole and quarter intervals in the Symposium. The theory of his marking scheme is given in the Symposium itself. Examining rst the theory and then the passages marking the opening quarternotes in the dialogue will reveal much about Platos symbolic techniques. The Symposium contains, in Eryximachus speech, an explicit theory of the nature of music (187a1 ff.). It involves two combinations of opposites: of fast and slow, and of high and low. We might call these tempo and pitch, but for Plato the rst is rhythm and the second is harmony or consonance (symph nia). Plato succinctly o summarised this view of music in the Laws: ... rhythm is the name for the order of the motion and harmony is the name for the order of the sound. (664e8-a2) An uptempo or fast rhythm, for example, is one in which the mixture of fast and slow is dominated by fast. Both rhythm and harmony are thus types of blending or agreement between opposites. Music establishes such agreements, according to Eryximachus, by implanting eros and homonoia, or love and like-mindedness. Eros is therefore a mediating force which reconciles disagreeing elements, and music is a science: the erotics of rhythm and harmony, or of motion and sound.5 This theory of music is the key to the symbolism that Plato uses to mark the notes in the Symposium.6 Careful examination shows that there is a denite similarity between passages lodged at the locations of the notes through the musical scale. The gure summarises the rst four such passages in the dialogue, where the pattern is rather heavy-handedly established.

14

3q

Motion: Socrates starts again, arrives at Agathons (175c4). Wise/Unwise: Socrates wisdom requested by dramatist Agathon (c8). Invite/Agree/Harmony: Agathon asks, Socrates agrees to sit together (d3). Motion Stops: Socrates sits, motion ceases again (d3).

2q

Motion: jokes about going to Agathons, departure (174c7, d4). Wise/Unwise: wise/phaulos, Socrates and Aristodemus (c7,d2). Invite/Agree/Harmony: invitation, agree to attend the dinner (d3). Motion Stops: Socrates stops on the road (d5-6).

1q

Motion: walking along the road to the city (173b9). Wise/Unwise: philosophy vs. worldly pursuits (c3-5 .). Invite/Agree/Harmony: agrees to recount the speeches (c2). Motion Stops: interlocutor is really doing nothing (d1).

Motion: Apollodorus was going to the city (172a2). Wise/Unwise: young philosopher, ignorant inquirer. (173c2-5, b8-c2) Invite/Agree/Harmony: he is asked to stop and does (a4). Motion Stops: Apollodorus stops (a5).

Figure 13: Similar Passages Mark the First Four Quarternotes: Each Contains the Elements of Music, Motion and Harmony These four passages share a consistent set of features. At each note, there are words indicating some sort of physical motion like walking. Each passage also concludes with the cessation of motion. Moreover, there is at each note some sort of agreement either assent to a request or acceptance of an invitation between a student of philosophy and someone else. Like a musician who rather emphatically begins with ONE, two, three, four, the Symposium marks the interval between its initial quarternotes with a rhythmically repeated pattern of passages.7 In short, there is a kind of rhythm (motion) and a kind of harmony (agreement) at the location of each note. The concepts, or perhaps the forms, of music mark the locations of the notes. A Platonist might conclude that, since the forms are the reality beneath appearances, there is real music at each note.

15

Figure 14: A Tabulation of the Occurrence of Music-Related Words in the Republic, Showing the Second and Third Musical Notes and Intervening Quarternotes This gure shows the results a novel investigation which, once understood, provides powerful evidence for the existence of quarternote structure in the Republic. In that dialogue, the locations of the whole notes are marked by clusters of musical and music-related words (like lyre, chord, string, tone, harmony, noise, etc.). Careful study of the passages at the whole notes produced a list of these words. In an effort to show that these clusters occurred only at the locations of the whole notes, I proceeded mechanically through the entire dialogue recording and tabulating the locations of these key, musical terms on my list. This led to a table giving the number of occurrences of these words in each Stephanus page. I was surprised to see smaller clusters of the key terms at three regular intervals between each pair of successive whole notes. This was the rst evidence for the existence of the quarternotes. This chart shows the structure between the second and third whole notes. There is a larger number of musical terms spread over a larger number of Stephanus pages at the whole notes, and smaller peaks at the quarternotes, but the histogram beautifully shows the quarternote structure. Tabulating the occurrences of a random list of words in the Republic would not have produced a regular structure. Thus my list of key terms and the graph reinforce each other, and constitute a strong, visual form of evidence for the presence of quarternotes.

16

Summary of the Evidence

The preceding illustrations aimed to assemble a range of independent, yet mutually reinforcing lines of evidence for the musical scale in the Symposium. Simple evidence for the twelve-note scale: four speeches early in the Symposium are each about one-twelfth long these four speeches each begin and end near a whole note Socrates speech is three-twelfths of the entire text highlights of Diotimas speech, the form of Beauty and the form of the One, occur at successive notes, and thus are separated by one-twelfth the rhetorical climax of the Symposium is located at its centre Evidence from the Pythagorean theory of relative harmony: harmonious concepts are lodged at harmonious notes, e.g., the top of Diotimas ladder is reached at the ninth note disharmonious concepts are lodged at disharmonious notes, e.g., the River Styx at the eleventh note of the Phaedo regions after harmonious notes are lled by speeches about the forms or with praise of Eros regions after disharmonious notes are lled by speeches about shame, insults, or arty rhetoric a similar pattern of regions occurs in the Phaedo (and other dialogues), showing that this gives the general structure of Platos dialogues the musical structure was tied to another Pythagorean concept, the Golden Mean Evidence for quarternotes between the twelve whole notes: the lengths of Agathons speech and of some banter are multiples of the quarterinterval the speeches of Agathon and Socrates each begin at a quarternote an explicit discussion in the Republic of quarternotes is lodged at the location of a quarternote a reference to quartering at the location of a quarternote in the Symposium the four passages marking the Symposiums rst four quarternotes are similar and contain references to motion and agreement, i.e., to the elements of music a tabulation of the music-related terms in the Republic clearly shows a regular series of peaks at the locations of whole and quarternotes.

17

Appendix: Locations of the Musical Notes

As discussed in the companion essay, the measured locations of the musical notes on the Symposiums musical scale are surprisingly accurate, despite the changes the text may have undergone during its transmission. The Stephanus pages have signicantly variable lengths but, in the Symposium and not generally in other dialogues, the interval between quarternotes is coincidentally about one Stephanus page. Note 0: Note 1: Note 2: Note 3: Note 4: Note 5: Note 6: Note 7: Note 8: Note 9: Note 10: Note 11: Note 12: 172a1, 176c5, 180e3, 185b6, 189d5, 193d8, 198a8, 202c7, 206e1, 211b4, 215c2, 219d6, 223d12 1q: 1q: 1q: 1q: 1q: 1q: 1q: 1q: 1q: 1q: 1q: 1q: 173c3, 177c6, 182a3, 186c2, 190d6, 194e5, 199b4, 203c7, 207e5, 212b8, 216c5, 220d6, 2q: 2q: 2q: 2q: 2q: 2q: 2q: 2q: 2q: 2q: 2q: 2q: 174c6, 178d2, 183a7, 187c8, 191d7, 195e8, 200b11, 204d4, 209a5, 213c3, 217c7, 221d8, 3q: 3q: 3q: 3q: 3q: 3q: 3q: 3q: 3q: 3q: 3q: 3q: 175c5, 179d6, 184b1, 188d1, 192e1, 197a3, 201c4, 205d9, 210b1, 214c1, 218d1, 222e7,

18

Notes
1. Platos Forms, Pythagorean Mathematics, and Stichometry is under review. 2. The difference between a musical fth and a third gave the basic interval of a tone (between note 8 and 9). A quarternote would be one-fourth of this distance. The concept and terminology for these smaller notes varied signicantly during antiquity. See West, Barker, Huffman, etc. 3. This passage has been much debated. I have used Cornfords translation here. Adams commentary discusses this passage. 4. See the companion essay for references. 5. This passage (187c4-8) lies at the second quarternote after note 3. 6. Each of Platos dialogues uses a different general scheme to mark its notes, but the scheme is usually explicitly (and obliquely) discussed in the dialogue. That is, each dialogue gives the theory needed for the interpretation of its symbolic scheme. 7. From the rst whole note until the advent of Alcibiades, the musical notes are marked with various species of homologia but not with explicit motion (Alcibiades appropriately reintroduces motion and disturbance). The narrator, however, is walking to town while reciting the speeches. Thus, once the motion or tempo is established in the opening quarternotes, it perhaps recedes into the background.

19

You might also like