You are on page 1of 30

Financial Capital and the Decline of Democracy

Bob Jessop Lancaster University

Financial Capital and the Decline of Democracy Bob Jessop

This paper revisits the argument, advanced by advocates and critics of capitalism alike, if somewhat hyperbolically, that liberal democracy is the best possible political shell for capitalism. This is contestable theoretically, historically and comparatively. Indeed, the relationship between capitalism and democracy is deeply contradictory and historically contingent. The connection is further challenged by recent trends in national politics such as authoritarian populism, authoritarian statism, and post democracy. More doubts are raised by growing gaps between world market integration, the continued importance of national territorial states, and the forms of global governance. These are producing an increasing democratic deficit, especially regarding control over the international, transnational, and supranational economic and extra-economic aspects of the emergent world market, and are reflected in the resort to technocratic and other forms of unelected, non-accountable executive powers linked to international regimes and obscure parallel power networks. These trends are decades-old but have been strengthened by the expansion of a financedominated accumulation that is tied to new forms of political capitalism. After reviewing some of these general issues, I turn to financialization as another debilitating factor, largely overlooked in neo-classical but not libertarian economics, in the decline of democratic governance.

WHICH CAPITALISM, WHICH DEMOCRACY?

Capitalism is usually defined as a system of commodity production involving private ownership and control of the means of production plus formally free labour power. On this basis, mainstream economics models the economy as a universal, harmonious, and self-equilibrating system. Likewise, for political theorists,

maintaining free markets is an important source of legitimacy in capitalist societies compared to the despotism in pre-capitalist class societies and the party dictatorships of state socialism (e.g., Friedman 1962). But this account of its democratic virtues highlights and idealizes one specific account of capitalism: 1

rationally organized capitalist production and trade oriented to free markets. This comprises only one of six modes of orientation to profit that Max Weber identified. The other five are: (1) traditional commercial capitalism, based on traditional types of trade or money deals; (2) rational trade and speculation in money and credit instruments; (3) predatory profit from political activities, including from financing of wars, revolutions, or party leaders; (4) profits from continuous business activity based on force or a monopoly granted by political authority; and (5) profit from unusual transactions with political bodies (Weber 1978: 164-166). An analysis that looks at these other modes of securing profit might reach different conclusions about the formal correspondence between capitalism and democracy. Indeed, the more that capital accumulation rests on politically oriented capitalism (types 3-5), the harder it is to maintain more than a faade of democracy. I explore this thesis below for finance-dominated accumulation, which is heavily inflected by forms of political capitalism (see also Jessop 2013b).

Democracy is also a problematic term. One definition, inspired by Joseph Schumpeter, treats it as an intermittent, quasi-plebiscitary competition between circulating political elites for the votes of individual citizens (Schumpeter 1943; cf. Weber 1994). Defined in this minimalist, elitist manner, democracy survives nationally and sub-nationally in most advanced capitalist states. But if we turn from competitive elections to the institutional and socio-cultural conditions necessary to democratic accountability, then the past and present of effective democratic participation in policy- and decision-making appear in less favourable light. Moreover, as the world market gets more integrated and the space of flows (including finance) grows more important relative to territorially-delimited economic activities, there are mounting challenges to the territorial (and temporal) sovereignty of states, whether or not these are democratic in substance or form.

THE BEST POSSIBLE POLITICAL SHELL?

Various theoretical traditions have attempted to establish the mutual implication and reinforcement of capitalism (defined for this purpose as trade in free markets and rationally organized capitalist production) and democracy (understood as liberal representative democracy). Despite contrasting political and ideological positions, a
2

common theme is that the separation of the economic and political spheres limits the concentration of power to the mutual benefit of economic and political agents. Economic power can be used to prevent the abuse of political power; political power can be used to counteract market failures. Where this separation exists, according to bourgeois apologists, competitive capitalism can expand in a crisis-free manner through the smooth operation of market forces and, in addition, dispersed economic power will help to block the abuse of political power. Indeed, Milton Friedman, among others, argued that a market economy combined with authoritarian rule (e.g., fascism, Nazism, military dictatorship) is preferable to a planned economy under totalitarian rule (i.e., communism). He reasoned that, while the former contains the seeds of democratization, the latter always suppresses democratic pressures, economically and politically (Friedman 1962: 10-11). Or, as the conservative historian, Niall Ferguson, put it, capitalism and democracy are the double helix of modern societies (2000: 10). Radical political economists dispute that liberal democracy is the co-guarantor (with competitive capitalism) of individual freedom and regard it, instead, as the co-guarantor of capitalist rule. Thus the Canadian ethical socialist, Crawford B. MacPherson, argued:

the more nearly the society approximates Friedman's ideal of a competitive capitalist market society, where the state establishes and enforces the individual right of appropriation and the rules of the market but does not interfere in the operation of the market, the more completely is political power being used to reinforce economic power (MacPherson 1973: 148-9).

Frankfurt critical theorists, structural Marxists, and some radical political scientists add that, as long as the state does not engage in production but draws its revenues from the private sector through taxation and/or public debt, it will be indirectly subordinate to the logic of profit-oriented, market-mediated accumulation and open to pressures from one or another fraction of capital. Neo-liberal pressures to reduce direct taxation (see below) and the role of credit-rating agencies in relation to sovereign debt reinforce these pressures. The vulnerability of radical governments to a strike of capital is the material basis to Friedmans claim that diffuse economic power restricts and limits totalitarian (or socialist) political rule. This threat increases the chances that the national interest will be defined to favour capital.
3

Such criticisms aside, capitalism is not always linked to political democracy. Friedman noted that it can co-exist with authoritarian rule; and radical political theorists have distinguished between 'normal' (democratic) capitalist states and 'exceptional' political regimes that abolish free elections in favour of executive authority. Such contingencies are summarized neatly in Stanley Moores aphorism that, 'when exploitation takes the form of exchange, dictatorship tends to take the form of democracy' (1957: 85, italics added). In short, the relation is not guaranteed.

This indicates a need to explore the historical trajectory of the modern state and its articulation to capitalist development. Several theorists have proposed that different stages in capitalist development have different implications for this relation. First, during the transition to capitalism, state action is needed to create the conditions for economic exchange among 'equals'. An absolutist state pursuing mercantilist policies is appropriate. Second, once competitive capitalism has been consolidated, a liberal state form gives the fullest freedom to individual capitals compatible with securing the general conditions for accumulation. It combines general laissez-faire with specific interventions to redress the effects of unfettered competition (e.g., factory legislation). Although the liberal state need not be democratic, it is based on the rule of law and often coupled with parliamentarism. This reinforces the illusion of equality among citizens to match the illusion of equality between buyers and sellers of labour-power. Even so, as voters elect large numbers of social democratic and communist deputies, parliament is less able to arbitrate among competing capitalist interests and this task is therefore transferred to the executive. Third, as capitals crisis-tendencies intensify, the state is pressured to intervene to renew accumulation, often at the cost of subaltern classes. This leads to a strong state and there are even fewer opportunities for popular participation in policy formation (cf. Holloway and Picciotto 1977; Mandel 1972; Gerstenberger 2011).

At most, this simplistic three-stage model holds for metropolitan societies that underwent early industrialization and had an extended period of competitive capitalism. Britain, Holland, Belgium, and the United States, for example, could have competitive capitalism, a strong bourgeoisie, and a liberal state. However, as Gerschenkron (1962) and others note, banks and the state had bigger roles in
4

second-wave industrialization: competitive capitalism was therefore weaker, even where it existed, and political capitalism had a bigger role. In such cases, the phases of mercantilism (with or without absolutism) and interventionism tend to merge and liberal states are absent or ineffective. Examples include Bonapartism and Bismarckism and Tsarist autocracy. Similar arguments apply to developmental states (which were often anti-democratic national security states) and their successors in third-wave industrialization and to many post-socialist transition states (notably those that are resource-rich). As developmental states sought to catch-up with advanced economies through export-led growth, there were strong incentives for low-waged, labour-repressive primitive accumulation. The experience of imperialism also indicates the limits to any simple equation of capitalism and democracy and this is reflected in the legacies of post-colonial states in Africa, Asia and Latin American states. In short, any study of the relations between capitalism and political regimes must consider variant forms and stages of capitalism and the insertion of societies into the world market and the international division of labour.

The commodity fetishism of free markets and the political fetishism of a constitutional state cannot ensure a stable fit between free markets and liberal democracy. Something more is required. A crucial material basis for the reproduction of liberal democracy is the institutional separation between the economic and political in capitalist societies and its reflection in a clear demarcation between economic and political class struggle. From capitals viewpoint, the ideal position is one where economic class struggle is confined within the limits of the market relation and political class struggle occurs within those of bourgeois parliamentarism. Thus, whereas trade union struggles would focus on wages and conditions, political struggles would seek social reforms by mobilizing public opinion and seeking parliamentary majorities. Trade union power would be confined to industrial disputes rather than used to support parliamentary action; and state power would be limited to the 'public' sphere and not used to interfere in private disputes or constrain the rights of private property, including capitals rights to manage their enterprises and freely allocate their capital. Insofar as this institutional separation and its impact on class struggle are reproduced, subaltern classes find it hard to mobilize their full potential for collective action, whether defensively or offensively. Moreover, where capitalism rests on equal exchange (trade in free markets and rationally-organized production),
5

the bourgeoisie need not control the state directly provided that it maintains the juridical, monetary, and other extra-economic conditions for accumulation.

Thus the adequacy of the bourgeois democratic republic depends on the overall economic, political and ideological situation and its implications for the unstable equilibrium of compromise necessary to the democratic constitution. Thus, commenting on the French constitution in 1850, Karl Marx noted a comprehensive contradiction: the classes whose social slavery the constitution is to perpetuate proletariat, peasantry, petty bourgeoisie it puts in possession of political power through universal suffrage. And from the class whose old social power it sanctions, the bourgeoisie, it withdraws the political guarantees of this power. From the first group it demands that they should not go forward from political to social emancipation; from the others that they should not go back from social to political restoration (Marx 1978: 77, italics added).

This comprehensive contradiction means that the form of political regimes and content of state policies depend on the dynamic of political struggles rather than immediate economic circumstances. It follows that political analysis must consider state forms, political regimes, political discourses, and the changing balance of political forces as well as basic economic relations, economic crises, and the economic conjuncture.

Any resolution of this contradiction is partial, provisional, and temporary because it depends on the changing balance of political forces. A key challenge, as Andrew Gamble (1973) observes, is to create one or more political parties that can reconcile the politics of support and politics of power. The former involves the democratic electoral constraints entailed in a 'one-person-one-vote-one-value' system in which success depends on securing a majority or large plurality of votes. Conversely, the politics of power denotes the constraints on the exercise of state power in conditions where power is not allotted equally to each and every citizen but depends on the changing economic, political, and ideological conjuncture. Thus the politics of support must be pursued within the constraints imposed by the politics of power.
6

Politicians and parties that exceed these constraints will be electorally unpopular (because their programmes seem sectional, extreme, or unrealistic) or, if elected, will be forced to make U-turns and/or to embrace the prevailing orthodoxies. In brief, unless political movements accept the rules of the electoral game and the realities of political power, they face electoral impotence or, if elected, the need for U-turns. Natural governing parties are those that win majorities (or pluralities) with electoral programmes that are politically realistic. Different parties with different social bases may achieve this status at different times. If they exist, liberal democratic politics is possible. Where these conditions are not met, we find a representational crisis of the political system and a crisis of hegemony.

These constraints also affect the dominant classes and class fractions. Democracy offers different fractions the chance to bargain, compromise, and adjust their interests in ways that promote their long-term interests. Nicos Poulantzas elaborated some of these mechanisms (1973, 1978). He argued that the institutional matrix of the state in advanced capitalist democracies facilitates the organization of the hegemony of the dominant power bloc and the disorganization of subaltern classes. This dual task is facilitated by the architecture of the state: individual citizenship fragments and atomizes the members of civil society (the 'isolation effect'); and the legally sovereign state is expected and empowered to define and promote the 'national interest' and 'public good' on behalf of these citizens (the 'unification effect'). Moreover, since citizenship is not based on class location but on the formal equality of all members of society, their common interests are expected to cut across class antagonisms. This encourages aspiring governing parties to articulate and aggregate the interests of the dominated classes and connect them to those of dominant classes. In addition, electoral competition and parliamentary politics permits changes in the balance of power without serious threat to the stability of the state system as a whole. The circulation of power among natural governing parties thereby reinforces the belief in a neutral state that can reconcile class conflicts.

In addition, where surplus-labour is appropriated through market forces rather than coercion, capital can offer political concessions (such as welfare state benefits) without threatening accumulation. In these conditions, universal suffrage, competing parties, the separation of powers, parliamentary government all contribute to the
7

flexibility of a political system which means that power can be continually readjusted to secure social cohesion. And, since the cohesion thereby secured is that of a class-divided society, this also maintains class domination. Indeed, working class struggles can sometimes force policies on capital that advance its long-term interests. Two examples are nineteenth-century factory legislation and the Cold War class compromise that facilitated a virtuous circle of mass production and mass consumption during the post-war Atlantic Fordist boom. There are limits to such policies, of course, seen in the developing fiscal crisis of the state and its repercussions on legitimacy.

Another important feature of the modern state is the formal separation between representation and administration as reflected in the partisan neutrality of officials compared to the partisanship of elected representatives. Bureaucratic domination separates citizens from control over the means of administration. This holds as much for economic intervention and welfare administration as for the means of coercion and repression. It leads to the individuation and potential mutual isolation of citizens as clients or consumers of distinct, multi-scalar public services. This fragments the agents and targets of political struggle and transforms the people into a series of client groups competing for state resources. The separation of powers has similar effects, especially when the administration is protected by official secrecy and state control over information flows. As neo-liberalism privatizes state services and or delegates their provision to public-private partnerships, there is even less public accountability, even if only in an irregular plebiscitary form.

FROM PARLIAMENTARY DEMOCRACY TO AUTHORITARIAN STATISM During periods of political crisis, the comprehensive contradiction of liberal democracy prompts open struggles between subaltern and dominant classes over the nature and ends of government. Three recurrent responses to this situation are: (1) reorganize the system of representation (especially its electoral aspects) to weaken the prospects of radical, popular-democratic or socialist governments; (2) promote governments of national unity based on cooperation among the natural governing parties and the co-option or suspension of other parties; and (3) limit the powers of parliament and elected officials by reinforcing the independence of key
8

administrative apparatuses (e.g., central banks, the security apparatus) and/or declaring states of economic or political emergency. All three responses have been seen since the crisis of Atlantic Fordism became clear in the mid-1970s and have been reinforced during the North Atlantic Financial Crisis (NAFC). Before reviewing recent events, however, I summarize two earlier accounts of these (and related) tendencies in metropolitan capitalism and refer to a subsequent account of the rise of post-democracy in the metropolitan heartlands.

State Monopoly Capitalism

Theories of state monopoly capitalism (SMC) emerged during the Great War to describe the war socialism adopted by the belligerent capitalist states. The y were elaborated in response to trends during the Great Depression, the Second World War, and the rise of Atlantic Fordism and its subsequent crisis. They focus on the economic policies and overall organization of the state as an apparatus of political class domination. They highlight ten trends: (1) the political commanding heights are occupied by persons with family, economic, or ideological ties to monopoly capital; (2) governing parties become key instruments of ideological control over the population through monopoly financing of parties, party conferences, and election campaigns and the centralization and bureaucratization of party organization; (3) monopolies extend their control over the means of mental production (e.g., education, advertising, mass media) with a view to limiting and channelling popular pressures for state intervention; (4) associations, lobbies, and individual firms gain influence in all fields of domestic and foreign policy, thanks to their direct contacts with ministries and politicians and the expansion of state-monopoly complexes in many areas, such as the military-industrial complex, energy supplies, big pharma, infrastructure, and agriculture; and (5) a financial oligarchy tends to dominate here because it has the central role inside the network of cross-cutting monopoly interests and/or its organizing role in the key peak organizations.

In addition, the state is reorganized. Thus: (6) parliament loses power to the political executive and to an expanding array of functionally-oriented ministries, special tribunals, soft law, quasi-state organs, state-sponsored economic institutions, etc.; (7) the police, paramilitary, and military apparatuses are reinforced and, at the same
9

time, (8) the states own ideological functions are also strengthened; (9) there are complementary processes of deconcentration und decentralization of power at the micro-economic and/or local political levels, which helps capital to manage the smallest sites of valorization and to penetrate all areas of social life; and (10) these changes are accompanied by massive growth in international state monopoly apparatuses on the political and economic levels and these lie beyond the control of national governments.

Although these theories often equate SMC with state planning, this relation does not always hold. For example, Heinz Jung distinguished a statist variant of SMC, based on extensive state economic intervention and the social-reformist integration of subordinate classes, and a 'private' variant, which pursued market-oriented economic management and relied on a strong state with a more repressive integration of the dominated classes. He argued that this second [eventually neoliberal] form was becoming more important, especially in Germany (Jung 1979).

Another scholar, Philippe Herzog, noted that these trends are shaped by the balance among all classes, fractions, and strata (not just monopolies) and that the search for policy coherence means that state actions rarely meet directly all the demands of specific interests but require (uneven) sacrifices on all sides. Indeed, if the state tried to resolve problems on behalf of just one fraction, it would aggravate them for capital as a whole and thus for all fractions. Conversely, even if it tried to realize the collective interests of capital, the state still needs support from some capitals to execute its policies and may favour these more thereby disturbing the prevailing equilibrium of compromise among these fractions and their allies (Herzog 1971).

Authoritarian Statism

In the 1970s, Poulantzas gave a similar account of democratic decline, describing the new normal form of capitalist state as authoritarian statism. Thus, continuing the earlier metaphor, this is now the best possible political shell for capital. Its basic tendency is intensified state control over every sphere of socio-economic life combined with radical decline of the institutions of political democracy and with draconian and multiform curtailment of so-called formal liberties (1978: 2034).
10

More specifically, drawing on several of Poulantzass analyses, authoritarian statism can be said to have six key features. First, the states legislative, executive, and judicial branches are increasingly fused, with real power now concentrated and centralized in the administration. Second, Parliament becomes a mere electoral registration chamber with circumscribed powers and there is a decline in the rule of law. Third, political parties no longer fulfil their traditional functions in policy-making (through compromise around a common programme) and in political legitimation (through electoral competition for a mandate). Instead, fourth, the natural governing parties (as defined by Gamble 1973) now function to legitimate state policy and transmit the prevailing state ideology to the masses through quasi-plebiscitary electioneering as Schumpeter (1943) had already posited and, in this context, engage in electoral manipulation based partly on cultivating close ties to the mass media, which also acquire a key role in legitimation. Conversely, fifth, as monopoly capital finds it hard to organize its hegemony through parties other than the dominant mass party (which can comprise an entrenched single party or a centrist tendency with wings in all natural governing parties), it also relies on an expanded lobby system to influence the administration. Sixth, a parallel power network cross-cuts the formal divisions of the state and wields a decisive role behind the scenes on behalf of monopoly capital in coordinating official, semi-official, and private activities across various policy fields. It follows the evolving strategic line of the dominant mass party (when it is in power) and plays an obstructive role if a radical party wins office (Poulantzas 1978: 203-40; for similar arguments, see Armin 2005; Greven 2010; and, on parties in particular, Blyth and Katz 2005). Poulantzas related the irresistible rise of authoritarian statism mainly to the states increasing assumption of economic functions to tame the wilder manifestations of capitals crisis-tendencies (witness the Great Depression), promote international competitiveness, and extend the profit-oriented, market-mediated logic of capital accumulation into ever more spheres of social life (1978: 163-99). In the era of finance-dominated accumulation, taming the wilder manifestations also means to intervene periodically to underwrite the solvency of banks, to provide extraordinary liquidity and to guarantee the deposits of the public with banks (Lapavitsas 2013 a: 27-28). This expanding range of activities undermines the rule of law based on
11

general, formal, and universal norms enacted by a parliament with a popular mandate. Instead legal norms are set by the political executive and administration in the light of particular conjunctures, situations, and interests. Nowadays one might add that their elaboration is increasingly delegated to non-accountable private authorities at different scales up to and including the global (for example, Cutler 2009; McKeen-Edwards and Porter 2013). While this summary may imply that Poulantzas believed that the authoritarian statist path runs smoothly, he stressed that state power continually runs up against limits inherent in its political matrix and operations (reflected in internal divisions and political resistance) as well as limits imposed by the contradictory and dilemmatic capital relation. Thus he argued that this trend involves a paradoxical strengthening-weakening of the state. Muddling through, crises of crisis-management, and pre-emptive policing of resistance were other symptoms of the incompressibility of capitals contradictions and the intensifying crisis-tendencies of an increasingly integrated world market (Poulantzas 1978: 241-247 and passim; for a detailed exposition and critique, see Jessop 1985).

Post-Democracy

Colin Crouch has recently won acclaim for an analysis that is superficially similar to those just presented. But he focuses on symptoms at the level of the political scene and fails to connect trends there to more fundamental shifts in capitalism. He starts from the vacuum in mass political participation created by the decline of the working class in advanced capitalist societies. The political class is now linked to society more or less solely via business lobbyists (Crouch 2004: viii). While elections continue and can change governments, electoral debate is now a tightly controlled spectacle, managed by rival teams of professional experts in persuasion and focusing on a few issues chosen by these teams. The mass of citizens plays a passive, quiescent, even apathetic part, responding only to the signals given them. Behind the scenes, however, politics is shaped by interaction between elected governments and self-serving elites, which overwhelmingly represent business interests (2004: 4, 19). This trend occurs not only in interventionist welfare states but also in neo-liberal regimes with limited state spending. Indeed, the more that the state withdraws from providing for the lives of ordinary people, making them

12

apathetic about politics, the more easily can corporate interests use it more or less unobserved as their private milch-cow (Crouch 2004: 19).

Crouch adds that the political party form has changed from a set of concentric circles tied to its social base towards a complex organization of leaders, activist professionals, sympathetic experts who work for money, pure professionals (who may not be supporters), and groups of lobbyists who move between party, lobbying, and business organizations (2004: 72-73; cf. Wedel 2009). An activist base is no longer vital to electoral success: electioneering is now funded by the private sector. So the classic party of the twenty-first century would be a self-reproducing inner elite, remote from its mass movement base, but nested squarely within a number of corporations, which will in turn fund the sub-contracting of opinion-polling, policyadvice and vote-gathering services in exchange for firms that seek political influence being well regarded by the party when in government (2004: 74).

FINANCE-DOMINATED ACCUMULATION

These three accounts indicate a declining affinity between capitalism and democracy, although they trace its origins to the interwar period, the mid-1970s, and the 1990s respectively. This paper now explores this decreasing fit in three ways. First, it identifies changes in the circuits of capital linked to financialization and the ties between interest-bearing capital and the state apparatus ties that become especially evident during economic crises. Second, it notes that the resulting crisis of bourgeois political hegemony (whether this is based on claims to democratic legitimacy or on delivering growth and prosperity for all or most citizens) is nonetheless combined with a remarkable survival of bourgeois political as well as economic domination. It relates this apparent paradox to the further extension of a post-democratic authoritarian statism. And, third, in line with Poulantzass analysis, it argues that this is related to a simultaneous strengthening-weakening of state power that is expressed in the current crisis of crisis-management in relation to the North Atlantic Financial Crisis, the Eurozone crisis, and the problems of dealing with public and sovereign debt.

13

For a while, some commentators held that the rise of finance -led growth following the crisis of wage-led growth linked to Fordism would facilitate economic democracy. This would not involve some form of workers control but the freeing of citizen-clients to become sovereign-consumers. Fordism involved a virtuous circle of mass production and mass consumption and a crucial role for the Fordist wage relation as a driver of rising prosperity in relatively closed national economies, the financialization of capitalist social relations (including the wage relation) would enable workers to share in wealth-driven growth based on their patrimony in home ownership, shares, funded private pensions, and so on (e.g., Aglietta and Rebrioux 2005; see also Boyer 2000). Some believed that this private Keynesianism was an adequate substitute for the Keynesian welfare state. Following the NAFC, however, advocates of this view are less sanguine. Well before this crisis, however, other commentators had already suggested the term finance -dominated to describe this post-Fordist regime in order to separate the empirical trend towards the autonomization of finance from the question of whether it produces growth, greater volatility, or stagnation (Stockhammer 2011: 3; see also van Treeck 2008).

Financialization is a principle of societal organization as well as a form of economic organization. Money, credit and debt have existed for three millennia but acquire new forms and functions with the consolidation of profit-oriented, market-mediated capitalism based on formally free labour-power. In particular, capitalist credit-money is one of the basic forms of the capital relation and essential to its continued reproduction. Among the forms of credit money emerging with capitalism is interestbearing capital (to be distinguished from more traditional usury capital) and this, in turn, can generate increasingly fantastic forms of fictitious capital (Marx 1967; Carneiro et al., 2012). Where the circuits of interest-bearing capital became increasingly autonomous from those of profit-producing capital (which can only occur in the short- to medium-term before serious crises occur), the impact of fictitious credit, fictitious capital, and fictitious profits reshaped the wider social formation in many respects. These fictitious forms are major vectors of the colonization, commodification, and, eventually, financialization of everyday life. This points beyond the general significance of capitalist credit-money in the circuits of capital to its specific forms and effects when interest-bearing capital, as opposed, for example, to suppliers of trade or production credit, becomes the dominant force in economic,
14

political, and social life. This did not result spontaneously from the operation of the invisible hand but required a series of deliberate economic, political, and social interventions mediated through the iron fist of the state (often in a velvet glove) and invisible handshakes that can be placed under the rubric of neo-liberalization and its role in accelerating world market integration (Dumnil and Lvy 2004; Harvey 2005).

Neo-liberalization varies nationally but everywhere tends to favour exchange- over use-value. The neo-liberal project treats workers as disposable and substitutable factors of production, the wage (including the social wage) as a cost of (international) production, profit-generating capital as value-in-motion rather than substantive assets, money as hypermobile interest-bearing capital than national fiat money, nature as a commodity, knowledge as intellectual property, and so on (Jessop 2002). The neo-liberal form of world market integration enhances capitals capacity to defer and/or displace internal contradictions and other problems onto other economic actors and interests, other spheres of society, and the environment in several ways (Jessop 2012). Interest-bearing capital gains strongly from this because it controls the most liquid, abstract, and generalized resource and because it has become the most integrated fraction of capital. More generally, the disembedding of capital from the frictions of national power containers and national politics means that the law of value tends more and more to operate globally by commensurating local conditions at the same time as it promotes the treadmill search for superprofits. Among other effects, this treadmill pressured banking capital to supplement the boring banking activities of financial intermediation and risk-management with financial speculation and risk-taking in the search for higher profits (cf. LiPuma and Lee 2004; Haldane 2012; Elsner 2012). Indeed, as more scandals emerge in the financial sector, it is becoming clear that these superprofits derive in part from predatory and, indeed, criminal activities that were facilitated by successive measures of deregulation enacted thanks to the financing of political parties and unusual deals with political bodies (Smith 2010; Will, Handelman, and Brotherton 2013).

In short, neo-liberalism tends to promote financialization, both as a strategic objective and as an inevitable outcome. As this process expands and penetrates deeper into the social and natural world, it transforms the micro-, meso- and macro15

dynamics of capitalist economies. First, it alters the calculations and behaviour of non-financial firms through the rise of shareholder value as a coercive discourse, technology of governance, and vector of competition. One aspect is the growing importance for non-financial firms of financial activities (e.g., treasury functions, financial intermediation, using retained profits for share buybacks and/or acquisition or expansion of financial subsidiaries) that are not directly tied to their main profitproducing pursuits. Thus financial revenues became more important relative to profits of enterprise for these firms (Krippner 2005; Nlke 2009; Lapavitsas 2013a). Second, it boosts the size and influence of the financial sector. Fee-producing and risk-taking activities increase relative to banking capitals more traditional roles in intermediation and risk management; securitization, leverage and shadow banking with corresponding liquidity risks and weak prudential controls also expand; and so does the significance of new forms of financial capital (e.g., hedge funds, private equity, vulture capital, sovereign wealth funds). Third, everyday life is financialized (see below). Fourth, as successive crises from the mid-1970s show, financialization makes the economy more prone to recession and, in severe cases, more liable to the downward spiral of debt-deflation-default dynamics (Dore 2008; Dumnil and Lvy, 2005; Fine 2010; Lapavitsas 2013a; Rasmus 2010).

Table 1 summarizes some of these themes and also presents some key aspects of the institutional and spatio-temporal fixes of an ideal-typical finance-dominated accumulation regime when it is relatively stable. This account is based on a modified rgulation approach perspective that returns to its first-generation studies that took seriously the contradictions of the capital relation (for details, see Jessop 2013a).

In these terms, the principal (or dominant) structural forms are money and the (social) wage relation; others are subordinated to these forms in potentially destabilizing ways as the genesis and repercussions of the NAFC show. The primary aspect of money (understood as credit money rather than coin or bullion) in this regime is its role as the most abstract expression of capital and its disembedding from national economic controls in a space of global flows. Fictitious credit (pseudovalidated loans that are not advanced for productive investment) and fictitious capital (capital as property rather than functioning capital) gain a much larger role compared with Fordism with the volumes of securitized loans and of credit advanced for
16

financial trading massively boosted by neo-liberal banking and financial deregulation. Financial innovation in turn facilitates the increasing acceleration and hyper-mobility of credit money and its escape from regulation. This contrasts with the more territorial logic of Atlantic Fordism, in which national economies were relatively closed, the Bretton Woods international monetary regime was based on a gold-dollar exchange standard and set limits to currency volatility, and even liberal market economies regulated their financial institutions. The secondary aspect of money capital (real assets) was secured through the neo-liberal policy boost to post-tax profits for profit-producing capital, reflecting the importance of ties to political authorities in finance-dominated regimes and the general dynamic of competitive fiscal policy in the world market in other regimes. The boost to post-tax profits has not always been reflected, however, in productive investment owing to pressures from the logic of shareholder value (Aglietta and Rebrioux 2005).

The primary aspect of the wage is its treatment as a cost of (global) production rather than as a source of (domestic) demand; this is linked to re-commodification of social welfare in housing, pensions, higher education, health insurance, and so on. This leads to growing flexibility of wage labour (especially increasing precarization), downward pressure on wages and working conditions, and cuts in the residual social wage. A further result is the financialization of everyday life as the labour force turns to credit (and usury) to maintain its standard of living and to provide for its daily, lifecourse, and intergenerational reproduction. Combined with the increased returns to profit-producing and interest-bearing capital, this also intensifies income and wealth inequalities in the economies subject to finance-dominated accumulation, which now match or exceed their levels in just before the 1929 Crash (Elsner 2012; Saez 2013).

The best possible state form for such a regime, more noted for its absence than presence, is an Ordo-liberal framework, as envisaged in the original Social Market Economy paradigm. This would provide a formally adequate institutional and spatiotemporal fix, including the embedding of neo-liberalism internationally in a new constitutionalism with credible commitments to corporate social responsibility. However, the neo-liberal bias towards de-regulation, which widened the space for financialization, was more often linked to an institutional fix that relied (and still relies) on unusual deals with political authority, predatory capitalism, and reckless
17

speculation all of which have fuelled the global financial crisis. As the limits to more market, less state emerged, there was growing resort to flanking and supporting measures to keep the neo-liberal show on the road. This was reflected in the discourse and policies of the Third Way, which maintained the course of neo liberalization in new circumstances, and is linked to the NAFC (witness its eruption under New Labour in Britain as well as the Bush Administration in the USA).

Table 1: Finance-Dominated Accumulation en Rgulation?


Basic Form Primary Aspect
Fast, hyper-mobile money as general form (+ derivatives) as general form Private wage plus household credit (promote private Keynesianism) Neo-liberal policies with Ordo-liberal constitution

Secondary Aspect
Valorization of capital as fixed asset in global division of labour Cut back on residual social wage as (global) cost of production Flanking plus soft + hard disciplinary measures to secure neo-liberalism Dampen uneven growth, adapt to rising economies

Institutional Fixes
De-regulation of financial markets, state targets price stability, not jobs Numerical + time flexibility; new credit forms for households

Spatiotemporal fixes
Disembed flows from national or regional state controls; grab future values War for talents + race to bottom for most workers and squeezed middle

Money / Capital

(Social) wage

State

Intensifies uneven Free market plus development at authoritarian strong many sites + scales state as market outcome Core-periphery tied to US power, its allies and relays

Global Regime

Create open space of flows for all forms of capital

Washington Consensus regimes

K E Y

Principal (or dominant) structural form Primary aspect of principal form Secondary aspect of principal form

Secondary structural form Primary aspect of secondary form Secondary aspect of secondary form

The global influence of financialization was facilitated by the Washington Consensus, which was heavily promoted by the USA and its allies to roll out liberalization, deregulation, privatization, and market proxies in any residual state services (whether infrastructural or welfare). This Consensus also promoted cuts in direct taxes (notably for corporations and financial institutions), aided by a fiscal race to the
18

bottom to attract or retain investment and by greater use of onshore as well as offshore tax havens) and a shift towards indirect taxes. This was supposed to increase the scope for market forces to allocate capital globally but, in conjunction with political capitalism and the logic of shareholder value, it has also re-distributed income and wealth towards the have-lots at the expense not only of the have -nots but also of the squeezed middle.

The crisis of finance-dominated accumulation emerges from the contradictions of the capital relation as these are modified by this regime and its specific instantiations. Because continued expansion depends heavily on the pseudo-validation of highly leveraged speculative and Ponzi debt, this regime contains its own inherent crisisgenerating mechanism rooted in the systemic conflict between interest-bearing and profit-producing capital. Wolfram Elsner explains this as follows. Financial capital in this regime has a target rate of return that is several times greater than the historic norm for profit-producing capital and, worse still, in an effort to achieve this target, engages in massive leveraging of fictitious credit and capital. In aggregate, the eventual validation of this massively leveraged capital would demand a total volume of surplus-value that far exceeds the productive and exploitative capacity of existing profit-producing capital. Attempts to square this circle depend on three strategies that are individually and collectively unsustainable. One is to create and manage bubbles, the main redistribution mechanism in finance-dominated accumulation, and then bail out (or get bailed out) at the right moment (Elsner 2012: 146-7). This is impossible without the complicity of central banks and government in the financedominated economies and those subject to their contagion effects. Another is to invoke a system-threatening financial emergency that justifies efforts to reduce individual and social wages, impose internal devaluation, and privatize public services and assets to pay off the public debt incurred in massive bailouts. States at different sites and scales have key roles here too. The third strategy involves primitive accumulation (e.g., land-grabbing, capitalizing nature and its services enclosing the intellectual commons, privatizing accumulated public wealth, colonizing the residual public sector, and so on). This is also impossible without state involvement. In short, the most rarefied and leveraged forms of fictitious credit and capital are now primarily, and systemically rather than merely contingently, problemmakers; and the rest of the economy, society and nature are the problem-takers.
19

Through these and other mechanisms the NAFC reverses many features of the institutional and spatio-temporal fixes that (could have) provided it with some partial, provisional, and temporary stability. Fictitious profits and wealth combined with private Keynesianism did not ensure stable finance-led growth but created volatility and crisis. Because of these reversals, and without decisive intervention to roll back the power of financial capital that neo-liberalism has facilitated, the crisis tends to feed on itself economically, politically, and socially (see Table 2). Contagion in the Eurozone has additional causes and consequences, rooted in attempts to use monetary union to reinforce neo-liberalism and promote the euro as a quasi-world money without establishing the necessary institutional conditions for an effective currency, banking, fiscal, and transfer union (cf. Lapavitsas 2013b).

Table 2: Finance-Dominated Accumulation in Crisis


Basic Form Secondary Aspect
Epic recession based on debtdefault-deflation dynamics (D4) Austerity reinforces D4 double dip or epic recession Austerity policies meet resistance, harsher discipline

Primary Aspect

Institutional Fixes
De-regulation crisis of TBTF predatory finance + contagion effects

Spatio-temporal fixes
Protectionism in core economies, growing resistance to free trade from periphery

Money/ Capital

Rising antagonism between Main Street and Wall Street (City, etc.)

(Social) wage

Credit crunch puts private Keynesianism into reverse

Growing reserve army of surplus, precarious labour

Global crisis and internal devaluation reproduction crisis

State

Political capitalism undermines any Ordo-liberalism

Crises in political markets reinforce post-democracy Crisis + rejection of (post-) Washington Consensus

Cannot halt uneven development at many sites + scales

Global Regime

Unregulated space of flows intensifies triple crisis

Multilateral, multiscalar imbalances and race to bottom

Crisis of US hegemony, BRICS in crisis and disarray

While financialization initially benefitted many economic agents, the collapse of credit bubbles and the implosion of financial speculation have reversed this stimulus effect.
20

Whereas growth in this regime depended on acceleration in fictitious credit, the writing down of bad debt, the repayment of debt, reluctance to contract new debt, and the hoarding of available capital throw the mechanism of pseudo-validated demand into reverse. Thus debt deleveraging, especially when it occurs in both the private and public sectors, creates conditions for a vicious cycle of debt -defaultdeflation dynamics and an eventual epic recession (Rasmus 2010; Keen 2011).

The unwillingness of interest-bearing capital to sacrifice its short-term economic interests to protect its long-term political hegemony or, at least, domination activates the potential antagonism between Wall Street and Main Street (and their equivalents elsewhere) in three ways. First, too-big-to-fail financial institutions benefit from bailouts and from quantitative easing that enables them to rebuild their capital base at low or no cost and to undertake further speculation. Second, small and medium enterprises find it harder to access production and trade credit. And, third, households find it harder to secure personal credit and/or to fund their now privatized health, pension, higher education, and other life-course and intergenerational reproduction needs. Most households also lose from the attack on entitlements, previously part of the social wage in democratic welfare states, as these are portrayed even more vocally than before as costs that prevent the rundown of public and sovereign debt. This reversal of private Keynesianism reinforces the debtdefault-deflation dynamics that threaten to shift economies from recession into epic recession or even another depression. Similar results follow in the Eurozone from official attempts to create an internal devaluation through cuts in the private and social wage, other production costs, and so on, to compensate for the legal restrictions on devaluation or exit from the Eurozone. I deal with the some of the political preconditions and effects of these crisis measures in the next section. Debt-default-deflation dynamics also strengthen other crisis-tendencies inherent in neo-liberalism. The global reserve army of labour expands, weakening workers bargaining power over wages and conditions, and increasing precarious work. Privatization and austerity in areas needed for a productive rather than parasitic economy (e.g., infrastructure provision, education, health, and science) are undermining their capacity to promote growth in the real economy. A fragile Washington Consensus is challenged by demands for protectionism in crisis-hit
21

metropolitan economies and opposition to free trade in the periphery (sometimes linked to proposals for post-neo-liberalism). Yet transnational elites continue to present free trade agreements as an essential and purportedly cost-free economic recovery measure and to veil the extent to which such agreements would actually entrench the rights of capital as private property against subaltern groups and less market-friendly states and regimes. The NAFC has also aggravated imbalances in the global economy and shifted its centre of gravity to the east and south but even beneficiaries such as the BRICS have suffered contagion from the NAFC in addition to experiencing their own particular, endogenous crisis-tendencies. From Social to Political Restoration?

The reversals noted above, the conflicts they provoke, and the resulting political and economic challenges for crisis-management, are reinforcing the trend toward postdemocratic authoritarian statism. The genesis and survival of the finance-dominated regime are linked to a predatory and parasitic politically oriented capitalism. Interestbearing capital and other capitals with vested interests in the neo-liberal project have used their political influence to rescue financial institutions that are too big, too systemically important, or just too well-connected to be allowed to fail. Rather than allowing market forces to discipline financial institutions through losses and bankruptcy, states have socialized losses, translating private debt into public and/or sovereign debt. They have also taken direct responsibility for managing contagion effects in the always-already monetized real economy, albeit in the pro-cyclical, counterproductive form of private and public austerity. These measures have been pursued at national level by natural governing parties from the centre -left and centre-right as well as by more technocratic (i.e., bank-friendly, non-accountable) regimes at the international, European, and some national levels. Indeed, the Federal Reserve, the Bank of England, and the troika in Europe (ECB, EU and IMF) asymmetrically defend too big to fail institutions, protect tax-avoiding, tax-evading companies and wealthy elites, and impose the costs of crisis on the general population (cf. Johnson 2009; Hudson 2011; Elsner 2012). This has involved virtual coups dtat in Greece and Italy and the more general fuelling of deficit hysteria to justify yet more neo-liberal policy measures in other indebted economies. Part of the ideological campaign in this regard is the spurious conflation of necessary but boring
22

banking with financial speculation and risk-taking and the claim that shrinking and regulating the latter activities will undermine the former.

Efforts to renew the finance-dominated, neo-liberal model tell us something about the ability of those with power not to have to learn from their mistakes as well as about the broader dynamics of class domination. Indeed, as interest-bearing capital has finally encountered the constraints of real economic growth, it has upped the stakes in the pursuit of neo-liberalism. The new normal regime involves a paradoxical strengthening and weakening of state power. Resort to bailouts and quantitative easing that rely on the states role as lender of last resort and its monopoly of taxation indicate the limited powers of the state to tame the effects of crisis and, thanks to the influence of financial interests, to introduce reforms that would present its resurgence. All the fisco-financial measures taken to date (July 2013), which are unprecedented in scale, have failed to resolve the underlying contradictions and crisis-tendencies of finance-dominated accumulation and there is a palpable crisis of crisis-management in many states and international agencies. One sign of this is the growing split between the exit strategies proposed by profitproducing capital and the policies favoured by those identified with the more fantastical, irrational forms of interest-bearing capital and their allies. The neo-liberal project has produced: (1) representational crises as the electorate grows more detached from stable alignments with natural governing parties; (2) a legitimacy crisis following from the failure to deliver sustainable finance-led growth and the costs associated with crisis-management; and (3) a crisis of intellectual and moral leadership associated with outright deception, official secrecy, populist rhetoric, and media spin. In short, declaring states of economic and political emergency and resorting to emergency measures indicate weakness rather than strength. Furthermore, as austerity policies begin to bite, there is growing, if still fragmented, resistance and growing anger about the kind of linkages among interest-bearing capital, politicians, and state managers that Max Weber would have called political capitalism. The best-known expressions of this resentment were for a while the Occupy Movement with its slogan of the 99% the 1% and the Astro-turf Tea Party movement in the USA. But there are many other grass -roots manifestations in, for example, Greece, Spain, and Italy and many commentators have related the Arab
23

Spring to the impact of neo-liberal policies and financialization in the Middle East and North Africa. But these movements mainly operate at a distance from the state, changing the calculations of economic and political elites, but lacking access to the real levers of power in the circuits of capital, the inner sanctums of national and supranational state authorities, and the international agencies that exercise decisive private authority in the world market. Overall, this reconfiguration of the state and governance in response to the NAFC, its contagion effects elsewhere, and the associated but distinct Eurozone Crisis involves more than a simple continuation of trends that were already being discussed in the 1920s and 1930s and again in the 1970s and 1980s well before the inherent crisis-tendencies of neo-liberalism, financialization, and financedominated accumulation emerged in their heartlands (as opposed to the semiperiphery and periphery) during the 2000s. Indeed, to flirt with evolutionary language, the development of authoritarian statism seems to have been a preadaptive change that is even more beneficial in the current crisis of financedominated accumulation. We are still witnessing a step-change in the move to postdemocratic authoritarian statism and this is grounded in the increasingly tight web of connections between interest-bearing capital and the political class along the lines indicated in theories of (privatized) state monopoly capitalism. This nexus created the conditions for financialization. It also enabled the de facto declaration of a state of economic emergency that justified (1) the use of exceptional powers to rescue insolvent financial institutions rather than to nationalize them or allow normal bankruptcy procedures to be implemented and (2) the parallel declaration of a state of political emergency that justifies increased surveillance, pre-emptive policing, and paramilitary suppression of dissent. Even if there is a return to financial business as usual and interest-bearing capital has been fully restored socially, political restoration of democratic rule will not be delivered voluntarily by the financial oligarchy. This must be wrested from below.

The Challenges of Political Restoration and Social Emancipation

The bourgeois democratic republic is no longer, if ever it was, the best possible political shell for capitalism. The declining affinity between profit-oriented, market24

mediated accumulation and constitutional democratic states is especially marked where neo-liberal, finance-dominated accumulation has prevailed under the aegis of interest-bearing capital. Yet the emerging conjuncture is taking a form different from that envisaged by Marx in his comments on the fundamental contradiction in the democratic constitution (see above). It is not the privileges of some national Ancien Rgime that is being restored politically as well as socially; instead we are seeing the political consolidation of a new transnational power bloc organized around the interests of interest-bearing capital.

This is a fresh illustration in another period of the comprehensive contradiction at the heart of the democratic constitution and shows the fragile nature of the correlation between capitalism and democracy. Where this correlation has existed, it depends on trade in free markets and the rational organization of capitalist production in conditions where an unstable equilibrium of compromise between capital and labour allows labour to share in productivity gains through the wage and social wage (a classic case is Atlantic Fordism). Neoliberalism and finance-dominated accumulation challenge this relation. For, as Michael Hudson (2011) notes, for neoliberals, a free market is one free for a tax-favoured rentier class to extract interest, economic rent and monopoly prices (Hudson 2011). This kind of free market, with its heavy dependence on political lobbying, on unusual deals with political authorities, and on force and domination to promote accumulation through dispossession, is incompatible with the stripped-down formal democracy that currently exists.

By way of illustration, Wolfram Elsner suggests: The EU Economic and Financial Governance (or Government) by the President of the EU Commission, the ECB president, the heads of IMF and ESM, the Council of Economic and Finance Ministers, and top bankers, may easily become the post-democratic prototype and even a pre-dictatorial governance structure against national sovereignty and democracies (Elsner 2012: 158, italics in original).

The post-democratic, authoritarian state of political emergency that is being constructed in this conjuncture will continue as the best possible political shell for a
25

predatory, finance-dominated accumulation regime even if, and when, the financial crisis is resolved. For, as noted above, the survival of this new bloc depends heavily on Webers three forms of political capitalism. The longer it survives, the more harmful its effects on the real economy, human flourishing, and the natural environment. Crises do not engender their own solutions but are objectively overdetermined moments of subjective indeterminacy. How they are resolved, if at all, depends on the balance of forces in each case. The manner and form of resolution determines the forms of appearance of subsequent crises. It remains to see whether the many fragmented forms of resistance can be linked up horizontally, vertically, and transversally to provide an effective challenge to this new bloc, its finance-dominated accumulation regime and its the new normal state form by exploiting their fragilities. This will require connecting economic and political power in ways that are proscribed by the democratic rules of the game but are realized continually in non-democratic ways by the new transnational financial bloc.

Acknowledgements

This paper derives from an ESRC-funded Professorial Fellowship (RES-051-270303). It benefitted from discussions with Alex Demirovi, Alexander Gallas, Mathis Heinrich, Thomas Sablowski, and Walter Oetsch. The usual disclaimers apply.

References

Aglietta, M. and A. Rebrioux (2005) Corporate Governance Adrift: A Critique of Shareholder Value, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. Armin, H.H. von (2001) Das System: Die Machenschaft der Macht, Munich: Droemer. Blyth, M. and Katz, R.S. (2005). From catch-all politics to cartelisation: the political economy of the cartel party, West European Politics, 28: 33-60. Boyer, R. (2000) Is a finance-led growth regime a viable alternative to Fordism?, Economy and Society, 29: 111-145. Crouch, C. (2004) Post-Democracy, Cambridge: Polity. Cutler, C.A. (2009) Constituting capitalism: corporations, law, and private transnational governance, St Antonys International Review, 5: 99-115.
26

de Medeiros Carneiro, R., M. Chiliatto-Leite, G. Santos Mello, and P. Rossi (2012) The fourth dimension: derivatives in a capitalism with financial dominance. Paper for International Initiative on Political Economy Conference, Paris: 06 July 2012. http://www.assoeconomiepolitique.org/political-economy-outlook-forcapitalism/wp-content/uploads/2012/06/Fourth-Dimension_version-Paris.pdf, (accessed 30 November 2012). Dore, R. (2008) Financialization of the global economy, Industrial and Corporate Change, 17: 10971112. Dumnil, G. and D. Lvy (2011) The Crisis of Neoliberalism, London: Harvard University Press. Elsner, W. (2012) Financial capitalism at odds with democracy: The trap of an impossible profit rate, Real-World Economics Review, 62: 132-159.

http://www.paecon.net/PAEReview/issue62/Elsner62.pdf (accessed 18 February 2013) Ferguson, N. (2001) The Cash Nexus. Money and Power in the Modern World , 1700-2000, New York: Basic Books. Fine, B. (2010) Locating financialization, Historical Materialism, 18: 97-116. Friedman, M. (1962) Capitalism and Freedom, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Gamble, A. (1973) A Conservative Nation, London: Routledge. Gerschenkron, A. (1962) Economic Backwardness in Historical Perspective, London: Harvard University Press. Gerstenberger, H. (2011) The historical constitution of the political forms of the capitalist state, Antipode, 43(3): 60-86 Greven, M. (2010) Sind Parteien in der Politik alternativlos oder ist ihre Rolle historisch begrenzt?, in D. Gehne and T. Spier (eds) Krise oder Wandel der Parteiendemokratie? Wiesbaden: VS Verlag. Haldane, A. (2012) The doom loop, London Review of Books 34(4): 21-22. Harvey, D. (2005) A Brief History of Neoliberalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Herzog, P. (1971) Politique conomique et planification en rgime capitaliste, Paris: ditions Sociales. Hirsch, J. (1985) Der Sicherheitsstaat, Hamburg: VSA Verlag. Holloway, J. and Picciotto, S. (1977) Capital, crisis, and the state, Capital & Class, 1(2): 76-101.

27

Hudson, M. (2011) Europes deadly transition from social democracy to oligarchy, Counterpunch, 9-11 December. Jessop, B. (1985) Nicos Poulantzas: Marxist Theory and Political Strategy, Basingstoke: Macmillan. (2002) The Future of the Capitalist State, Cambridge: Polity. (2012) Neo-Liberalism, in G. Ritzer (ed.),The Wiley-Blackwell Encyclopedia of Globalization, vol 3, Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell. (2013a) Revisiting the regulation approach: critical reflections on the contradictions, dilemmas, fixes and crisis dynamics of growth regimes, Capital & Class, 37(1), 5-24. (2013b) The North Atlantic financial crisis and varieties of capitalism a Minsky moment and/or a Marx moment? And perhaps Weber too?, in S. Fadda and P. Tridico (eds), Financial Crisis, Labour Markets and Institutions, London: Routledge. Johnson, S. (2009) The quiet coup, The Atlantic, 9 May Jung, H. (1979) Zur privatmonopolistische Entwicklungsvariante des staatsmonopolistischen Kapitalismus in der BRD, in Staat und Monopole (III), Berlin: Argument Verlag. Keen, S. (2011) Economic growth, asset markets and the credit accelerator, RealWorld Economics Review, 57: 25-40. Krippner, G.R. (2005) The financialization of the American economy, SocioEconomic Review, 3: 173208. Lapavitsas, C. (2013a) Profiting without Producing: How Finance Exploits All, London: Verso (in press). (2013b) The Eurozone crisis through the prism of world money, in M.H. Wolfson and G.A. Epstein (eds), The Handbook of the Political Economy of Financial Crises, Oxford: Oxford University Press, LiPuma, E. and Lee, B. (2004) Financial Derivatives and the Globalization of Risk. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. MacPherson, C.B. (1973) The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mandel, E. (1972) Late Capitalism. London: Verso. Marx, K. (1967) Capital, Vol. 3. London: Lawrence & Wishart <1894>

28

(1978) Class Struggles in France 1848-1850, in Marx-Engels Collected Works Vol. 11, London: Lawrence & Wishart, 47-145 <1850> Nlke, A. (2009) Finanzkrise, Finanzialisierung und vergleichende Kapitalismusforschung, Zeitschrift fr Internationale Beziehungen, 16: 12339. Mckeen-Edwards, H. and Porter, T. (2013) Transnational Financial Associations and the Governance of Global Finance, London: Routledge. Moore, S.W. (1957) The Critique of Capitalist Democracy, New York: PaineWhitman. Poulantzas, N. (1973) Political Power and Social Classes, London: NLB. (1978) State, Power, Socialism. London: Verso. Rasmus, J. (2010) Epic Recession. London: Pluto. Saez, E. (2013) Striking it richer: The evolution of top incomes in the United States (Updated with 2011 estimates), at http://elsa.berkeley.edu/~saez/ (accessed 18 February 2013). Schumpeter, J.A. (1943) Capitalism, Socialism, Democracy, London: George Allen & Unwin. Smith, Y. (2010) Econned: How Unenlightened Self-Interest undermined Democracy and Corrupted Capitalism, New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. Stockhammer, E. (2011) Interview with Engelbert Stockhammer, Revue de la Rgulation, 10, http://regulation.revues.org/9365 (accessed 19 December 2012). van Treeck, T. (2008) The political economy debate on financialization: a macroeconomic perspective, Working Paper 01/2008. Dsseldorf: Institut fr Makrokonomie und Konjunkturforschung. Weber, M. (1978) Economy and Society. Berkeley: University of California Press <1922> Weber, M. (1994) Max Weber: Political Writings, ed. P. Lassmann and R. Spiers, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press <1905-1919> Wedel, J. (2009) Shadow Elite, New York: Basic Books. Will, S., Brotherton, D., and Handelman, S. (eds) (2013) How They Got Away with it: White Collar Criminals and the Financial Meltdown, New York: Columbia University Press.

29

You might also like