You are on page 1of 13

THE TERRITORY IS NOT THE MAP

PLACE, DELEUZE AND GUATTARI, AND AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY


Bruce B. Janz

At the beginning of “1227: Treatise on in the face of a coercive nation-state, but rather
Nomadology—The War Machine” in A Thou- begins by considering the roots of the experi-
sand Plateaus, Gilles Deleuze and Félix ence of territory.
Guattari contrast chess with Go in terms of the The concepts of the refrain and of nomadic
relation between the pieces and the kind of philosophy give us a clue to a way to rethink
space they create. “Chess,” they maintain, “is a African philosophy. The project of this essay is
game of state . . . chess pieces are coded; they to consider ways in which we might think of
have an internal nature and intrinsic properties African philosophy outside of the metaphors
from which their movements, situations, and of maps used by both modernist and also some
confrontations derive.”1 Go, on the other hand, postmodernist writers, the first to delineate and
has pieces that “are pellets, disks, simple arith- define area and establish ownership and citi-
metic units, and have only an anonymous, col- zenship, the second to clear space and allow for
lective, or third-person function: ‘It’ makes a possibilities. The first project of mapping,
move.” Chess has a “milieu of interiority,” in which has been the explicit or implicit project
other words, it takes its set of meanings from of the majority of African philosophy, leaves
the previously defined “essence” of each piece. African philosophy forever at the edge of
The space it creates is striated. Go, on the other Western thought, defining its territory by that
hand, has a milieu of exteriority. The space in already claimed. The second project, meant to
Go is smooth. It is a war without battle lines, resist that sense of entitlement, ends up avoid-
without boundaries, without aim or destina- ing discussions of subjectivity even as it tries to
tion, without departure or arrival. Chess avoid any hint of essentialism. We find out
“codes and decodes space,” while Go “pro- what we might choose, at the expense of know-
ceeds altogether differently, territorializing or ing what we do choose. The result in the first
deterritorializing it (make the outside a terri- case is a map that has little legitimacy, and in
tory in space, consolidate that territory by con- the second a map that has little use. The alter-
struction of a second, adjacent territory. . .).” native, I would like to suggest, is to rethink
Deleuze and Guattari here follow in the both the metaphysical and the postmodern ad-
theme of other plateaus, tracing nomadic diction to the notion of space, and instead sug-
subjectivities and exploring the contingent, gest that the concept of place holds more hope.
multifarious ways they come into themselves. The title to this essay is an obvious play on
The Treatise on Nomadology, while perhaps words. “The map is not the territory” is a com-
the most famous plateau, focuses on the con- mon expression that indicates the limits of rep-
trast between the “interiority,” or essentialism resentation. It suggests that we can never fully
of the State versus the “exteriority” or nomadic nor properly represent or capture the world.
qualities of the war machine. But this is “set Jorge Luis Borges imagines a map that is a 1:1
up” (to the extent that anything is really set up representation of the territory it is supposed to
for Deleuze and Guattari) by the plateau imme- represent.2 Of course, if we broaden our con-
diately preceding, “1837: Of the Refrain.” This ception of a map, we can imagine maps that are
plateau does not concern the social-philosoph- much larger than the territory—“maps” of sub-
ical problems of the emergence of subjectivity atomic reactions, the genome, and so forth.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY WINTER 2001


392
These maps define the boundaries, internal in- thinking and rethinking our relationship to the
teractions, and identity of the territory in ques- earth. We find ourselves in this flux, yet are not
tion. Maps, at least the ones common in the obliterated by its uncertainty.
modern age, start with abstractions, and fit the On a cursory reading, it may seem that
“territory” into a numerical or conceptual grid. Deleuze and Guattari are arguing for the prior-
To suggest that the map is not the territory is to ity of Greece in the history of philosophy. They
recognize that the territory is more than the ab- identify Greece as a unique point in the history
stractions of the map. of thought, a point at which there was suffi-
In turning the metaphor around, I want to cient organization to give relative safety to
turn the function of maps themselves around, thought but sufficient porousness to allow
and with it, turn around the way we think of Af- seepage of ideas from the outside. Greece has a
rican philosophy. Instead of mapping it, either set of necessary characteristics for the devel-
explicitly through a set of “trends” or some opment of philosophy. They identify three
other device that allows us to determine who’s such characteristics: immanence, friendship,
4
in and who’s out, to defend borders and claim and opinion. “Immanence” concerns the “in-
territory, I want to start with the notion of terri- ternational market” in which those who have
tory instead. In short, I want to argue that place, been alienated by the “empire” are able to find
the place we find ourselves in and which has freedom and mobility. It is the interaction of
meaning to us, precedes space, the bounded people outside of the structures of state. To be
and abstractly defined territory. sure, Greece had its city-states, but these con-
Deleuze and Guattari will serve as an unex- tained highly diverse interaction and inter-
pected door into this topic. Unexpected, be- change. “Friendship” refers to the pleasure
cause they are heirs of Western philosophy, people take in association, both in the connec-
and explicitly draw on Western themes. Unex- tions and the rivalries that it affords. And
pected also because of some comments made thirdly, Greek society made “opinion” possi-
in their final collaborative project about ble, or a freewheeling exchange of views and
“geophilosophy,” about the origins of philoso- conversation. These possibilities do not appear
phy. Nevertheless, they suggest a way to think in an empire, for empires are governed
placially that may be of value to African phi- “arboreally,” while Greece operated “rhizo-
losophy. matically.” Philosophy can only emerge under
Several aspects to the issue of place must be the horizontal life of rhizomes, not under the
addressed. First, what do we make of Deleuze vertical life of trees.
and Guattari’s seeming inappropriateness? The place of philosophy, then, is the place
Second, what is a place? Third, what is this that is made possible by these conditions.
place, the place out of which African philoso- Deleuze and Guattari do mention that philoso-
phy comes? Fourth, how do we clarify the con- phy emerges in cultures other than the West,
cepts available at this place, that is, how do we but they maintain that philosophy proper is es-
dwell in this place? sentially a Western artifact. “Chinese, Hindu,
Jewish, or Islamic” philosophy are possible,
Geophilosophy: “Thinking Takes Place inasmuch as thinking may take place on a
in the Relationship of Territory and the plane of immanence that can be populated by
5
figures as much as concepts, but philosophy in
Earth”
these contexts is really pre-philosophical.
In What Is Philosophy, Deleuze and While Deleuze and Guattari do not think there
Guattari use the term “geophilosophy” for a is any internal necessity to philosophy, they do
philosophy of the earth, one that recognizes the argue that in the case of non-Greek planes of
3
ebb and flow of life. We, as individuals and as immanence other outcomes such as religion or
a species, define and redefine our territory, wisdom are possible. As well, the milieu in the

PLACE IN AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY


393
non-Greek planes of immanence are not the in- tradition, and their usefulness to African phi-
teraction of concepts, but the reflection of con- l os ophy m us t be s e e n i n t hi s l i ght .
cepts on the non-philosophical. Nevertheless, they provide the possibility of
This seems to make Deleuze and Guattari thinking about place as a key concept, which
less than useful in a project that is meant to the- allows us to get out of the metaphysical pre-
orize African philosophy. However, it is im- sumptions that both Western and most African
portant to be clear about exactly what they are philosophy finds itself encumbered with.
saying here. In suggesting that Greek philoso- Still, we should also be aware of their com-
phy has a kind of priority, we are not led to a de- mitments as expressed in this chapter. The ben-
bate about the possibility that Greek philoso- efit of dealing with a concept such as that of
phy originated in Egypt. This is not an place, is that there is less of a tendency to sub-
historical argument that they are making, but sume the particular origins of the concept un-
an essentially philosophical one. Just as der some supposed universal such as space.
Hobbes need not (and should not) be read as Nevertheless, all concepts have their history,
saying that there really was a time in the history all are answers to a particular set of questions
of humanity that a state of nature existed, so that have a context. So, the task will not be to
Deleuze and Guattari are not necessarily say- excise any particular concept of its Western (or
ing that philosophy is historically traceable any other) bias, but to bring its particular ori-
only back to Greece; indeed, they say that “phi- gins to light, and in that way hope that its use in
losophy was something Greek—although conversation with other territorial assumptions
6
brought by immigrants.” Rather, we should
will give us another component in the task of
pay attention to the conditions they suggest as
asking about what it is to do philosophy in this
essential to its development. John Rajchman
African place.
puts it this way:
What can we gain from Deleuze and
One might say it was Deleuze’s intuition that we Guattari’s discussion of geophilosophy?
might now see philosophy as having—or as Geophilosophy emerges from the milieus that
having had—no intrinsic “home” or “land” or act and interact. These milieus become terri-
“civilization,” and that we might then rethink its tory, which itself is deterritorialized through
geographies and borders in terms of an odd po- the creative power of the refrain. There is no
tential that keeps arising in different times and
essence to place; it cannot be used as a trump
places, released through many circumstances
card by anyone to assert ownership or entitle-
and contingencies. Thus in his “geophilosophy”
ment. Deterritorialization, and its counterpart,
Deleuze says that philosophy might well have
started elsewhere than in Athens and with Plato,
reterritorialization, becomes possible because
for, instead of origins, philosophy has only a the refrain, the reflective habits that show us
“milieu” or “atmosphere,” favored by certain for who we are, continually re-think our place
conditions such as those provided by the “colo- in all its forms, re-configure it to be adequate
nizing democracy” of Athens, which brought for the times, and ultimately “release it to the
itinerant strangers into its agora to encounter Cosmos.” Place becomes something more than
Socrates.7 simple location, but less than essence, entitle-
ment, or citizenship. It cannot be identified by
None of this suggests that Deleuze and a map, it is not reducible to power alone. Yet,
Guattari can unambiguously be used in a pro- despite Deleuze and Guattari’s privileging of
ject such as this. They still do use Greece as Greece, the conditions become available for
their prime example of the source of philoso- philosophy to appear, and to be seen as having
phy, and they do explicitly mention non-West- appeared, outside of the West.
ern philosophies as being pre-philosophical. But we are ahead of ourselves. We have
Deleuze and Guattari are reacting to their own seen how it is not impossible that Deleuze and

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
394
Guattari could be part of the conversation as one sees it (sometimes, as in an Arctic storm,
about place and African philosophy. How, one cannot discern directional markers of any
then, is it possible? Put another way, as our sec- kind, and yet a native to the region knows how to
ond question: What is a place? get to places). . . . One finds one’s bearings
where one is , that is, in the very place, the local
Now We Are At Home. absolute one occupies—without counting.13

But Home Does Not Pre-Exist.


This does not re-introduce the concept of
The question of the nature of place has been space, though, because there is nothing ab-
the focus of a great deal of recent thought. The stract about the region of the nomad. The no-
chief analyst and synthesizer has been Edward mad does not “move around” a predetermined
8
C asey, w h o p r o d u c e d a ve r y fi ne space; indeed, the nomad should not be defined
phenomenological analysis in Getting Back in terms of movement at all (381). The nomad
Into Place and a synoptic and magisterial his- “does not depart, does not want to depart, who
torical overview of the origins, subsumption clings to the smooth space left by the receding
under the concept of space, and eventual re- forest, where the steppe or the desert advances,
emergence of place in The Fate Of Place. and who invents nomadism as a response to
Many others, in a variety of disciplines, have this challenge” (381). “One does not move to a
also contributed to the discussion of the nature dwelling but dwells by moving, that is, by tran-
9
of place. What has not been sufficiently inves- sition from place to place within (or, again, as)
tigated, however, is not so much the question of a region.”
14

the nature of place, but the place(s) from which The nomad continually deterritorializes, in
10
philosophy can and does come. Where, that this person re-produces the environment at
placially, is African philosophy located? the same time as he or she is produced by it.
Deleuze and Guattari’s A Thousand Plateaus Nomad “make the desert no less than they are
11
proves useful for this task. Two ways emerge made by it” (382). This is demonstrated most
from that work for thinking about place—the effectively by the second entry-point to
rel at ive ly w e ll- k n ow n “ Tr e a t i s e on Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of place in the
Nomadology,” and the lesser known idea of the preceding plateau, “1827—Of the Refrain.”
refrain. The refrain is an auditory notion, a repetition
The nomad traverses a territory, not as one that determines a territory. The refrain is a song
who is traveling between different points or to- that organizes and fends off chaos, that draws
ward destinations, but as one who “relays” be- from the earth a set of contingent meanings
tween intermediate points. The nomad is not that lead to identity.
the migrant, who goes from one point to the “From chaos, Milieus and Rhythms are
12
next, but rather one whose space is distributed born” (313). The milieu is a codification of
openly and indefinitely. The place of the no- repetitions, a limitation and rhythmatization
mad, then, is not a point but a trajectory and a on the chaos (which itself is the milieu of all
region. The nomad’s space is such that they do milieus). When we are at home, we have a set
not need to orient themselves by means of of rhythms that define a place as home, and in
fixed land-points: fact when we are away from home, we often
Here one moves not only in accordance with find ourselves setting up familiar rhythms to
cardinal directions or geometrically determined make a new place into home. There are
vectors but in a “polyvocality of directions”— codes—items are placed in a way meaningful
directions that are as much heard as seen, and in to those that know a place as home, and only
any case not merely posited as exigencies of partially accessible (if at all) by others. But
theory. On the high sea, or in the windswept these codes are never fixed; if they were, this
desert, one listens to direction, feels it, as much would just be an exercise in structuralism.

PLACE IN AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY


395
First, we change them just by living in and with bodies do not stop at our skin, they stop some-
them. Second, the milieus are constantly inter- where beyond, where our space becomes
acting with each other, changing the coding of identified as ours. This can expand or contract
the rhythms we have set up. It is not that I as a based on the clothing we wear, the way we
reflecting subjectivity set out to model the spread out our belongings out around us on a
world in my image, in some Hegelian manner. table, or the language we use. The milieu con-
My subjectivity lies in the set of rhythms and stantly changes, and is constantly layered.
repetitions I have found to be useful. Territory is not the same as the milieu. Terri-
But perhaps most importantly, the milieu is tory, as MacGregor Wise puts it, is the “accre-
18
not simply an external location of meaning for tion of milieu effects.” Milieus are constantly
the self. This does not easily fall into the tradi- shifting, while territories are more bounded. A
tional tension in interpretation theory, between territory
(post) structuralism, in which meaning lies is not a milieu, not even an additional milieu,
outside the self as a function of independent re- nor a rhythm or passage between milieus. The
lations, and hermeneutics, in which meaning territory is in fact an act that affects milieus and
lies inside the self in an ontological moment. rhythms, that “territorializes” them. The terri-
Paul Ricoeur dialectically overcomes this tory is the product of a territorialization of mi-
15
split, but Deleuze and Guattari will not settle lieus and rhythms. (314)
for a dialectical answer. Instead, the answer co-
mes as an almost Humean proto-phenomenol- A territory is the interrelation of many mi-
ogy. (Deleuze, after all, wrote on Hume early lieus. It is, in a sense, a stance taken on milieus.
16
in his life.) The self is nothing, quite literally, It is not our site, but our situation. Milieus are
apart from its habits; yet the self is not in any the meanings of objects, while the territory is
way reducible to the overlapping spaces cre- the expression that becomes possible through
ated by externalized meaning-structures in the the objects. Animals (and this plateau is full of
world. examples from the animal world) mark their
Place (to use a word not used by Deleuze territory using a variety of signs, including
and Guattari) is not just a choice taken within urine and excrement, odors, and sounds. The
the set of possibilities that a negotiated or specific objects used to sign these (the milieu)
claimed space allows. It is the interaction of may change (certainly in token, and likely also
milieus into a territory. This territory cannot be in type), but the territory itself remains the
mapped any more than the range of a bird can same over the change of milieu-objects, just as
be mapped. The range of the bird is just wher- one’s home may be populated with different
ever it goes. We can, after the fact, produce objects over time, while at the same time main-
conceptual grids which account for where the taining the home’s homeliness.
bird has been, and we can, as the result of At the same time, while territories are more
knowledge of repetition, have an idea of where stable, Deleuze and Guattari more often speak
the bird will go (there is habit, after all), but the of “territorialization,” “deterritorialization,”
map comes after, not before. Philosophy is not and “reterritorialization” than of territory by it-
reducible to biology; biology is always already self. Territory becomes an action, and just as
philosophical, and if it is so for the bird, it is all milieu markers may shift, so too can territory.
the more so for humans. Home (to use Macgregor Wise’s term) remains
The milieu, for Deleuze and Guattari, is not beyond the shift in markers, but it also changes.
17
a singular phenomenon. Our world is layered Home is a territory or place of comfort (I hesi-
by milieus of various sorts. We begin by mark- tate to use the word “space,” as Wise does, be-
19
ing our places, extending ourselves by the use cause of its problematic history), but it is by
of objects, language, gesture, and so forth. Our no means a static place.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
396
What is place? Deleuze and Guattari outline moves us in ways that visuality, and particu-
a “new classification system” to account for larly color, do not.
the “machine” that territorializes. This classifi- The refrain is a repetition, the song of the
cation system is one of different sorts of re- bird repeated, but not verbatim. Repetition
frains: necessarily contains difference,20 yet what is
1. Milieu refrains, which have at least two important is its resonance, the sympathetic vi-
parts, one of which answers the other; brations that occur in a territory that give it life.
2. Natal refrains, or refrains of the territory, The refrain is a catalyst, a to-and-fro move-
“where the part is related to the whole, to an ment. It “fabricates time” by its rhythm. “The
immense refrain of the earth.” These refrains refrain remains a formula evoking a character
mark the disjunction between the earth and the or landscape” (349). In other words, place is
territory (lullabies, drinking songs, hunting created through the repetitions in which we do
songs, work songs, military songs); not simply react to the interplay of meanings of
3. Folk and popular refrains, “tied to an im- the objects that create territory, but actively
mense song of the people, according to vari- voice a position in the midst of the
able relations of crowd individuations that si- overdetermination that territory affords.
multaneously bring into play affects and Wise characterizes the choice that the re-
nations (the Polish, German, Magyar, or Ro- frain allows as “habit.” Habit is the sort of repe-
manian, but also the Pathetic, Panicked, tition that admits variation (indeed, requires
Vengeful, etc.)”; it), but through which we are recognized for
4. Molecularized refrains—the sea and the who we are. Habit is not necessarily simply a
wind, which are tied to the Cosmic refrain; function of individual will—there are habits
5. Cosmic refrain. This final refrain should that are cultural, as well as individual. These
not be seen as transcendence. Perhaps the best habits, taken together, are who we are. There is
example of this is one which ends the plateau: no “core,” no essence of self apart from the
“In Schumann, a whole learned labor, at once habits we are. “There is no fixed self, only the
21
rythmic, harmonic, and melodic, has this sober habit of looking for one.” Yet, habits are not
and simple result: deterritorialize the refrain. just blind instincts. They are reflective conti-
Produce a deterritorialized refrain as the final nuities, the same produced differently, con-
end of music, release it in the Cosmos—that is tainers for a self that is nothing without them.
more important than building a new system” Jacob Boehme, the seventeenth century mys-
(350). tic, speaks of a will to “power, color, and vir-
22
These refrains are not particularly milieus, tue” that produces Gefassete, a German neol-
nor are they territories. They are the rope that ogism that combines Gefaß, a container, with
23
ties together sets of territories and milieus to- fassen, to grasp. The container is produced
gether. It is significant that the “refrain” is an from the inside, and exists as a temporary (one
auditory metaphor. Deleuze and Guattari con- might say, nomadic) representation of the self.
sider the visual metaphor, as used in visual art, To the extent that this container ossifies, what
and find it limited (347–48). The refrain is is contained is lost. It will move on, one way or
“eminently sonorous.” They argue that another. The question is, whether the succes-
visuality, and particularly color, tends to con- sive containers can keep up.
nect too closely to the territory with which it is The place is not, then, a home in a
identified or which it marks. Sound does not Heideggerian sense, one which we yearn for,
signify or communicate values, but rather it from which we are unheimlich. Our wandering
“invades us, impels us, drags us, transpierces is not the condition of being lost; rather, being
us. It takes leave of the earth, as much in order still is being lost. Wandering is our human con-
to drop us into a black hole as to open us up to a dition, and movement binds our territory to-
cosmos. It makes us want to die” (348). Sound gether in a way that remaining stationary can-

PLACE IN AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY


397
not. The bird that sings the refrain sings by ritory with a refrain engages in habit, but it is
habit, reacts to its environment but also asserts not the habit of the state institution. It is not
itself to create its environment. Its repetition about interiority. Its refrain is governed not by
produces its place, itself. instinct, but by the vagaries and contingencies
This suggests that any list of place-attrib- of what is outside; yet, there is repetition. The
utes will not succeed. We cannot identify nomad will have to deal with striated space,
“home” any more than the bird can map out in and indeed the nomad’s desert will be over-
advance its territory. It is constantly in the pro- taken by the State, but at the same time, the
cess of deterritorializing and reterritorializing. State will be overtaken by the desert.
This does not suggest that there is no home, but
simply that home cannot be rendered as either The Territory is not the Map
a nostalgic source or an eschatological or uto-
pian finality. We are, in the final analysis, homo Third question: Where is this place?
viator, but we cannot understand that in terms Deleuze and Guattari bring us to this place
of the garden from which we were banished, through the game of Go, the refrain, and the
nor the heaven for which we might yearn, nor idea of territory. All these offer us a way of
the desires of a subterranean subjectivity. thinking about the fundamental question of
While we may not be able to give a list of African philosophy, which is not the unan-
place attributes, we may nevertheless be able swerably metaphysical “What is African phi-
to recognize the disruptive force that we might losophy?” or worse yet, “Does African philos-
describe as home. The following example co- ophy exist?” but rather: “What is it to do
mes immediately after Deleuze and Guattari’s philosophy in this place?” Specifically, we
discussion of chess and Go: have the beginning of an answer to the ques-
Luc de Heunsch analyzes a Bantu myth that
tion, “what place are we in?”—or perhaps,
leads us to the same schema: Nkongolo, an in-
“what place can Africa philosophize from?”
digenous emperor and administrator of public Working out a notion of place that relies on
works, a man of the public and a man of the po- contingency avoids a notion of entitlement that
lice, gives his half-sisters to the hunter Mbidi, simply mirrors Western presumptions, and has
who assists him and then leaves. Mbidi’s son, a formed the basis of much African philosophy
man of secrecy, joins up with his father, only to to this point. African philosophy, like that of
return from the outside with that inconceivable any other place, is earned through reflection on
thing, an army. He kills Nkongolo and proceeds the concepts made available in the place that
to build a new State. “Between” the magical- creates an identity. These concepts should not
despotic State and the juridical State containing be thought as necessarily unique, tied to some
a military institution, we see the flash of the war notion of the uniqueness of consciousness, lan-
machine, arriving from without. (353) guage, history, tradition, social organization,
or so forth. This search for uniqueness, or the
The “magical-despotic” state (the original, “myth of purity,” is self defeating, in that the
traditional empire governed by Nkongolo) and purity will never be proven to the satisfaction
the juridical state containing a military institu- of those who are skeptical, and does not need to
tion (the new state produced by Mbidi) are di- be proven to those who are already committed
vided by a rupture, a “war machine,” an ele- to the idea that African philosophy is a coher-
ment of exteriority that does not work by the ent enterprise. So, instead of searching for pu-
internal rules of the state, but cannot be con- rity, or for an Ursache, or Ding-an-sich, it is
ceptualized. The war machine is doomed to fall more useful to think about the questions that
into the regularizing impulses of some state. It can arise when we consider the place we are in.
is the rupture that is the refrain, which is the If what has been said to this point is true,
smooth space of Go. The bird that marks its ter- that African philosophy should not look for the

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
398
space established by modernist maps to orient thinkers from around the world, and may ac-
itself (as this space is abstract, defensive, and count for the suspicion toward the lack of
always already looks to the areas on the map al- textual tradition that most people see within
ready claimed), and it should not look to place African history. If we need to legitimate the
as defined statically, a kind of “home” in a nos- concepts by finding their roots, by thinking
talgic or hopeful sense. “The map is not the ter- “arboreally,” to use a Deleuzian metaphor, we
ritory” suggests that the representation is not will naturally be concerned if those roots are
identical to that which it represents. Its inver- unavailable. African philosophy has found
sion, as has already been mentioned, suggests text-substitutes, or text-analogues, to make up
that territory, that which is earned by nomadic for this. So, collective oral tradition, sages, an
action within a set of milieus, cannot be repre- “African mind” or “African consciousness,” a
sented by a map. Maps, at least in their usual unique cultural or linguistic history have all
understanding, make the world abstract. The been used to substitute for the seeming lack of
abstract categories come first—lines of longi- textuality. This, though, just plays the space
tude and latitude, scales and conventions. Into game.
these abstractions the earth fits. The earth is This place, the set of nomadic vectors that
governed by the abstractions. The nomad, the describe this place, cannot easily be given in a
bird singing the refrain, the piece in Go, none list. The point is not to try to come up with a
of these are governed by abstractions. All these new description, as if we were going to try to
are irreducibly concrete, yet not as particulars. define the robin as a bird that has this territory.
Abstractions, then, become the carcasses (or But perhaps what is more useful is to think
perhaps more in the spirit of territory markers, about where the field has been, where it has as-
the excrement) of thought, not thought itself. serted its territory, deterritorialized and
Maps tell us who is in and who is out, who reterritorialized, and what kind of refrains
owns what and whose laws one must obey. emerge. I am not suggesting that we just need
Deleuze, if he has maps at all (and some writers to give an account of the battles engaged in and
do talk about maps in this context, but in a radi- the entitlements claimed. Thinking about phi-
cally different fashion, much closer to how I losophy in Africa needs to be more than giving
24
am talking about the notion of place), is not a history (and by implication a justification) of
concerned about ownership, but about ac- philosophy in Africa. History
counting for the ways in which concepts might is always written from the sedentary point of
emerge, and the way one might understand view and in the name of a unitary State appara-
one’s world given a set of contingent actions. tus, at least a possible one, even when the topic
In this, perhaps unexpectedly, Deleuze and is nomads. What is lacking is a Nomadology,
Guattari come close to Gadamer. While the opposite of a history. (23)
Gadamer’s notion of tradition would not carry
much weight for them, and there would be little History becomes another map, another way
sympathy for his lingering hints of transcen- of charting and defending space and determin-
dence, the idea of contingent understanding ing citizenship. Deleuze and Guattari’s point is
based on local conditions begins to look close that this preoccupation, if left as the sole task of
to Gadamer’s concerns. philosophy, actually stands against generating
So where is this place? When African phi- concepts that are the life-blood of philosophy.
losophy endeavors to set its concepts free into It should be noted that Deleuze and Guattari
the Cosmos, those concepts that emerge from never say that striated space (chess, arboreal
25
its milieus and defines its (temporary) terri- thought) ought to be forsaken or ignored, but
tory, it has for the most part started with the rather that smooth space (nomadology, go,
concepts and tried to find their origins. This is rhizomatic thought) needs to be present, or we
not so different than the impulse of many have lost what it is to do philosophy.

PLACE IN AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY


399
This African place from which we philoso- The second way in which place is relevant to
phize does not particularly need to establish a African thought is in the nature of thought it-
historical account of the conditions under self, as opposed to that which engenders it.
which philosophy takes place. Whether that is Philosophy generates concepts, it does not
a matter of arguing for the existence of philo- simply analyze them or uncover them. This is a
sophical texts in ancient or historical Africa, or fact usually forgotten not only by African phi-
arguing for the inclusion of patterns of thought losophy but philosophy anywhere. It is behind
available in non-western text-analogues (prov- the charges still made by some Western philos-
erbs, the wisdom of sages, the structure of lan- ophers, that African philosophy is simply
guage), in themselves these will remain am- warmed-over Western philosophy. It is also be-
biguous about the existence of philosophy hind the impulse to resist that argument by
identifying the uniquely African and uniquely
itself, because philosophy is not a point in his-
philosophical aspects within African philoso-
tory. To borrow a phrase, philosophy is as phi-
phy. Neither side generates new concepts, but
losophy does. This place, then, is not reducible
simply defends the stock of existing concepts.
to the points on the way. I n ne i t he r c a s e i s t he r e a ny r e a l
There are two senses in which place is rele-
deterritorialization and reterritorialization.
vant to African philosophy. First, it is relevant African philosophy becomes moribund if it
as a way of rethinking the object of reflection does not create concepts. Creation does not im-
in African circles. If we are not looking for a ply “ex nihilo” production, nor does it imply
fundamental source of thought, a static “place” that there are no lines of contact or influence
that is a site on an abstract map, but rather a re- outside of itself. It means that, like the nomad
gion created by refrains, the object of philoso- or the singing bird, there is a direct response to
phy changes. While passing attention has been the specificity of the place or region. Instead of
given to the dynamism of African thought, defining what these are, the next section sug-
most of the attention has been spent showing gests examples and directions of research.
the longstanding continuity and stability of tra-
dition. Ironically, the dynamism itself has been
made into a static object of investigation. In- To Dwell as a Poet or as an Assassin?
stead of supposing that a rooted, striated space
can guarantee the legitimacy of African philos- Paul Virilio’s question, quoted by Deleuze
ophy, my argument here has been that such a and Guattari, leads us to our final question:
search focuses not on philosophy itself, but on how do we clarify the concepts available at this
place? In other words, what might African phi-
its carcasses, or put even more crudely (but
losophy look like if it paid attention to the hab-
perhaps more accurately, in that the metaphor
its of those who in-habit? How might we dwell
of carcasses might suggest dualism), its excre-
as poets, making the milieu of thought avail-
ment. If this excrement was taken as a refrain, able to the Cosmos, rather than as assassins,
an incremental (nomadic) marker of territory, “bombard(ing) the existing people with mo-
we might be able to see the dynamism. The lecular populations that are forever closing all
State-apparatus always has to try to subsume of the assemblages, hurling them into an ever
the nomad, but in fact can never completely ac- wider and deeper black hole” (345). The assas-
complish this. Unfortunately, the excrement is sin produces concepts and strategies of train-
usually taken as an end in itself, and we end up ing, control, and ultimately annihilation of the
thinking that African philosophy is a matter of people, while the poet produces concepts that
interiority, like chess, like the State. Interiority bring forth (in a phrase reminiscent of Nietz-
must cede to exteriority; excrement must cede sche) “the people yet to come,” the people who
to increment. can navigate their shifting territory.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
400
The argument I have made to this point has 3. The habits that are the milieu, or the pro-
tried to focus on the disruptive, nomadic nature cess of deterritorializing and reterritorializing,
of African philosophy. I have not given an ac- must command more attention. This would
count that has a teleology—we are not at the suggest a new theory of tradition, one that does
point of having “won” a space on a map, and not rely on identification and recovery, but
can now go about writing the kind of history rather on recognizing the habits that have lived
that victors write. If we take seriously this no- on. In this sense Gyekye’s admonition that tra-
tion that philosophy reflecting on Africa must dition is adopted by the daughter generation
be about exteriority rather than interiority, how rather than handed down by the parent genera-
29
does this affect the kinds of projects worth do- tion is apt. While he continues to try to
ing? essentialize tradition, at least he has recog-
1. For one thing, the search for the “African nized that dealing with the current ways that
identity” or the “African concept of the per- we “mark our territory” is the entry point to Af-
son” would become a dead end. Didier rican philosophy that can treat Africans as per-
Kaphagawani, in a posthumously published sons rather than as cultural or anthropological
essay critiquing some African concepts of the curiosities.
person, takes issue with trying to use 4. Boniface Abanuka gives an excellent ex-
communalism as a metaphysical guarantor of ample of how African experience can be
26
African personhood. Communalism, he ar- reterritorialized, in his discussion of ances-
30
gues, is a dynamic feature of the actions of Af- tors. Unlike Kwame Gyekye, who regards
ricans themselves, and is therefore talk of ancestors as an unnecessary and per-
not an ontologically stable entity. It is a collabo-
haps harmful conservative force in African so-
31
rative life-world which brings into sociation
ciety, Abanuka tries to see this as a kind of re-
forces, meanings, and agents of varying gender, frain that produces territory from chaos. He
age, and influence to construct their space, their does not take it in metaphysical terms (“do an-
habitus.27 cestors exist or not?”), but rather addresses the
question of how to deal with the exigencies of
Despite his use of “space” where it seems place life, not so that the individual slavishly follows
would be more appropriate (habitus is the the details of the ancestor’s example, but so
place we find ourselves in, not the space of that the individual can creatively deal with new
possibilities), his point is well taken, and could circumstances. The good things that come to
be extended. Personal identity is not about in- the community come through the creative ac-
teriority, nor is it about mapping the terrain in tions of individuals, and the example of the an-
such a way that the African “self” can be told cestors shows just what could be the case,
apart from other selves. Instead, the first task is rather than simply holding the individual to a
to identify the refrains Africans use to create rigid set of societal norms.
home, and to establish territory. Ancestors, then, do not simply hand down
2. Following on Kaphagawani’s question- rigid laws, and they are not simply a conserva-
ing of the communal as the basis for the Afri- tive force on society. Abanuka comes very
can sense of self, we might take the issue fur- close to Deleuze and Guattari’s argument by
ther: what place does the individual have in the recognizing the contingent and creative aspect
public realm in African society? Hannah of ancestors. Far from being retrogressive, he
Arendt argues that the polis is the model of the shows that the ancestors are a kind of refrain,
28
public realm. This suggests a specifically one that breaks apart and reconfigures itself,
Greek model for human interaction, which and contributes to the territory.
may well not apply to African life. What place 5. As has already been mentioned, the place
is established by collective action in (both tra- “Africa” is the answer to a set of questions.
ditional and modern) African society? These questions are worth raising. Mudimbe

PLACE IN AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY


401
has begun this task in his The Invention of Af- be to consciously pursue intercultural dialogue
rica and The Idea of Africa. But it is not enough between Africa and other traditions of philoso-
to just raise the questions, as if that will settle phy than the West.
for all time the perfidy of the West. Let us grant 8. Deterritorialization, in Deleuze and
that guilt, and then ask what refrain is now con- Guattari’s sense, is an ambiguous term. It can
tinuing to mark this territory? point to the positive aporias of thought, that
6. Gadamer’s concern for practical philoso- make new concepts possible. It can also refer
phy is suggestive for African philosophers. to the dangerous and violent affronts to
Most discussions of practicality in philosophy thought that are imposed by the outside. Afri-
have revolved around identifying the concep- can philosophy has been acutely aware of the
tual roots of perennial problems in Africa, and outside affronts—Fanon theorizes it well, and
proposing solutions. Again we might look to a host of other thinkers, quite rightly, have ar-
Gyekye’s Tradition and Modernity, particu- gued that not only the land but also the mind
larly his discussion of corruption. Odera Oruka must be decolonized. Less attention, though,
also has written a great deal about this. The has been paid to the positive aporias of
problem has been that practicality has been thought, the production of new concepts. My
conceptualized in terms of influence within a argument here has been against relying on the
technocratic bureaucracy. “If only we can negative, spatial logic to establish African phi-
make the concepts clear,” so the argument losophy, and the main reason has been that this
goes, “we might be able to effect social does not produce new concepts.
change.” But what if this isn’t true? How can 9. Following Deleuze and Guattari (and for
philosophy truly be practical in Africa? that matter, Gadamer and Kierkegaard as
The refrain is not simply an account of the well), the relationship between repetition and
construction of existing territory, but also a difference could be explored more fully. In
way of creating new concepts that might have what ways are concepts repeated in different
an effect, that might “create a people” in the forms, in what ways is there consistency over
way an artist needs a people (346). This is a change? In African philosophy, the relative
new opportunity for philosophers, not to ex- lack of a textual tradition has meant that other
pertly wield yet another tool in a society that sources for thought have been explored, in-
has seen too much of tools, and of experts, but cluding oral tradition, the wisdom of the sages,
to create concepts that deterritorialize existing proverbs and sayings. These sources have al-
ways, and reterritorialize. Philosophers need ways been seen as second-best to a written tra-
to sing new refrains, not simply imagine new dition, at least as far as philosophy is con-
tools. cerned. But the Western written tradition itself
7. If philosophy reflects on the constant pro- can be seen as a set of repetitions, refrains that
cess of deterritorializing and reterritorializing, have produced new concepts. To use the tools
and if this happens as Deleuze and Guattari of recovery that the West has used may not be
suggest, when the milieus interact in various all that useful when dealing with a tradition
ways, it would be worth producing new config- that draws on other versions of the refrain,
urations to generate new concepts. The unspo- more overtly related to the auditory. Thus, at-
ken assumption of much African philosophy, tending to the kind of refrains that typify Afri-
even when it has tried to look inside itself, is can territories may yield new forms of access
that its milieu includes Western thought. This to those refrains. This is what is happening in
has limited the scope of questioning, and sage philosophy, although it has become en-
thereby limited the set of concepts available. crusted with Anglo-American philosophy. At
One relatively easy (although almost com- its best, it tries to imagine new ways of access
32
pletely ignored) way to break out of this would to new refrains.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
402
10. Theories of tradition and modernity History has always dismissed the nomads.
(and for that matter, postmodernity) abound, (394)
usually as map lines of demarcation between Success has been closely circumscribed by
preconceptual, unreflective, uncreative “Afri- Western standards—success in technology,
for instance, or in the stability of the State ap-
can” thought and truly conceptual, reflective,
paratus. But we philosophical nomads may
and creative “Western” thought. Nomadic find different ways of understanding success,
thought would turn this on its head. Deleuze not totally unrelated to these standards but also
and Guattari: not beholden to the historical accounts that
write out nomads, and Africa, by definition.
It is true that the nomads have no history; they
Kwame Gyekye, in Tradition and Modernity,
only have a geography. And the defeat of the no-
mads was such, so complete, that history is one
contributes to this rethinking by pointing out
with the triumph of States. We have witnessed,
the ways in which tradition and modernity are
as a result, a generalized critique dismissing the not so hermetically sealed, indeed the ways in
nomads as incapable of any innovation, whether which they continue to require each other to
technological or metallurgical, political or operate.
metaphysical. Historians . . . consider the no- These suggestions are by no means meant to
mads a pitiable segment of humanity that under- be exhaustive, but suggestive. Once the tools
stands nothing: not technology, to which it sup- are found to examine what it is to do philoso-
posedly remained indifferent; not agriculture, phy in this place, we may well be able to chart
not the cities and States it destroyed or con- (yes, even map) a new course, one that does not
quered. It is difficult to see, however, how the rely on abstractions, assertions, or defensive-
nomads could have triumphed in war if they did ness, but rather can work from the phenomena
33
not possess strong metallurgical capabilities. . . . and conversations that present themselves.

ENDNOTES

1. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Pla- 9. A sample of a few recent works would include Marc
teaus: Capitalism and Schizophreniz, trans. Brain Augé, Non-places: Introduction to an Anthropology
Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota of Supermodernity, trans. John Howe (London:
Press, 1988), p. 353. Henceforth references to this Verso, 1995); Robert Harbison, Thirteen Ways: The-
work will appear in the text in parentheses. oretical Investigations in Architecture (Cambridge:
2. Jorge Luis Borges, “Of Exactitude in Science,” in MIT Press, 1997); Lucy Lippard, The Lure of the Lo-
Borges, Collected Fictions (New York: Viking Press, cal: Senses of Place in a Multicentered Society (New
1998). York: The New Press, 1997); Jeffrey Malpas, Place
3. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, What is Philoso- and Experience: A Philosophical Topography (Cam-
phy? trans. Hugh tomlinson and Graham Burchell bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999); Jeffrey
(New York: Columbia University Press, 1994). Walsh, “The Value of Place Meaning: Practical Ap-
4. Ibid., pp. 87–88. plications for the Future.” Parks & Recreation 35
5. Ibid., p. 93. (August 2000): 42-51; David Seamon and Robert
6. Ibid. Mugerauer, Dwelling, Place and Environment: To-
7. John Rajchman, The Deleuze Connections (Cam- ward a Phenomenology of Person and World (New
bridge: MIT Press, 2000), p. 40. York: Columbia University Press, 1985).
8. Edward Casey, Getting Back Into Place 10. I have written about this question in connection with
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1993); The Derrida. See my “Debt and Duty: Kant, Derrida, and
Fate Of Place (Berkeley: University of California African Philosophy,” Janus Head (Winter 2001):
Press, 1997). 109–24.

PLACE IN AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY


403
11. It is worth noting that Deleuze and Guattari are only 16. Gilles Deleuze, Empirisme et subjectivité: Essai sur
one source for interrogating place in recent philoso- la nature humaine selon Hume (Paris: Press
phy. Casey, in chapter 12 (“Giving a Face to Place in universitaires de France, 1953).
the Present: Bachelard, Foucault, Deleuze and 17. An excellent discussion of this can be found in J.
Guattari, Derrida, Irigaray”) of The Fate Of Place, Macgregor Wise, “Home: Territory and Identity,”
gives a brief and by his own admission incomplete Cultural Studies 14 (2000): 295–310.
overview of recent scholarship on the issue. These 18. Ibid., p. 298.
19. Ibid., p. 300.
theorists do not produce a unified or coherent outline
20. Indeed, earlier, in 1968, Deleuze had written Differ-
of the concept, and that is probably all to the good, as
ence and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton (New York:
unity and coherence itself may be the virtue of spatial,
Columbia University Press, 1994), which extensively
not placial thinking. This is not to say that incoher-
addresses this very point.
ence and contradiction are now valued, but that at-
21. Wise, “Home,” p. 303.
tending to the particular places from which philoso- 22. Jacob Boehme, Mysterium Magnum 1:6–7.
phy emerges may require that we initially (and 23. Ibid. 1:4.
perhaps permanently) suspend the impulse to ratio- 24. Indeed, the introduction of A Thousand Plateaus dis-
nalize concepts before they can be used. Deleuze and cusses maps at some length. See pp. 12ff.
Guattari provide for this: they were inclined to think 25. “The two spaces in fact exist only in mixture: smooth
that people should use the concepts that emerge from space is constantly being translated, transversed into
their writing, rather than interpret them. That is my a striated space; striated space is constantly being re-
intention here. versed, returned to a smooth space” (A Thousand Pla-
12. One good portrayal of migrant-thought can be found teaus, p. 474)
in Vincenzo Vitiello’s description of Moses in the 26. Didier Kaphagawani, “Some African Conceptions of
desert. Vincenzo Vitiello, “Desert, Ethos, Abandon- Person: A Critique,” in Ivan Karp and D. A. Masolo,
ment: Towards a Topology of the Religious,” in eds., African Philosophy as Cultural Inquiry
Jacques Derrida and Gianni Vattimo, Religion (Stan- (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press,
ford: Stanford University Press, 1996), pp. 136–69. 2000), pp. 66–79.
27. Ibid., p. 77.
Vitiello describes Moses as a stranger to all lands, one
28. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (New York,
whose home is in the desert, and thus has no home ( p.
Anchor Books, 1959), chapter 1: “The Public and the
139). As the opposite of home, the desert takes on all
Private Realm.”
the dangers and threats we would expect, and life ex-
29. Kwame Gyekye, Tradition and Modernity: Philo-
ists mainly for the promise of the future. This depic-
sophical Reflections on the African Experience (Ox-
tion is not of a nomad, but someone whose existence ford: Oxford University Press, 1997), p. 221
is oriented toward a goal, even if that goal is not yet 30. B. Abanuka, A New Essay on African Philosophy
known. God, then, becomes the guide in the absence, (Nsukka, Nigeria: Spiritan Publications, 1994).
for Vitiello. The nomad, on the other hand, has no re- 31. Gyekye, Tradition and Modernity, pp. 257–58.
course to transcendence, even that of a negative theol- 32. See my “Thinking Wisdom: The Hermeneutical Ba-
ogy. sis of Sage Philosophy,” African Philosophy 11(June
13. Casey, Getting Back Into Place, p. 304. 1998): 57–71.
14. Ibid., p. 307. 33. An earlier version of this essay was delivered at the
15. Paul Ricoeur, Interpretation Theory: Discourse and conference on “Africana Philosophy” at DePaul Uni-
the Surplus of Meaning (Fort Worth: University of versity in March 2000. That version will appear in
Texas Press, 1976). Philosophy Africana 5 (March 2002).

Augustana University College, Camrose, Alberta T4V 2R3, Canada

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
404

You might also like