You are on page 1of 27

Philosophy & Social Criticism http://psc.sagepub.

com/

The practices of theorists: Habermas and Foucault as public intellectuals


Thomas Biebricher Philosophy Social Criticism 2011 37: 709 originally published online 14 June 2011 DOI: 10.1177/0191453711400244 The online version of this article can be found at: http://psc.sagepub.com/content/37/6/709

Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com

Additional services and information for Philosophy & Social Criticism can be found at: Email Alerts: http://psc.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://psc.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Citations: http://psc.sagepub.com/content/37/6/709.refs.html

>> Version of Record - Jun 29, 2011 OnlineFirst Version of Record - Jun 14, 2011 What is This?

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Article
Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6) 709734 The Author(s) 2011 Reprints and permission: sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/0191453711400244 psc.sagepub.com

The practices of theorists: Habermas and Foucault as public intellectuals


Thomas Biebricher
Goethe-Universita t Frankfurt

Abstract
The scholarly works of Ju rgen Habermas and Michel Foucault have been subject to ongoing scrutiny for a number of decades. However, less attention has been given to their activities as public intellectuals and the relation between these and their philosophical and theoretical projects. Drawing on their own conceptualization of the role of the intellectual, the article aims to illuminate these issues by examining Habermas advocacy of a Core Europe and his defense of NATO bombardments in Kosovo in 1999 as well as Foucaults involvement with the Groupe dInformation des Prisons (GIP) and a wide variety of his interviews, op-ed articles, etc. In showing that the intellectuals views differ in important ways from those of the scholars but nevertheless inhabit a crucial position in the overall edifice of their oeuvres, the article concludes that the practices of theorists deserve more attention for a comprehensive and more nuanced account of their thought.

Keywords
Albert Camus, Europe, Michel Foucault, Ju rgen Habermas, , intellectual, Kosovo

Introduction
The scholarly works of both Habermas and Foucault have been subject to ongoing scrutiny for a number of decades. However, their activities as public intellectuals1 have received much less attention. Yet both thinkers have taken on this role. Foucault had been involved in numerous political and social causes ever since his return to France from Tunisia in 1970.2 Habermas, in contrast, has rarely lent his name to political

Corresponding author: t Frankfurt, Thomas Biebricher, Cluster of Excellence Formation of Normative Orders, Goethe-Universita Senckenberganlage 31, 60325 Frankfurt am Main, Germany. Email: Thomas.Biebricher@normativeorders.net

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

710

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

movements but continues to be a regular and influential contributor to the op-ed pages of German newspapers, and occasionally French and American, ones, where he offers astute political analyses, in which he does not shy away from taking sides.3 In this article I would like to examine these practices of two of the most influential contemporary public intellectuals. What interests me in particular is the relation between these practices and the respective theories of the intellectuals. In turn, I will explore whether the prima facie tensions that exist between the two can be accounted for with reference to Habermas and Foucaults respective understanding of the role of the intellectual. Although I will devote a significant part of this article to highlighting such tensions, my ultimate purpose is not to make an ad hominem argument that accuses Foucault and Habermas of failing to practise what they preach. Rather, I would like to treat their practical activities as an additional dimension of the respective oeuvres that has been under-appreciated and might prompt us to look at the works of both Foucault and Habermas in a different way.4 Specifically, it will serve as an antidote to the incessantly circulating cliche s of Foucault as the cynic of power whose self-defeating anti-humanism effectively undermines all emancipatory political action and thus inadvertently strengthens the status quo,5 and those of Habermas as the dreamer of universal reason and consensus who is out of touch with reality. Finally, there are two potential reservations regarding the task of this article that I would like to address immediately. First, there is the question whether political theory is well advised to focus on interviews, political activities and even more or less personal letters in its assessment of a particular thinker. While I have my own reservations about an overly biographical approach to political theory that will sift through the personal correspondence of a writer to find additional clues to his or her thought, I believe that such concerns do not apply to the material I intend to analyse in this article.6 As intellectuals, both Habermas and Foucault are self-chosen public figures; the activities, writings and interviews I will make reference to are all published by them or with their explicit permission, and neither of them has ever tried to keep any of these practices secret, as if they were part of a private sphere to be respected by commentators quite to the contrary. Therefore, I believe that it is perfectly legitimate to explore the relation between scholarly endeavors and activities as intellectuals, not the least because both are widely regarded not just as philosophers but as political philosophers. Second, raising the question of tensions between scholarly treatises and practices seems to presuppose a certain unity of an oeuvre in this case including the dimension of practices. This assumption is contentious, particularly, with respect to Foucault who has often stressed the discontinuities in his writings.7 However, while I concur with the view of Foucaults work as one of many diachronic shifts and displacements that seems to defy any internal unity, it is, once more, Foucault himself who has emphasized the intricate relation between his writings and his political activities: But if one is interested in doing historical work that has political meaning, utility and effectiveness, then this is possible only if one has some kind of involvement with the struggles taking place in the area in question (Foucault, 1980: 64). This is particularly obvious in the link between his work for the GIP (Groupe dInformation des Prisons) and Discipline and Punish. But it has been asserted by Foucault as a more general pattern that holds for much of his scholarly

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Biebricher

711

work: If I do the analyses I do, it is . . . because I have been involved in certain conflicts regarding medicine, psychiatry and the penal system (ibid.: 65). In the case of Habermas my approach appears even less problematic given the many substantive interrelations between his scholarly work and his op-ed activities as well as his occasional attempts to articulate the relation between scholar and intellectual with reference to himself, which also presupposes a minimal unity. Such a minimal unity, in my view, only amounts to the assumption that theories and practices are not entirely independent from one another and, thus, it is possible to increase our understanding of the one through the other. The article is structured as follows. As a preface to the core of my analysis I offer a brief discussion of Habermas and Foucaults views on the notion of the intellectual. I will then proceed to examine a number of cases of their public intellectualism. Of course, I can neither cover each and every op-ed piece by Habermas, nor all of the many resolutions signed by Foucault. With regard to the former, I will focus on two particularly controversial cases, namely his advocacy of the NATO bombardments during the Kosovo War in 1999 and his plea(s) for a European constitutional process that might necessitate a Core Europe acting as a transitory catalyst. My discussion of Foucault will place considerable emphasis on his role in the founding and operating of the GIP but also make reference to a fairly wide range of other reported activities, resolutions and interview statements. In the final section, I will draw together the findings and offer some concluding thoughts about the link between scholar and intellectual in the two cases examined as well as on the relation between theory and practice in general.

1 General vs. specific intellectual


Conveniently, both Habermas and Foucault have addressed the concept of the intellectual themselves in more or less detail. Therefore, their own considerations can serve as a starting point for a comparison of their activities as intellectuals. The concept of the intellectual is largely absent from Habermas thought until the 1980s, when he explicitly scrutinizes the history of intellectuals in Germany in a speech on Heinrich Heine, the German poet and satirist who ends up spending many years of his life in political exile in Paris (Habermas, 1987a). I will return to Habermas historical sketch once I have examined Foucaults differing conception of the intellectual. For the time being, let us consider Habermas view on what characterizes an intellectual. Just like Heinrich Heine in his political comments, the latter becomes active in the name of public interests, although she or he cannot claim any special expertise regarding the particular matter at hand. Paying respect to the specific logic of the political, economic, legal or aesthetic sphere in which the embattled topic is located, the intellectual intervenes as a relative dilettante, in order to widen the spectrum of topics and arguments considered and to keep the political communication open (Habermas, 1990: 97).8 It is only in passing that Habermas has referred to himself as an intellectual and quite unenthusiastically, one might add. He views the role of the public intellectual attributed to him as frequently irritating and a disturbance to his academic work (ibid.). There can be no doubt, though, that this concept of the public intellectual fits Habermas rather well. As such he particularly gained recognition beyond academic circles through his

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

712

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

involvement in the so-called Historians Controversy in the 1980s. Strictly speaking it was Habermas own op-ed piece in the German weekly newspaper Die Zeit, which triggered the whole debate, when he responded to another article by Ernst Nolte previously published in the Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung that had relativized the racial genocide of the Nazis as a response to the Bolshevik class genocide.9 At the time, many historians criticized Habermas involvement in a debate located in their domain as an illegitimate crossing of borders, but, as has been pointed out, such an amateurish engagement is exactly what Habermas considers to be the role of the intellectual. The purpose of the latter is to spark and enrich public debate and the very provocation inherent in the lack of formal competence is supposed to contribute to that task. In a way, the intellectual as envisioned by Habermas is no more than an informed citoyen, who explicitly rejects any claims to expertise and thus performatively shows the possibility and necessity of open and inclusive political discourse, not the least against the exclusionary strategies of experts (See Habermas 2009a). Ever since the Historians Controversy Habermas has used the op-ed pieces of newspapers at home and abroad to intervene in issues that range from the Kosovo War to the Holocaust Memorial and, more recently, to the fate of newspapers once they are controlled by finance investors or the fallout of the financial crisis and, particularly, the current sovereign debt crisis of some European countries that threatens to erode European unity and solidarity (see Habermas, 2007; 2010; 2011). The views he expressed have rarely gone unchallenged in the ensuing debates, but concrete positions aside, Habermas has rarely failed to accomplish the intellectuals most general goal, to provoke and trigger complex and controversial public debate. In Foucaults thought the concept of the intellectual reaches the height of its significance in the 1970s when he coins the term specific intellectual in juxtaposition to the general intellectual (see Foucault, 1980: 126).10 Foucault, as far as I know, has never explicitly attached the label of specific intellectual to himself, and, although some of his activities fit the description quite well, others, as I will show below, are far more congruent with the concept of the general intellectual. What is the specific intellectual?11 Foucault uses the negative foil of the general intellectual in the tradition of Voltaire, Emile Zola and Jean-Paul Sartre to clarify the features of the specific intellectual. The general intellectual speaks in the name of the universal, takes the side of humanity, reason, or truth and seeks to represent all those excluded from the circuits of public debate. The archetype of the general intellectual is the writer who exposes the secrets of power and reveals the truth behind ideological distortions and thus acts as a normative compass for the people (see ibid.: 1267). At times, Foucault sharply distinguishes his own work from that model although, as mentioned above, it is unclear whether Foucault wants to claim the label of specific intellectual for himself. The genealogist of the 1970s has no intentions of veiling the partisan character of his analyses but explicitly embeds his own work in societal power relations even to the degree of a problematization of intellectuals themselves as agents of this system of power (Foucault, 1977: 207). The specific intellectual lays no claim to a position representing the general interest and also abstains from advice regarding what is to be done: they [the masses] know perfectly well, without illusion; they know far better than he and they are certainly capable of expressing themselves (ibid.). The task of the specific intellectual is a different one. She

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Biebricher

713

or he provides localized, specific and thoroughly partisan knowledge related to the particular context she is immersed in professionally. In contrast to the writing lawyer who is the archetype of the general intellectual, the specific intellectuals blueprint is the savant or expert (Foucault, 1980: 128). Foucault sees the general intellectual in decline after the Second World War with the simultaneous rise of the specific intellectual. Still, what kind of knowledge can the latter provide? Foucaults elaborations are mostly clad in military metaphors. He refers to the task of the genealogical intellectual as to analyze the specificity of mechanisms of power, to locate the connections and extensions, to build little by little a strategic knowledge (ibid.: 145). The intellectual ought not to impose her or his analysis onto others, instead she or he is to provide instruments of analysis, to locate lines of weakness, strong points, positions where the instances of power have secured and implanted themselves, [in short (T.B.)] a topological survey of the battlefield (ibid.: 62). Due to the intellectuals intimate knowledge of a particular institution, technology or science he or she can offer strategic profiles of these fields but also, furthermore, historical accounts that detail the contingency of various systems of power, from which their transformability can be inferred: these things have been made, they can be unmade, as long as we know how it was they were made (Foucault, 1994c: 127).12 Unlike its organic counterpart in the descriptions of Antonio Gramsci, the specific intellectual is not aligned with a specific political project but lends her or his analyses to those who require them in their oppositional struggles. Taken to the extreme, the specific intellectual shows utter indifference to the subject positions from which resistance emerges, as long as there is resistance (see Foucault, 1994a: 108). Conversely, any identification of a normative framework by the intellectual the preferred action of the general intellectual is viewed as deeply problematic because of its normalizing and exclusionary effects: It is because of the need not to tie them down or immobilize them that there can be no question for me of trying to tell them what is to be done (Foucault, 1989: 284). How do these accounts relate to each other? It seems fairly obvious that Habermas concept of the intellectual and his own activities would have to be considered to be subsumable under Foucaults notion of the general intellectual. Habermas, at least seemingly, speaks as a citoyen who attempts to represent the common good possibly of humanity, and thus does everything that the specific intellectual tries to avoid. Furthermore, Foucaults specific intellectual fashioned after the expert is the complete opposite of Habermas dilettante who questions the demarcation lines between various realms and provokes through his or her very lack of expertise. Interestingly, though, Foucault himself has often stressed his relative lack of expertise in the various fields he has worked on such as medicine, penal institutions and history as a scientific discipline itself. Additionally, Foucaults self-description as someone whose role it is to raise questions in an effective, genuine way, and to raise them with the greatest possible rigor . . . to pose problems, to make them active, to display them in such a complexity that they can silence the prophets and lawgivers, all those who speak for others or to others (Foucault, 1989: 288) is strongly reminiscent of Habermas self-understanding as someone who tries to enrich and broaden a potentially impoverished public debate. This is also confirmed by Foucaults characterization of the intellectual as someone who tries to participate in the formation of a political will (where he has his role as citizen to play) (ibid.:

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

714

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

463). Thus, it already becomes apparent that the initial impression of a clear-cut dichotomy between the general intellectual Habermas and the specific intellectual Foucault is a simplistic model that is in need of qualification. Being familiar with Foucaults distinction of the two types of intellectuals and his implicit criticism of the general intellectual, Habermas, nonetheless, has repeatedly asserted the importance of the latter type for the German context. This assessment is based on Habermas reading of the history of the German intellectualism briefly hinted at above. In his speech on Heinrich Heine Habermas paints the picture of Germany as a belated nation (Plessner) with regard to intellectuals that stands in explicit contrast to France. While the latter predominantly applauded the activities of Voltaire, Zola and Sartre, the intellectuals were viewed with much greater suspicion in the German context of the Second Reich, where the intellectual was ridiculed as a political dilettante (Weber) or vilified as an enemy of the nation (Mann) (see Habermas, 1987a: 28). According to Habermas, it is only after the Second World War that Germany starts to embrace the notion of the intellectual in a more positive fashion. Still, even in the postwar context the status of intellectuals is far from unequivocal. Habermas refers to the fierce criticisms of intellectuals to be found in the works of Arnold Gehlen, Kurt Sontheimer and Helmut Schelsky, who coincide in their assessment of intellectuals as societal pathology. Therefore, Habermas concludes: We can be content if Sartres self-understanding of the general intellectual (Foucault) spreads around here (Habermas, 1990: 36).13 We can conclude from this that the respective positions on what it means to be an intellectual are not as diametrically opposed as it might seem initially. Habermas and Foucault both argue for the need to historicize the concept of the intellectual. While Foucault claims the adequacy or predominance of the specific intellectual in the French context after 1968, Habermas historical account of Germany as a belated nation of intellectuals lends some plausibility to the general intellectual as an acceptable model for this context at least for the time being. Now it is time to take a closer look at some of the concrete activities of the two intellectuals.

2 Habermasian politics, or, The impurity of becoming


As mentioned above, Habermas has been an extremely prolific and visible public intellectual with numerous op-ed pieces in German, French and American newspapers. Here, I will focus on only two cases that, in my view, highlight the complex relationship between Habermas theories and his practices as an intellectual. These are his support for the NATO bombardments of Belgrade in the Kosovo War in 1999 and his spirited advocacy of an integrated Europe based on a constitutional treaty up until the French and Dutch referenda.

2.1 Towards a future cosmopolitan condition legality and legitimacy in the Kosovo War
By 1999 it had become apparent that the Serbian government in Belgrade actively supported activities of ethnic cleansing in the Kosovo region carried out by Serbian

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Biebricher

715

militias. After an arduous process of negotiations NATO decided to resort to military action in order to stop what were considered to be crimes against humanity. In an unprecedented way NATO took action without a mandate by the UN Security Council, which was unable to reach a decision mostly due to Russian and Chinese resistance. The bombardments triggered intense controversies in many NATO countries. In Germany, the governments active support of the military action almost tore the governmental Green Party apart because of its long-standing pacifist tradition. In the midst of these events Habermas offered his reading of the situation in an op-ed piece published in the German weekly Die Zeit. Habermas argument examines the normative legitimacy of the NATO intervention. The particular angle he chooses emphasizes the goal of a more thorough juridification of the international arena along the lines of a cosmopolitan law envisioned in Kants Perpetual Peace in contrast to the law of nations that forms the basis of current international law. Habermas places the Kosovo conflict in the context of a process of ever-increasing enforcement potentials of human rights. So far, their effect has mostly been confined to declaratory appeals to a moral universalism and often enough they have thus remained an empty promise. Habermas wants to see this situation rectified through a codification of individual rights held by the members of an international citizenry, which could even be claimed against a particular state and would be enforceable by the international community. Given the frequency of domestic conflicts, in which governments more or less openly side with a warring faction and thus partake in crimes against humanity ranging from displacement of people and ethnic cleansing to full-scale genocide as has happened in Rwanda and Sudan, Habermas position commands some prima facie normative plausibility. Habermas views the Kosovo War as a crucial point of transition from the post-1648 law of nations to a truly cosmopolitan law that provides human rights with legal teeth through enforceability (Habermas, 1999: 8). To put it in stark terms, the international community either clings to a legalistic recognition of Serbian sovereignty and thus indirectly cements the status quo in international law with dire consequences for those persecuted and displaced, or it shuns the legal constraints and claims the moral legitimacy of an intervention that supposedly relieves the suffering of those subject to ethnic cleansing and, more generally, signifies a step towards a future cosmopolitan condition (Kant). But Habermas wants to soften the edges of this seemingly aporetic alternative by introducing the notion of emergency help, which can be found in German criminal law ( 34 StGB) and has equivalents in many other domestic legal orders. According to Habermas, democratic governments can resort to emergency help as an ultima ratio when all other options have been exhausted. Just like the citizen is entitled to defend her or his neighbor through the use of force in a concrete situation where recourse to courts and law enforcement agencies is not given, analogous interventions by countries should be covered by the notion of emergency help. However, Habermas attempt at a legal circumscription of the NATO intervention leads to immense difficulties and thus remains ultimately implausible.14 In domestic contexts the legality of emergency help is tied to certain preconditions derived in analogy to police law.15 The legal status of police actions and it is often claimed that the NATO intervention is just that on an international scale in domestic

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

716

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

contexts can be assessed according to three criteria: is the intervention suitable, necessary and appropriate. Taking a closer look at the first criterion of suitability already reveals the problems of Habermas argument.16 The question is whether the bombardments are likely to achieve the goal of the emergency help, i.e. stopping the killing and ethnic cleansing in Kosovo. The response reveals two important points. First, after a certain point the suitability of the bombardments can no longer be upheld, given the widely reported intensification of the ethnic cleansing after the beginning of the police action.17 Second, the paradoxical implications of the emergency help argument come to the fore, because the more determined the Serbian government is in pursuing its project of forced displacement the less justifiable is the intervention in legal terms (see Blanke, 2000: 513). Whether the police action is legal or not, is up to the alleged perpetrator. This shows that the emergency help argument cannot really shoulder the normative burden entailed in the justification of the bombardments, aside from the fact that even if the notion of emergency help had less problematic implications and were already fully acknowledged in the international arena, the decision whether the preconditions for a police action are given clearly has to be reserved for an independent (judicial) institution and cannot be made by the NATO states themselves (see Habermas, 1999: 5). This means that Habermas argument rests on the anticipation of a perceived future cosmopolitan condition (1999: 5) and willingly accepts an unavoidable temporary paternalism (ibid.: 6) to bring about this future state of affairs. Despite the caveats Habermas adds, namely that NATOs self-empowerment should not become the rule (1999: 6), his position amounts to a justification in close analogy to the Part B of Karl-Otto Apels version of Discourse Ethics. In this second part of his Discourse Ethics Apel had addressed the crucial question of how to establish the precondition for a generalized implementation of discourse ethical procedures, or, to be more precise, how to justify the actions necessary for their establishment. Is it legitimate to use force in order to bring about conditions that make the use of force unnecessary? To be sure, this is not an entirely new question for political philosophy. One finds different versions of it in many other works, e.g. in Max Webers discussion of the tension between an ethics of responsibility and an ethics of ultimate ends. Apels solution is to rest the justification of use of force or strategic action more generally on the agreement of the ideal communication community. Unfortunately, this highly speculative notion can easily degenerate into a fig leaf for hard-nosed the-ends-justify-the-means decision-making rationales, because what exactly the opinion of the ideal communication community is seems to lie in the eye of the beholder to a very large extent. Habermas has signaled awareness of the question to which Apels Part B responds without siding with the latter or offering any elaborate solutions of his own (see Habermas, 1992). In the case of the Kosovo War he appears to settle for a different version of Part B, because the normative status of the intervention supposedly hinges on the anticipated consent of a future world citizenry that could potentially provide a post-hoc justification. But of course, given the peculiar nature of political decisions and that events that come with unintended consequences abound and involve in the famous words of Don Rumsfeld unknowables of which we do not even know that we do not know them, their consent is far from guaranteed and Habermas construction appears hardly less speculative than Apels and is open to appropriation from all sides. Furthermore, it hardly deserves

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Biebricher

717

mentioning that in the case of withheld consent from the future world citizenry there would only be a very limited reversibility to the actions in question, mostly in the form of retribution, which comes with its own normative problems such as eligibility, retroactive application, etc. The fact that Habermas is willing to travel down this normatively troubling road where force is used illegally is noteworthy for a number of reasons, but before I ascertain these issues I want to examine another case of Habermas public intellectualism, which reveals a similar dilemma, namely his advocacy of a Core Europe as a potentially necessary step towards a more deeply and constitutionally integrated European Union.

2.2 Core Europe and the European Constitution


European integration has been an issue on Habermas agenda for a long time. Particularly the essays in his book The Postnational Constellation originally published in 1998 make a comprehensive case for a united Europe; still, it has to be added that Habermas assessments with regard to the chances of successful transition towards a constitutional democracy of Europe have grown ever more pessimistic culminating in some recent newspaper op-ed articles chiding particularly German elites for recklessly having abandoned the European project out of parochial national interests.18 The main reasons for Habermas advocacy can be found in his elaborations on a discursive theory of democracy in Between Facts and Norms and many other publications. Here, Habermas had emphasized the importance of deliberative processes that are ensured and specified through constitutional norms. One of the many theoretical accomplishments of that theory is a convincing case for the inextricable link between democracy and the rule of law in contrast to the many views that consider the relation to be a trade-off. But Habermas subsequently becomes aware that the project of a deliberative constitutional democracy on the national scale is increasingly anachronistic given the predominance of the postnational constellation, i.e. increasing interdependence and transnational economic integration. This conviction forms the base of his support for a strong European Union. The response to the postnational constellation can only be supra-national (democratic) decision-making. Under those circumstances processes that lie beyond the sovereign powers of individual nation-states could be brought under a regulatory regime, those affected by a political decision would more strongly coincide with those who have made the decision and through a harmonization or at least coordination of Europe-wide social standards the European welfare model could be saved from the erosive effects of a race to the bottom. It is easy to see now where Habermas enthusiasm for a European constitution comes from. If a necessary condition for functioning deliberative democracy is a constitution, as Habermas has argued ever since Between Facts and Norms, and the appropriate scale of democracy in the postnational constellation is the supranational one, the European constitution inhabits a crucial place in Habermas thought on democracy in the 21st century. Although support for the European Union is not in itself a controversial position, Habermas insistence on a constitution has attracted lots of criticism to which he has responded in countless speeches, articles and interviews (see Habermas, 1998; 2009b). However, the point I would like to focus on is a different one and easily the most contentious aspect of Habermas stance on Europe. On 31 May 2003 an article by

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

718

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

Habermas, signed by Derrida, four other European intellectuals and Richard Rorty, appeared in the Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung along with op-ed pieces of these authors in other European newspapers. The article addressed transatlantic relations in the wake of the Iraq War as well as the internal state of affairs of the European Union that displayed divisions between Don Rumsfelds infamous Old and New Europe (see Habermas and Derrida, 2005). From this assessment of the situation, which constituted a rare and somewhat unexpected case of collaboration between Habermas and Derrida, two issues emerged as the most controversial ones and were taken up over and over again in the ensuing debate.19 The first one, on which I will focus, is Habermas push for a group of core European nations (ibid.: 5) to lead the way toward a more deeply integrated union. Habermas refers to this avantgardist core of Europe, which happens to coincide largely with Rumsfelds Old Europe, as a locomotive (ibid.: 6) of European integration.20 Common security policy as well as common defense policy and a decreased veto power of individual member-states are supposed to generate a momentum that attracts others in the long run. Commentators from central and eastern Europe in particular were quick to disagree. Not only could Habermas caveat that taking a lead role does not mean excluding (Habermas and Derrida, 2005: 6) easily be discounted as a rhetorical fig leaf, the list of common traditions serving as a resource for a European identity listed in the piece also seemed to generalize the experience of Germany, France, the Benelux countries and maybe Italy, but hardly did justice to the experiences more common to central and eastern European countries. In European countries secularization is relatively developed (ibid.: 9) write Habermas and Derrida, but the role of religion in Polish society certainly does not conform to this judgment. And while the statement that Europeans have a relatively large amount of trust in the organizational and steering capacities of the state, while remaining skeptical toward the achievements of markets (ibid.) accurately tatisme and the German sentiment of Obrigkeitsstaatlichkeit, Italys captures French e political culture is already hard to square with it let alone the post-totalitarian societies of eastern Europe that tend to view the state with great suspicion. Thus, while Habermas portrayed Core Europe as a transitory and inclusive arrangement, the fact that European identity seemed to be reduced to a Core European identity lent credence to those who fear that this transitory Core Europe is nothing but a pragmatic-looking cloak for the hegemonic aspirations of Germany and France. Finally, and in connection to the peculiar characterization of European identity that seemed to exclude eastern European experiences at least to a certain extent,21 it was Core Europes position vis-a ` -vis the United States that triggered some heated debates in the aftermath of Habermas article. To accuse Habermas of outright anti-Americanism smacks of ignorance given his long-standing personal links to the United States and the great influence of American political and philosophical thought on his own work. Nevertheless, the main point of Habermas article was to claim that first signs of the birth of a European public sphere (Habermas and Derrida, 2005: 4) were showing when mass demonstrations against the Iraq War swept through European cities on 15 February 2003. The link between the unifying experience of demonstrations focused on one particular topic and the topic itself being that of protest against the US administration suggests that the Other against

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Biebricher

719

which Europe is to define itself could very well turn out to be the United States. This would explain the selective character of the list of European traditions presented by Habermas that may not accommodate eastern Europe but certainly highlights some differences between western Europe and the United States such as secularization, (welfare) statism, or the slightly technophobe awareness of the costs and dialectic of enlightenment. Habermas concern with regard to the role played by the current American administration22 in world affairs comes to the fore when he writes that Europe has to throw its weight on the scales to counterbalance the hegemonic unilateralism of the United States . . . to defend and promote a cosmopolitan order on the basis of international law (ibid.: 6 and 8). Many have doubted the feasibility of building Europe against the United States, not the least because so many of the very real transatlantic points of disagreement seem to hinge strongly on the administration in power. Has the election of Barack Obama in 2008 meant that the United States no longer serves as a bogeyman to frighten the Europeans into unity? Furthermore, as Umberto Eco was quick to point out, the United States may reorient itself towards the economically booming regions of Asia in the medium turn and it remains to be seen if Europe after all is not in much more need of the United States than the other way around (see Levy et al., 2005: 1420). Thus, it is not only problematic to pitch Core Europe against the United States for the sheer inaccuracy of such an account regarding common traditions and identities shared across the Atlantic, it is also problematic for very pragmatic reasons. Without delving further into the substantive issues at stake let us now turn to a more analytical assessment of Habermas stance on Core Europe and the Kosovo War.

2.3 How to get from A to B


How can the advocate of a moral universalism of inclusiveness condone a potentially exclusionary Core Europe and how can the champion of communicative action justify an illegal use of force against Serbia? This is a pointed formulation of the puzzle that Habermas interventions as public intellectual constitute. I would like to suggest that these interventions should not be seen as odd aberrations from an oeuvre characterized by unfaltering universalism and commitment to general consensus. This characterization in itself is rather a cliche often attached to Habermas due to his early but significantly relativized endorsement of the ideal speech situation. Instead, Habermas reflections as a public intellectual inhabit a definite position in his overall system of thought.23 The latter in its strictly scholarly aspects is impressive and some might even say unrivalled when it comes to sophisticated normative theorizing. Habermas has gone to great pains in order to identify procedures to justify norms, democratic arrangements, or other states of affairs. However, his scholarly works remain relatively silent when it comes to a discussion of the ways and means of bringing about these normatively desirable conditions, which is to say, the dynamic and genuinely political aspect of a normative critical theory receives much less attention in his writings.24 This void left by Habermas the philosopher is filled by Habermas the intellectual. This division of labor serves an important and systematic purpose in my view. As a philosopher addressing the classic question what is to be done, Habermas would be wide open to the charge of elitism. Furthermore, the choices involved in an assessment of a political strategy regarding the question how

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

720

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

to get from A to B, often involve glaring paradoxes and dilemmas that make it necessary to strike painful compromises and engage in wagers on the future and how things will eventually turn out. The philosopher is well advised not to get entangled in these issues too deeply. Her or his task might be considered the identification of desired states of affairs based on philosophical arguments. However, how to realize these conditions, what risks to take and what means to choose are matters that cannot be decided by philosophical fiat but ultimately only by the actors themselves. According to Habermas self-understanding and his distinction between the philosopher and the intellectual, only the latter is entitled to speak to these questions and contribute to the debate as a concerned citizen, whose voice is just one more in the cacophony of an anarchic public sphere (See Habermas 2009a). Let me briefly illustrate what I have in mind with reference to the Kosovo War, Core Europe and the European Constitution in general. It has already been shown above that the logic of Habermas argument regarding the NATO bombardments relies on the implicit assumption that, although being illegal at the time, the intervention would be retroactively justified by a world citizenry that has reached a cosmopolitan tradition. Above, I have already spelt out the various ways in which this assumption could very well turn out to be misguided: the world could never reach a cosmopolitan condition anyway, this could be due to the unforeseen consequences of this very intervention, or, even in a best-case scenario of an existing cosmopolitan condition, the citizenry could withhold its post hoc consent. In other words, Habermas taking sides leaves his position exposed to the repercussions of all kinds of things that could go wrong on the road from the law of nations to a truly cosmopolitan condition. The philosopher can argue convincingly for the normative desirability of the latter, but only the intellectual can enter the discussion relying on emphatically fallible and thus much more modest validity-claims than the ones the philosopher raises. Similarly, Habermas has provided persuasive and rich arguments in favor of a supranational European democracy. However, the path towards this desirable state of affairs is riddled with paradoxes, trade-offs and risky strategies. Core Europe may function in the way Habermas hopes it will. The initial cluster of more deeply integrated countries demonstrates the merits of such a close union and thus attracts more and more additional members. Still, there is a realistic chance that Core Europe ossifies into a more and more insulated union within the union, seals itself off against the new member-states out of protectionism or due to cultural disagreements and transforms itself into a small Europe under the hegemony of Germany and France. This would be an outcome that could not be further from what Habermas has in mind. In the light of this unpredictability the philosopher has to step aside for the intellectual to voice an opinion that may claim to be informed but explicitly rejects any claim to real expertise, philosophical or other. Finally, the same constellation can be highlighted with reference to the European constitutional process Habermas advocates. In the absence of an already functioning public sphere that, according to Habermas, will only eventually result from a common constitution, the process will be far from all-inclusive and in this sense imperfect. However, the alternative would be for a functioning and somewhat inclusive public sphere to emerge on its own, which Habermas for good reasons believes to be unrealistic. Thus, if there is

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Biebricher

721

to be any movement at all in the direction of a constitutional Europe, the standards of inclusiveness, equality of access, etc., so important to Habermas normative thought have to be violated. And while it must not be ruled out that the blind spots of the constitution due to lack of inclusiveness can be remedied over time given Habermas commitment to a living constitution that can be amended and reinterpreted indefinitely, it might just as well be the case that an initial elite succeeds in setting a constitutional agenda that prejudices future constitutional developments in a fundamental way and makes sufficient and equal access to public spheres, etc., unreachable. In sum, what Habermas public interventions discussed here share, is that they address what could be called the impurity of becoming, i.e. a world that lacks the perfection and purity that philosophical thought at times seems to presuppose. In the face of vicious cycles and Gordian knots the intellectual enters a wager and has to espouse actions that are morally, legally and politically questionable, hoping that the decision will somehow be redeemed in the future. The conclusions I draw from this with regard to the issues raised in the Introduction of this article are the following. Generally speaking, it seems obvious to me that public interventions like the ones discussed here deserve to be taken into account when assessing Habermas oeuvre as a whole. What they show is that the cliche of a hopelessly unrealistic theory of na ve altruism, consensus and reason does not do justice to Habermas thought. The latter turns out to be much more multifaceted as it embraces a more strategic and consequentialist reasoning.25 With respect to the relation between the scholarly theories and the political interventions, there is obviously some tension, but since the one mostly focuses on defining and justifying certain conditions, while the other is concerned with the dynamic that could lead to realizing these conditions, one could also view the relation as one of mutual complements that relies on a division of labor between philosopher and intellectual and the different validity-claims they can legitimately raise. After this examination of some of Habermas interventions as a public intellectual let us now turn to some of Foucaults activities.

3 Foucault hyperactivism, rights and communication 3.1 Foucault and Camus on an ethics of revolt
The first apparent tension between Foucaults scholarly texts and his activities as an intellectual refers to the very fact of his activism that could be considered utterly futile in the face of power regimes forming and transforming themselves seemingly unimpressed by individual or collective action aimed at what could be considered relative emancipation as described in books like Discipline and Punish. However, there is a long-standing controversy over the status of Foucaults gloomy depictions of the carceral society or other disturbing images. Early on, commentators well-versed in the hyperbolic style of Nietzsches genealogical narratives have pointed to the analogies between these and Foucaults genealogical writing of history, in which rhetoric and style play an equally important role. Thus, the gloomy descriptions are supposed to provoke an existential response on behalf of the readers who could be prompted to take action due to the alarmist scenarios found in Foucaults books (see Foucault, 1989: 144; Hoy,

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

722

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

1986). Nevertheless, others have pointed out that such catastrophic rhetoric could turn out to be a double-edged sword: What happens is that the more powerful the vision of some increasingly total system or logic . . . the more powerless the reader comes to feel (Jameson, 1984: 57). In other words, paralysis is just as likely an effect as activism is. To be sure, there is little to be found in Foucaults writings that would justify the hope for some form of grand emancipation or liberation. Societies without power are abstractions for Foucault and even in the light of the various revisions of Foucaults notion of power this means that there will always be government, subordination and even subjugation, although the forms will vary in important ways. So why resist? This has always been a difficult question to respond to for Foucault, who willingly forfeits recourse to a framework of universal norms that fuels Habermasian critique and, as mentioned, refuses to engage in millenarian hopes of the Great Reversal. Foucaults attitude is neatly summed up in the following well-known statement: My point is not that everything is bad, but that everything is dangerous, which is not exactly the same as bad. If everything is dangerous, then we always have something to do. So my position leads not to apathy but to a hyper- and pessimistic activism (Foucault, 1984: 343). Still, in my view, this does not fully answer the question why one would choose hyperactivism over apathy. Opting for hyperactivism in the absence of motivational resources like the ones just mentioned (universal norms, hope) places Foucaults attitude in an intriguing intellectual proximity to a figure who is rarely discussed in the context of poststructuralism. This figure is the French philosopher Albert Camus who is usually placed in the intellectual tradition of existentialism. It is obvious that Foucault and Camus are deeply at odds when it comes to important philosophical issues. Camus commitment to a subject that provides an absurd world with meaning out of itself, as it were, smacks of the humanism that Foucault attacks so relentlessly in The Order of Things. The rebel that Camus envisions struggles in affirmation of a common human bond, which would easily fall prey to Foucauldian criticism of an ahistorical essentialism. In short, I do not mean to attempt an assimilation of the two philosophical profiles and projects. Nevertheless, when it comes to Foucaults activist attitude there is a lot that is reminiscent of Camus famous interpretation of the Myth of Sisyphos. The latter figure, whose crime it was to outsmart Thanatos so humans would finally be spared the scourge of death, blends easily into Camus rebel (or the revolting individual, to choose a more literal and less corny translation of the respective book). What ties them together is an awareness and acceptance of the ultimate futility of their (oppositional) actions when considered from the point of view of an eschatological thinking that envisions some point of culmination in human history that would bring about fundamental emancipation, etc. Like the doctor Bernard Rieux in The Plague who fights death incessantly knowing all too well of the idle nature of his struggles, the smiling Sisyphos who rolls the rock up the hill and whoever else chooses to revolt do so without a glimmer of hope for redemption. Yet they continue to revolt in the broad sense of the term and choose activism over apathy. With regard to what could be called an ethic of revolt there are indeed surprising correspondences between Camus and Foucault. Both opt for a form of revolt in sharp contrast to the notion of revolution, which they view with deep suspicion. Foucaults reservations concerning the PCF and the Marxist concept of revolution are well

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Biebricher

723

documented (see Foucault, 1989: 223).26 Camus The Rebel is a response to the excesses of Stalinist communism that he sees rooted in a Hegelian apotheosis of history and the accompanying dream of a revolution as a fundamental transformation of societal life and human nature that is bound to descend into mass slaughters (see Camus, 1956: 24652, 288). Camus revolt/rebellion, instead, is oppositional action that knows its limitations and accordingly is tempered by moderation (ibid.: 294).27 Nevertheless, there is a determination to the individuals actions that can count as another similarity between Camus and Foucault. What distinguishes the rebel is the willingness to risk ones life in the act of revolting. Camus has emphasized this particularly with reference to the historical phenomenon of the so-called social revolutionaries in Czarist Russia who receive an overall positive interpretation in many of his plays, especially Les Justes. These fastidious assassins (ibid.: 164) as Camus calls them in The Rebel are willing to give their own lives in exchange for taking anothers. However, in contrast to the suicide bombers of today, they fiercely refuse to jeopardize the lives of non-combatants, when trying to assassinate generals or politically leading aristocrats.28 The fascination that this existential dimension of the revolt had on Foucault comes to the fore in the most obvious manner in the various discussions of the Iranian Revolution in 1979. This is, of course, a somewhat controversial chapter in his life as a journalist/intellectual. Be that as it may, Foucaults initial siding with the revolutionary movement certainly is due to the spirit of revolt he attributes to the uprising: The impulse by which a single individual, a group, a minority, or an entire people says I will no longer obey and throws the risk of their life in the face of an authority they consider unjust seems to me to be something irreducible, writes Foucault in an op-ed piece entitled Useless to Revolt?, which appeared in Le Monde in May 1979 (Foucault, 1994a: 449).29 Interestingly, Foucault chooses the term revolt over revolution throughout most of the article30 and, of course, eventually answers the rhetorical question of the title in the negative. Finally, there is a point of similarity that stands in close connection with the existential experience of a revolt just mentioned. It is a sense of solidarity that emerges out of the act of revolting. For Camus this is a key feature of the concept he develops in The Rebel. It is summed up most elegantly in his variation on Descartes Cogito, ergo sum: I rebel, therefore we exist (Camus, 1956: 22). The willingness to give ones life presupposes that there is something beyond the individuals existence worth dying for. The refusal to go along with unendurable conditions any longer affirms a common bond between human beings and creates a strong sense of human solidarity that Camus highlights once more with reference to the camaraderie celebrated by the social revolutionaries who choose execution over betraying those whom they consider their brothers and sisters. Now, it would seem that this somewhat flat humanism is something that Foucault could not concur with and it rarely finds any correspondence in Foucaults writings where this humanism is attacked most fiercely, especially in the Order of Things. However, examining once more what intrigued Foucault about the Iranian Revolution one cannot miss his fascination with the sense of community generated through the peoples movement (Foucault, 1988: 214) something that is also present during his stay in Tunisia where he supports groups of oppositional students and thus experiences what he considered a major politicization (see Eribon, 1991: 193). Foucault even refers to the collective will of the people he saw on display all over Iran, explicitly

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

724

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

acknowledging that, hitherto, he had taken the idea of a collective will to be just another political myth (Foucault, 1988: 215). In sum, there are some startling similarities between the humanist existentialist Camus and what could be called his Other in any number of philosophical controversies, that is, Foucault, when it comes to the question of revolt. I will return to this relationship in the conclusion but first let us complement these more general considerations with an examination of some of Foucaults more specific projects as an intellectual.

3.2 The GIP and beyond


During the tumultuous events of 1968 Foucault is in Tunisia. In his support of oppositional students he overcomes the speculative skepticism (Foucault, 1994a: 279) regarding political activism that had remained as a bitter taste in his mouth after his brief membership in the French Communist Party during the 1950s. Politically rejuvenated he returns to France in 196970 to teach at the newly founded university in Paris-Vincennes, which shortly turns into a hotbed of political activism with Foucault at the helm of many protests, etc. (see Eribon, 1991: 210). It is soon afterwards that he co-founds the Groupe dInformation des Prisons (GIP), which is of eminent importance for Foucault as a scholar31 but also as an intellectual, because of the popularity the group gains in French public discourse. The crucial position that the GIP has with respect to Foucaults visibility as an intellectual as well as the substantive goals of the group make it a perfect starting point for my discussion. What was the purpose of the GIP? At the most general level its aim was to inform the public about prison conditions and the penitentiary processes taking place in and outside the prisons.32 This was done with the explicit goal in mind to strengthen the position of the prisoners. The GIP did not mean to idealize criminals but it argued that prisoners were a marginalized population that suffered grave injuries far beyond what could be considered a just punishment. There are two aspects of this plea I will emphasize in the following and from which a more general profile of the politics of the intellectual Foucault will emerge. First of all, let us focus on the way Foucault, speaking for the GIP, expresses the wrongs that the prisoners have to endure. Commenting on a controversial trial taking place at the time, Foucault attacks the prison as an institution which is supposed to apply the law but which, in reality, suspends it: once through the prison gates, one is in the realm of the arbitrary, of threats, of blackmail, of blows (Foucault, 1994a: 419). Against this, the rights of prisoners have to be defended or claimed in the first place (ibid.: 420). What is surprising about this statement is that Foucault resorts to the vocabulary of law and rights. This invocation of legal devices stands in marked contrast to many aspects of his scholarly work. Foucaults reservations regarding law and rights are spread throughout his works in the 1970s, from the Nietzschean assumptions regarding the necessary injustice of any system of law in the early 1970s to the relative obsolescence of law vis-a ` -vis the rise of the norm or, to be more precise, the colonization of the former by the latter, that is affirmed over and over throughout lectures and writings (see Foucault, 1989: 197).33 Similarly, the significance of rights-claiming as a political strategy is seriously discounted in many statements, the most pointed of which can be found in the preface to Anti-Oedipus by Deleuze and Guattari: Do not demand of

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Biebricher

725

politics that it restore the rights of the individual (Foucault, 1994a: 109).34 Interestingly, the practice of rights-claiming lies at the center not only of Foucaults activities at the GIP but also of many other public interventions of the intellectual. It is almost tedious to list all of the many documented references to rights that need to be claimed, restored and respected. From the prisoners whose rights are defended by the GIP (see Eribon, 1991: 22437) to prisoners in Iran after the revolution who are to have every means of defense and every possible right (Foucault, 1994a: 441); from the general observation that against power one must always set inviolable laws and unrestricted rights (ibid.: 453) to the right to abortion that Foucault advocates as a member of the Information Group concerning Health (GIS) (ibid.: 425); from the human rights he sees as that which one confronts governments with (ibid.: 471) in reference to the situation after the military coup in Poland in 1981 to the absolute right to stand up and speak to those who hold power [and] this new right that of private individuals to effectively intervene in the sphere of international policy and strategy (ibid.: 475) invoked in the famous Boat People Resolution from 1981.35 The latter has become the object of shrewd analyses (Lemke, 2001; Keenan, 1987) that detect a subtle performative undermining of traditional rights in this resolution, which is to pave the way towards a new form of right Foucault had called for in a lecture from 1976, a form which must indeed be antidisciplinarian, but at the same time liberated from the principle of sovereignty (Foucault, 1980: 108).36 Whether Foucault only subscribes to a rights discourse for strategic reasons after all, rights-claiming is treated as a political strategy here anyway or genuinely relapses into the traditional notion of subjective (human) rights, it is undeniable that this practice is of the utmost importance for the activities of the intellectual and places him in a tension with his other scholarly persona that is hard to miss. It is all the more interesting that these activities and the form in which they take place, i.e. claiming rights and invoking the law, have gone rather unnoticed by the legions of commentators on Foucaults work. Before I draw any broader conclusions let me turn to the other major purpose of the activities of the GIP that point towards a more general aspect of Foucaults practices as an intellectual, which could raise some eyebrows of those more familiar with his scholarly work. First of all, I would like to briefly remind the reader of Foucaults reservations with respect to (public) communication. In the History of Sexuality, vol. 1, the productivity of power is illustrated at length through its ability to incite discourses over sexuality. Always hesitant to ascribe an emancipatory potential even to ambitious models of communication Foucault states with a fair amount of hyberbole: The more talking goes on, the more power there is (Foucault, 1989: 157) and suggests developing silence as a cultural ethos (Foucault, 1994b: 122). Still, while silence may appear as the prime strategy against a power that makes subjects speak (about themselves), it has never been unrivalled. In his thoughts on the polyvalence of discourses it becomes clear that reappropriating discourses and instilling them with new meaning is another equally as important strategy to be pursued (see Foucault, 1978: 1001). Nevertheless, one would be hard-pressed to find textual evidence in Foucaults scholarly work that not only refrains from condemning communication tout court but takes the additional step of advocating processes of (public) communication for their desirable effects, whatever their specific nature may be. Therefore, it is deeply intriguing to find the GIP and

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

726

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

Foucault pursuing this very strategy when it comes to supporting the prisoners and their rights. The GIP wanted to inform the public about the prison conditions and raise questions regarding penitentiary practices (see Foucault, 1994a: 394). Thus, the power of transparency and publicity as a device of oppositional practices is already implicitly affirmed. More specifically, the goal Foucault has in mind is that of creating a counter-discourse of prisoners and delinquents (Foucault, 1989: 76). The significance of this counter-discourse would lie in the ability to force the institutionalized networks of information to listen . . . and to confiscate, at least temporarily, the power to speak on prison conditions (ibid.: 79). This idea of a counter-discourse entails several aspects. First of all, it illustrates the view of the intellectual Foucault on public debate and the public sphere more generally. Obviously, he rejects any notion of censorship; quite to the contrary he argues for a multiplication of channels and relays of communication in order to enhance the amount of information available: Why do we suffer? From too little: from channels that are too narrow, skimpy, quasi-monopolistic, insufficient. ... Rather, we must multiply the paths and the possibility of comings and goings (ibid.: 305). Another episode in Foucaults life as an intellectual is strong testimony to these convictions. In 1973 he acts as a co-founder and consecutive contributor to the new daily paper Liberation. The mission statement of the paper, to enrich public discourse through new perspectives mostly from the left of the political spectrum coincides with the notion of an impoverished public sphere that is in need of additional channels to spread more information (see Eribon, 1991: 252). Furthermore, it is not the classic general intellectual speaking for someone else who is to serve as the subject of a counterdiscourse but rather the specific intellectuals to be found in the respective realms and institutions, e.g. the prisoners possibly even wardens and staff themselves (ibid.: 2278). This has already become clear in the quote mentioned above and it is further confirmed by the practice of distributing questionnaires to the prisoners so the responses could be published by the GIP to inform the public about prisoners needs and wants as they themselves conceived of them (ibid.). Moreover, Foucaults project of a Chronicle of the Workers Memory in Liberation, in which he planned to interview workers about their experiences in order to bring these memories into circulation, can be cited in this regard.37 In other words, it is the irreplaceable individuals themselves who acquire the power to speak and have their voices heard.38 Finally, what is the purpose of this communication aside from the revelatory scandalization of prison conditions and penitentiary practices? An important secondary effect to which Foucault refers repeatedly is the building of community and one might even say solidarity. In a discussion of the functions of film he emphasizes the importance of this medium in serving as a collective memory of experiences and enabling recognition of ones own life-events as part of an experience shared by others (see Foucault, 1989: 123). Sharing a collective experience is also emphasized as an important motivational factor for oppositional action with respect to the situation in Poland39 and, once more, with respect to the Iranian Revolution (see Foucault, 1988: 224). What are being built through the flow of public communication are oppositional identities that emerge in the course of the very act of opposition. As mentioned above, this notion of solidarity built on a common struggle plays a crucial role in Camus notion of revolt and thus signifies another important correspondence

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Biebricher

727

between the two thinkers stance on oppositional practices. However, as the similarities between Foucault and Camus have already been scrutinized above, in the following I would rather like to focus on the questions related to the issues raised in the Introduction. The tension between theory and practice has already become apparent. A relative dismissal of the significance of rights in the scholarly treatises is countered by frequent and explicit references to the practice of rights-claiming in Foucaults activities as an intellectual. Reservations regarding the emancipatory potential of (public) communication derived from Foucaults notion of discursive power stand against a commitment to an extended public sphere in which marginalized voices acquire the power to speak. It should be added, though, that an implicit appraisal of symmetrical and unrestrained relations of communication can already be attributed to some passages in Discipline and Punish as Jim Johnson has shown in a controversially discussed article (see Johnson, 1997). Nevertheless, it can hardly be denied that there remains a tension that, in contrast to Habermas case, cannot necessarily be mitigated with reference to a division of labor between scholar and intellectual. One possible preliminary conclusion from this constellation could be that it may prove beneficial to review the conventional interpretation if there is such a thing of Foucault as a critic of liberal thought and the latters emphasis on rights, public debate, etc. If our understanding of the intellectual Foucault informs our analyses of his scholarly works, we might be prompted to give more emphasis to aspects that have been marginalized so far and/or view these works in a completely different light altogether. In fact, I would argue that it is only possible to disregard these practices if one might entirely separate them from Foucaults work as a theorist, which is a position that seems hard to defend particularly with regard to Foucaults above-mentioned position that theory does not express, translate, or serve to apply practice: it is practice (Foucault, 1989: 75).

Conclusion
In this article I have attempted to examine the activities of Habermas and Foucault as public intellectuals. The guiding assumption in this undertaking has been that there exists a tension between the scholars and the intellectuals and their respective endeavors. My starting point has been the discussion of the concept of the intellectual offered by Habermas and Foucault themselves. From there I have proceeded to scrutinize two major intellectual interventions by Habermas, his advocacy of the NATO bombardments in the Kosovo War and his support for a constitutionally integrated Europe. In turn, I have taken a closer look at Foucaults role in the GIP and, then, elaborated on a couple of themes, particularly rights and public communication, which are of crucial importance not only for the GIP but other activities of Foucault as well. This account was prefaced by a brief discussion of some intriguing parallels regarding the ethics of revolt between Foucault and Camus. Let me briefly summarize the findings before I offer some concluding thoughts on the larger issues at stake here. Although it appeared initially that there was a neat dichotomy between the general intellectual Habermas and the specific intellectual Foucault, it turned out that this relation was more complex. Habermas may fit the category of the general intellectual fairly

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

728

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

well, but it is difficult to subsume Foucault under the label of the specific intellectual. Not only because Foucault never explicitly claimed the label of the specific intellectual for himself but, more importantly, because some of his actions and self-descriptions as intellectual fit the model of the general intellectual much better. This is at least curious, given that Foucault at times argues vehemently in favor of the specific intellectual. It has to be noted, as well, that both Habermas and Foucault lean towards a historicization of the concept of the intellectual. Thus, if one accepts Habermas point about Germany as a laggard when it comes to the acceptance of public intellectualism one can come to the conclusion that general and specific intellectuals need not be mutually exclusive but are more or less legitimate relative to a particular spatio-temporal context. With regard to the contention formulated in the Introduction, a tension between some aspects of the theories and the respective practices of Habermas and Foucault can be confirmed. There is no need to overstate these tensions. Still, a tension clearly exists, for example, between Habermas deontological commitments in Discourse Ethics and his consequentialism when it comes to a future cosmopolitan condition as well as Foucaults reservations about the significance of individual rights affirmed in many of his scholarly treatises and the pervasive reference to the importance of rights found in GIP documents and in many other pieces by the intellectual Foucault. This takes us to some concluding thoughts that point beyond the scope of this article. First of all, I would argue that the contested relation between Habermas and Foucault deserves some renewed attention from a perspective that does not focus exclusively on their scholarly works. Since an understanding of their activities as intellectuals offers us a more complex view of their overall oeuvres, this may also lead us to a different interpretation of the way these oeuvres relate to each other beyond a simple dichotomization. Furthermore, it is the link between Foucault and Camus, which has hardly received any attention at all so far, that I would highlight as an area that warrants further scrutiny. As has been shown, Foucaults hyperactivism as an intellectual shows surprising parallels to the existentialist ethos of the rebel endorsed by Camus. The latters rich thought on political violence and the ethics of revolt remains a largely untapped resource so far presumably due to the tides of intellectual fashion. In my opinion, it could serve to further illuminate the relation between Foucaults theories and practices, if nothing else. Finally, the most fundamental issue that the article has only implicitly addressed is the perennial question of the relation between theory and practice in general. Part of that question is an issue I have addressed in the Introduction, namely, to what extent it is important or even necessary to give at least some consideration to the practices of theorists when assessing their work. In my view, those practices are largely disregarded in the spirit of time-honored metaphysical dualisms, according to which practice is only the impure and deficient counterpart to the realm of pure thought. Legions of scholars analyse the books written by Habermas and Foucault, only very few concern themselves with their activities as intellectuals. But how important are theoretical differences in themselves aside from practice, or, in the pragmatist words of William James: Whenever a dispute is serious, we ought to be able to show some practical

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Biebricher

729

difference that must follow from one side or the others being right. . . . If no practical difference whatever can be traced, then the alternatives mean practically the same thing, and all dispute is idle (James, 1904). The first thing to be noted, then, is that the politics of Habermas and Foucault and for that matter Derrida and many others as well are often remarkably similar. Publicity, access to the circuits of public debate and individual rights are elements on which those writers practically speaking seem to be able to agree, all philosophical differences notwithstanding. I do not believe that purely philosophical differences in themselves are entirely insignificant, therefore I would not want to travel down the pragmatist road all the way. As commentators, however, we should examine the merit of philosophical controversies carefully when they make very minuscule difference in political practice especially to the extent that we regard thinkers like Foucault and Habermas as political philosophers. While their thought cannot and should not be reduced to the respective political implications, I find it equally impermissible simply to disregard the fact that Foucaults politics as an intellectual bear an almost eerie resemblance to some of the values Habermas liberal political thought espouses. Thus, I think it is of crucial importance to award some consideration to the practices of theorists, not only because there might be a tension between theory and practice but also because they will often serve to provide us with a more nuanced and comprehensive understanding of the overall oeuvres. Given that Habermas almost deliberately splits his intellectual personality into a scholar and an intellectual, in order to have the latter say and write things that the former is not entitled to, according to the very theories of the scholar, it would be imprudent to disregard that intellectual, who makes up an integral element of Habermas overall project. In Foucaults case the intricate albeit tension-laden link between theory and practice is even more apparent, as has been mentioned above. Thus, the proof of the theoretical pudding does not lie in practice, but its taste is enriched when practice is considered. Notes
The author would like to thank Andrew Rehfeld and Leslie Paul Thiele for helpful comments on earlier versions of this article. 1. For a discussion of the notion of the public intellectual see Alcoff (2002) and Gattone (2006). 2. One notable exception is the analysis of Foucaults controversial reports on the Iranian Revolution in Afory and Anderson (2005). 3. Habermas esteem as a public intellectual has been steadily growing in recent years. On the occasion of his 80th birthday in 2009 the newspaper Die Zeit referred to him as an intellectual superpower and most commentators would agree with Hockenos who regards him as Germanys public intellectual No.1. See Hockenos 2011. 4. For an example of such an integrative reading see the provocative intellectual history of Foucault by Eric Paras (2006) and the intellectual biography of Habermas by Specter (2010). 5. Along these lines, Habermas himself has referred to Foucault as a Young Conservative (1981: 13). 6. Of course, this is not to say that letters cannot contain such important clues. Machiavellis Letter to Vettori is just one of countless examples.

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

730

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

7. See, however, Foucault (1994a: 266) for an explicit reference to the links between various parts of his oeuvre. 8. All translations from German are mine. 9. See Eine Art Schadensabwicklung (1987b) where all of his contributions to the debate are compiled. 10. At times, though, Foucault seems to be perplexed by the sheer concept of the intellectual: The word intellectual is foreign to me. I have never encountered any intellectuals (1989: 302). However, at other times, he has embraced the label without any qualification or specification: I am an intellectual (1994a: 453). 11. See Pickett (1996) for a discussion of what he refers to as the new intellectual. 12. See also the following famous characterization: I dream of the intellectual destroyer of evidence and universalities, the one who, in the inertias and constraints of the present, locates and marks the weak points, the openings, the lines of power . . . (Foucault, 1989: 225). 13. See also Habermas comments on anti-intellectualism in western Germany against former GDR intellectuals after 1990 (Habermas, 1997: 139). 14. Note that the legal situation has been slightly altered since the United Nations adopted the principle of the responsibility to protect in 2009. 15. Habermas has confirmed this view with respect to the first Gulf War. See Habermas (1991: 24). In the following, I exclusively refer to the legal situation in Germany but I assume that most western legal orders have equivalents given the importance of the respective regulations for the rule of law. 16. Necessity of an action is given if there is no less intrusive alternative, and appropriateness refers to the balance between ends and means. 17. Even Habermas himself has considered this in passing, when he refers to military strikes, which were to serve as deterrents to stop him [Milosevic], but in the end only gave him a pretense to continue (1999: 3); see also Habermas (2006a: 279) where he addresses this issue more extensively without altering his position. 18. See The Divided West (2006b) for a compilation of Habermas op-ed pieces on Europe and Europe: The Faltering Project (2009b) for a compilation of Habermas op-ed pieces, essays and speeches on Europe. 19. See Levy et al. (2005) for a compilation of the many op-ed pieces written in response to the initial essay. 20. In the following years, Habermas has shied away from the contentious notion of core Europe and instead has referred to a politics of graduated integration. See Habermas 2009a, 78. 21. Note, however, that Habermas is far from oblivious to the particular experience of eastern and central European countries: And the Central and Eastern European countries, while certainly working hard for their admission into the EU, are nevertheless not yet ready to place limits on the sovereignty that they have so recently regained (Habermas and Derrida, 2005: 5). This is exactly the reason why a core Europe will have to move forward alone if it is not to be bogged down by the reservations of the new member-states. 22. Note that Habermas is not concerned with the American people as much as with the administration. The accusation of anti-Americanism thus seems far-fetched. 23. A similar albeit slightly different position lies at the center of Specter (2010). 24. See Biebricher (2007) for an elaboration of this claim with regard to deliberative democracy.

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Biebricher

731

25. One can even sense vaguely Schmittian undertones in Habermas argument about the need for Europe to define itself at least to some extent against another entity; for example, the United States. 26. Foucault was a reportedly unenthusiastic member of the French Communist Party from 1950 to 1953 when the Stalinist leanings of the party and a general disillusion with Marxism on Foucaults part prompted his leaving the party. See Eribon (1991: 5060) and Foucault (1994a: 24850). A brief intellectual liaison with Maoism at the beginning of the 1970s aside, Foucault kept a distance from French radical leftism. 27. Rebellion, at the same time that it suggests a nature common to all men, brings to light the measure and the limit which are the very principle of this nature (Camus, 1956: 294). 28. The rebel has only one way of reconciling himself with his act of murder if he allows himself to be led into performing it: to accept his own death and sacrifice. He kills and dies so that it shall be clear that murder is impossible (Camus, 1956: 282). The restrictions of space do not permit me to problematize this normatively questionable ethic. 29. More bluntly, Foucault also refers to the masses that face the machine guns bare-chested (Foucault, 1988: 217). Foucaults stance on the legitimacy of political violence is somewhat difficult to infer. The terrorism of the 1970s is unacceptable to him as well as the Maoist fantasies of a violent overthrow of the established order. See Eribon (1991: 260 and 247). Still, the Iranian uprising that certainly involved violence at some point is not criticized by him at least not in the initial phase. 30. In another piece Foucault explicitly argues that the Iranian Revolution lacks all the defining features of a conventional revolution. See Foucault (1988: 213). 31. Foucaults lectures from 1971 to 1973 as well as Discipline and Punish focus on the penitentiary system; as mentioned in the Introduction, Foucault has explicitly affirmed the influence that the experience with the GIP had on his research during those years and beyond. See Foucault (1994a: 2445 and 458). 32. See Eribon (1991: 2245) for the complete founding statement. 33. See also Hunt (1992) and for a differing view Tadros (1998). 34. See also Foucault (1989: 339) and Foucault (1980: 106). 35. See also Foucaults elaboration on rights-claiming as a strategy for the gay movement in an interview called The Social Triumph of the Sexual Will (Foucault, 1994b: 15762). 36. See also Foucaults suggestion of a new relational right (Foucault, 1994b: 158) that is taken up in Golder and Fitzpatrick (2009). 37. Foucault, admittedly, ended up doing only one of these interviews and stopped working as a regular contributor altogether fairly soon after the paper had been launched. The reasons seem to lie both in the factionalism that ensued between the various editors and also in a general shortage of time on Foucaults behalf. See Eribon (1991: 2534). 38. In an interview with himself and Foucault Deleuze makes explicit reference to the attempt to give irreplaceable individuals a voice: It was on this basis that you organized the Group for Information on Prisons (GIP), the object being to create conditions that permit the prisoners themselves to speak (Foucault, 1989: 74). See also Pickett (1996: 4612) who emphasizes this aspect of Foucaultian resistance. 39. But in the behavior of the Poles there was an experience that can no longer be obliterated. What am I referring to? First, the consciousness they had of all being together. That is paramount. Thirty-five years of the previous regime had convinced them, finally, that the

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

732

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

invention of new social relations was impossible. In a state like that one, each individual can be consumed by the difficulties of his own existence. One is, in every sense of the word, occupied. This occupation is also the solitude, the dislocation of society. . . . So the Poles discovered something they knew but had never been able to bring fully into the light of day their shared hatred of the regime. That hatred was inside each one of them, to be sure, but now surfaced and was clearly formulated in words, discourses, and texts, and it was converted into the creation of something new and shared in common (Foucault, 1994a: 4678).

Bibliography
Afory, Janet and Anderson, Kevin B. (2005) Foucault and the Iranian Revolution: Gender and the Seductions of Islamism. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Alcoff, Linda M. (2002) Does the Public Intellectual have Intellectual Integrity?, Metaphilosophy 33: 52134. Biebricher, Thomas (2007) Habermas and Foucault: Deliberative Democracy and Strategic State Analysis, Contemporary Political Theory 6: 21845. Blanke, Thomas (2000) Der Philosoph im Handgemenge, in Stefan Mu ller-Doohm (ed.) Das Interesse der Vernunft. Ru ckblicke auf das Werk von Ju rgen Habermas seit Erkenntnis und Interesse. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, pp. 486521. Camus, Albert (1956) The Rebel: An Essay on Man in Revolt. New York: Vintage. Eribon, Didier (1991) Michel Foucault. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Foucault, Michel (1977) Intellectuals and Power, in Donald Bouchard (ed.) Language, Counter-Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews with Michel Foucault. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, pp. 20517. Foucault, Michel (1978) History of Sexuality, vol. 1, The Will to Knowledge, trans. R. Hurley. New York: Pantheon. Foucault, Michel (1980) Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 1972 1977, ed. Colin Gordon. New York: Pantheon. Foucault, Michel (1984) The Foucault Reader, ed. Paul Rabinow. New York: Vintage. Foucault, Michel (1988) Iran: The Spirit of a World without Spirit, in Lawrence D. Kritzman (ed.) Michel Foucault: Politics, Philosophy, Culture: Interviews and Other Writings. London: Routledge, pp. 21124. Foucault, Michel (1989) Foucault Live: Collected Interviews 19611984, ed. Sylvere Lotringer, trans. J. Johnston. New York: Semiotext(e). Foucault, Michel (1994a) Power: Essential Works of Foucault 19541984, ed. James Faubion. New York: New Press. Foucault, Michel (1994b) Ethics, Subjectivity and Truth: Essential Works of Foucault 19541984, ed. Paul Rabinow. New York: New Press. Foucault, Michel (1994c) Critical Theory / Intellectual History, in Michael Kelly (ed.) Critique and Power: Recasting the FoucaultHabermas Debate. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 10938. Golder, Ben and Peter Fitzpatrick (2009) Foucaults Law. New York: Routledge. Gattone, Charles F. (2006) The Social Scientist as Public Intellectual: Critical Reflections in a Changing World. Lanham, MD, Boulder, CO and New York: Rowman & Littlefield. Habermas, Ju rgen (1981) Modernity versus Postmodernity, New German Critique 22: 314. Habermas, Ju rgen (1987a) Heinrich Heine und die Rolle des Intellektuellen in Deutschland, in Ju rgen Habermas, Eine Art Schadensabwicklung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, pp. 2754.

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

Biebricher

733

Habermas, Ju rgen (1987b) Eine Art Schadensabwicklung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Habermas, Ju rgen (1990) Interview mit Hans Herbert Kru ger, in Ju rgen Habermas, Die nachholende Revolution. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, pp. 8298. Habermas, Ju rgen (1991) Vergangenheit als Zukunft. Das alte Deutschland im neuen Europa? Ein Gespra ch mit Michael Haller. Zurich: Pendo. Habermas, Ju rgen (1992) Morality and Ethical Life: Does Hegels Critique of Kant apply to Discourse Ethics?, in Ju rgen Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, trans. C. Lenhardt and S. Weber Nicholsen. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 195216. Habermas, Ju nen Rasen zersto rt. Lessing-Preis fu rgen (1997) Nu tzlicher Maulwurf, der den scho r Alexander Kluge, in Ju rgen Habermas, Vom sinnlichen Eindruck zum symbolischen Ausdruck. Philosophische Essays. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, pp. 13649. Habermas, Ju rgen (1998) Does Europe need a Constitution? Response to Dieter Grimm, in Ju rgen Habermas, Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 15564. Habermas, Ju t und Humanita t, Die Zeit, 29 April 2007, available in English rgen (1999) Bestialita online at: www.theglobalsite.ac.uk/press/011habermas.htm Habermas, Ju rgen (2006a) From Power Politics to Cosmopolitan Society, in Ju rgen Habermas, Time of Transitions. Cambridge: Polity Press, pp. 1930. Habermas, Ju rgen (2006b) The Divided West, ed. and trans. Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: Polity Press. Habermas, Ju rgen (2007) Keine Demokratie kann sich das leisten, Su ddeutsche Zeitung, 16 May 2007, available online at: www.sueddeutsche.de/kultur/artikel/455/114341/ Habermas, Ju rgen (2009a) An Avantgardistic Instinct for Relevances: The Role of the Intellectual and the European Cause, in Ju rgen Habermas, Europe: The Faltering Project. Cambridge: Polity Press, pp. 4958. Habermas, Ju rgen (2009b) Europe: The Faltering Project. Cambridge: Polity Press. Habermas, Ju rgen (2010) Wir brauchen Europa, Die Zeit, 25 May 2010. Habermas, Ju rgen (2011) Ein Pakt fu r oder gegen Europa, Su ddeutsche Zeitung, 7 April 2011. Habermas, Ju rgen and Derrida, Jacques (2005) February 15, or What binds Europeans together: Plea for a Common Foreign Policy, beginning in Core Europe, in Daniel Levy et al., eds (2005) Old Europe, New Europe, Core Europe: Transatlantic Relations after the Iraq War. London: Verso, pp. 313. Hockenos, Paul (2011) Germany public intellectual No.1, The European Voice, 14 April 2011. Available online at http://www.europeanvoice.com/article/imported/germany-s-public-intellectual-no-1/70830.aspx. Hoy, David C. (1986) Introduction, in David Hoy (ed.) Foucault: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 126. Hunt, Alan (1992) Foucaults Expulsion of Law: Toward a Retrieval, Law and Society 17: 138. James, William (1904) What Pragmatism means, available online at: www.marxists.org./reference/subject/philosophy/works/us/james.htm Jameson, Frederic (1984) Postmodernism, or, the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, New Left Review 146: 5393. Johnson, James (1997) Communication, Criticism, and the Postmodern Consensus, Political Theory 25: 55983. Keenan, Tom (1987) The Paradox of Knowledge and Power: Reading Foucault on a Bias, Political Theory 15: 537.

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

734

Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(6)

Lemke, Thomas (2001) Freiheit ist die Garantie der Freiheit Michel Foucault und die Menschenrechte, Vorga nge 40: 2706. Levy, Daniel et al., eds (2005) Old Europe, New Europe, Core Europe: Transatlantic Relations after the Iraq War. London: Verso. Paras, Eric (2006) Foucault 2.0. Beyond Power and Knowledge. New York: Other Press. Pickett, Brent (1996) Foucault and the Politics of Resistance, Polity 28: 44566. Specter, Matthew (2010) Habermas: An Intellectual Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Tadros, Victor (1998) Between Government and Discipline. The Law and Michel Foucault, in Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 18: 75103.

Downloaded from psc.sagepub.com at Copenhagen University Library on January 3, 2014

You might also like