You are on page 1of 3

MARTIN HEIDGGER

by Jonathan Ree
The German philosopher Martin Heidegger died nearly 40 years ago, but his work has
never stopped making the headlines: not because of his ideas, but because of his association
with Nazism. The latest stage of the controversy (well covered here and here by Jonathan
Derbyshire) has been occasioned by prepublication hype for an edition of the Schwarzen
Hefte, a 1000 page transcript of the little notebooks bound in black covers, in which he
jotted down observations for most of his life. According to the pre-publicity, these
notebooks show that Heidegger was a deep-dyed anti-Semite, and suggest that no selfrespecting thinker should touch him with a bargepole. I cant say that I agree.

1. In the first place, its common knowledge that, as well as being a member of the Nazi
party for many years, Heidegger was an anti-Semite. Not a violent one, but the sort of
cultural anti-Semite (DH Lawrence, TS Eliot, Ezra Pound) often found in the 1920s and
30s, not only in Germany but throughout Europe and America. For good measure, I guess
he was also a womaniser and a male chauvinist pig. The question is whether these facts are
a reason for avoiding his works, or whether we can in fact read him without putting our
political purity in danger.

I think that those who say that because he was anti-Semitic we should not read his
philosophy show a deep ignorance about the whole tradition of writing and reading
philosophy. The point about philosophy is not that it offers an anthology of opinions
congenial to us, which we can dip into to find illustrations of what you might call greeting
card sentiments. Philosophy is about learning to be aware of problems in your own thinking
where you might not have suspected them. It offers its readers an intellectual boot camp,
where every sentence is a challenge, to be negotiated with care. The greatest philosophers
may well be wrong: the point of recognising them as great is not to subordinate yourself to
them, but to challenge yourself to work out exactly where they go wrong.
2. In my opinion, Heideggers Being and Time, which was first published in 1927, deserves
to be read closely, openly, argumentatively, and often. It is a remarkable testimony to the
kind of uncompromising intellectual scrupulousness that philosophy ought to aspire to, and
as such it bears comparison with the finest works of, say, Spinoza, Kant, and Wittgenstein.
For myself, I would say that if I have managed to think any fresh thoughts in a lifetime of
philosophising, I owe it in large part to the time I have spent in the intellectual company of
Heidegger.

Its hard to extract a take-away message from Being and Time, but if I had to, I might offer
the following:

(a) It is an exploration of the ways in which every human life is lived in the light of
traditions passed down from earlier generations (especially traditions of language, poetry,
and thinking).
(b) It argues that a tradition is not something that we passively inherit, but something that
we must actively adopt and interpret for ourselves.
(c) It maintains that the biggest threat to our well-being is thoughtlessness, specifically the
thoughtlessness associated with modernity and metaphysics.
(d) One aspect of this thoughtlessness is that it makes us misunderstand our own historicity,
and to underestimate the ways in which our lives are moulded by the traditions we adopt.
3. As for the hullaballoo over the Schwarzen Hefte. In the first place it seems to me a
remarkable piece of publicity-seeking on the part of the publisher, who hints that we may at
last find the black heart of anti-Semitism that beats in every sentence Heidegger wrote.
That would of course be very gratifying to people who want an excuse for not taking
Heidegger 9seriously, but it seems to mefrom the few leaked passages I have seen, dating
from 1938-9that if Heidegger is on trial for vicious anti-Semitism, then the newly
published notebooks make a case for the defence rather than the prosecution.
One of the most striking things about them is that they show Heidegger explicitly
treating Faschismusand Bolschewismus as two sides of the same coin: namely the
imperious dehumanising movement of western modernity. Or as he puts it, echoing other
writings of his from the 30s, its about the ravages wreaked by modernity in the form
of Machenschaft (manipulative power, manipulative domination) Machenschaft being
Heideggers term for a peculiar form of power (cf Michel Foucault) that dominates not
through outward violence but through cunning infiltration and incorporation of the
powerless.

Heidegger also offers some suggestions about where Judaism fits in amongst other
traditions. These suggestions operate in a world quite at odds with the quantitative and
genealogical notions that drove Nazi racial legislation, which of course from Heideggers
point of view could only be seen as an expression of the impoverished culture
of Machenschaft. One of his arguments is that Judaism, like Bolshevism and Fascism,
participates in the corrosive calculative culture of modernity, even though it goes back
thousands of years. But his main point is that Judaism is structurally different from the kind
of nationalism that came into existence in the 19th century: the nationalism of the suffering
motherland as you might call itRussian or German nationalism, or for that matter Irish or
Scots or English or French. That strikes me as a reasonable piece of conceptual analysis,
and not intrinsically anti-Semitic.

If the Heidegger-bashers were hoping that the Schwarzen Hefte would expose the old
man in flagrante, indulging in some mindless Nazi rant, they are going to be disappointed.
The notebooks remind us that he was anti-Semitic, but they also remind us that he was antieverything-else, including fascism and every other facet of modernity. But above all they
remind us that however nasty he may have been, he never stopped thinkingrestlessly,
subversively, fearlessly thinking. Like the best of what Heidegger wroteindeed the best
of philosophy in general they are full of sharp observations: observations that we should
respond to not as opinions we might like to fall in with, but as incentives to think again, and
to think more thoughtfully.

You might also like