You are on page 1of 8

Emotion, Space and Society 10 (2014) 55e62

Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect

Emotion, Space and Society


journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/emospa

The potential of paying attention: Tripping and the ethics of affective


attentiveness
Maria Cichosz
University of Toronto, Canada

a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t

Article history: There is enormous power and ethical potential in the seemingly simple act of paying attention and
Received 27 December 2012 choosing what one pays attention to. Taking this power seriously, I explore the ethical value attunement,
Received in revised form or the state of paying attention, holds in relation to affect and its circulation. Because the affective texture
17 May 2013
of the everyday is not always directly accessible to experience, the ethical potential of becoming attuned
Accepted 24 May 2013
to this texture can be more effectively examined through a conceptual framework of a radically altered,
affectively-mediated state of consciousness: the trip. Conceptualizing tripping allegorically, as meaning
Keywords:
something other and more than what is literally said, I use this mode of experience as a framework to
Affect
Potential
think through the question of what ethical potential lies in practices of affective attentiveness. Exploring
Attention the connections between affect, attention, and tripping, I bring these concepts together in a close reading
Tripping of excerpts from David Foster Wallaces The Pale King and This is Water. Engaging with the work of a
Drugs writer who has always seen attention as an ethical imperative, I show that an indenite, shifting un-
Ethics derstanding of affect can have concrete ethical applications in day to day life.
2013 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

Consulting a dictionary yields no fewer than twelve denitions more broadly I think of the trip the way the eld of Addiction
for trip: a journey or excursion, especially for pleasure; an act of Studies considers drugs and addiction: not as contingent socio-
going to a place and returning; an exciting or stimulating experi- logical terms, but as conceptual and philosophical frames for
ence; a stumble or fall due to catching ones foot on something; a thinking about modes of being in culture (see Alexander and
mistake; and of course, a hallucinatory (or otherwise strange) Roberts, 2003; Redeld and Brodie, 2002).
experience caused by taking a psychedelic drug. While we usually There is enormous power and ethical potential in the seemingly
think of tripping as hallucinatory and tied to the consumption of simple act of paying attention and choosing what one pays atten-
narcotics, not all trips are hallucinatory and not all drugs are psy- tion to. Taking this power seriously, I explore the ethical value
chedelics, or even narcotics. Indeed, some trips require no drugs at attunement, or the state of paying attention, holds in relation to
all (or rather no drugs that we recognize as Controlled Substances) affect and its circulationdthat which is hidden in plain sight all
and are comprised entirely of intense, strange, disturbing, pro- around us. Because the affective texture of the everyday is not al-
found, and unexpected affectively-mediated psychic experiences ways directly accessible to experience (Massumi, 2002b: 33), the
that challenge our ideas about intoxication and sobriety, erasing ethical potential of becoming attuned to this texture can be more
clear dividing lines between the two. effectively examined through a conceptual framework of a radically
Moving tripping away from traditional, drug-centred deni- altered, affectively-mediated state of consciousness: in this case,
tions, I think of it more broadly, as a mode of being encompassing a the trip. Conceptualizing tripping allegorically, as meaning some-
wide spectrum of experiences. In other words, I consider tripping thing other and more than what is literally said, I use this mode of
metaphorically, not as separate from other forms of experience, experience as a framework to think through the question of what
such as reading, art, sport, or meditation, but as an affectively- ethical potential lies in practices of affective attentiveness. Out-
amplied part of a continuum of consciousness that can teach us lining my understanding of affect as undened, and thus different
something about how we relate to the world. In dening tripping from emotion, to explain why attentiveness constitutes a particu-
larly ethical stance towards affect, I examine how such an ethics
might look in practice in a close reading of excerpts from David
Foster Wallaces The Pale King and This is Water. Engaging with the
E-mail address: maria.cichosz@utoronto.ca. work of a writer who sees attention as an ethical imperative, I show

1755-4586/$ e see front matter 2013 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.emospa.2013.05.001
56 M. Cichosz / Emotion, Space and Society 10 (2014) 55e62

that an indenite, shifting understanding of affect can have con- outside of ordinary human experience, and primarily felt rather
crete ethical applications in day to day life. than understood, a trip is inherently unrepresentable, or always at
least partially inaccessible through the symbolic, or semiotic level
1. Affect as something of language. Following an extensive attempt to convey the feeling of
an LSD trip, Tom Wolfe gives up and writes:
As an interdisciplinary term of study, affect lacks a cultural-
But these are words, man! And you couldnt put it into words. The
theoretical vocabulary specic to itself. As such, it is often used as
White Smocks liked to put it into words, like hallucination and
a synonym for emotion, devoid of specic, contextualized meaning
dissociative phenomena [but.] The whole thing was.the
(Massumi, 2002b: 27). While scholars generally agree that affect
experience.this certain indescribable feeling.Indescribable,
encompasses the various capacities of bodies (whether animate or
because words can only jog the memory [emphasis in original].
inanimate, living or non-living) to affect and be affected, and refers
(Wolfe, 1968: 44e5)
to forces and intensities that are visceral, precede conscious
knowing, and insist beyond emotion (Gregg and Seigworth, 2010), Even Edgar Allan Poe, who declared that he never had a
many studies of affect take denite, clearly circumscribed emotions thought which [he] could not set down in words and did not
as their starting point. See, for instance, Sara Ahmeds The Cultural believe that any thought, properly so called, is out of the reach of
Politics of Emotion, where various socially-categorized emotions language found his opium dreams to be a class of fancies, of
such as hate, fear, disgust, shame, and love are taken as points of exquisite delicacy, which are not thoughts, and to which, as yet, [he
entry to explore how naming emotions involves different orien- has] found it absolutely impossible to adapt to language (Poe,
tations towards the objects they construct (Ahmed, 2004: 14). 1902: 88). Tripping shows us that undened intensities exist
Naming emotions is key in theoretical models that categorize and before becoming identiable as specic, socially-categorized
label affects so that they can be more effectively analysed. The emotions, and that these amorphous affects nonetheless shape
terms affect and emotion are used interchangeably, as synonyms, our world in very real ways.
with no clear distinction between the two. This lack (indeed, impossibility) of denition marks the trip as a
Consider, as a point of contrast, Kathleen Stewarts Ordinary space of openness and potential. Henri Michaux, who spent a great
Affects, where a careful distinction between affect and emotion is deal of time attempting to write about his mescaline trips, described
maintained by referring to forces and intensities only as something, tripping as being as if there was an opening, an opening like a
consistently refusing to give any feeling a determinate name or gathering together, like a world, where something can happen,
category. Stewarts understanding of affect encompasses impulses, many things can happen, where theres a whole lot, theres a swarm
sensations, expectations, daydreams, encounters, and habits of of possibilities, where everything tingles with possibility (quoted in
relating, [.] forms of persuasion, contagion and compulsion, [.] Plant, 1999: 146). Anything can happen during a trip, and trips
modes of attention, attachment, and agency (Stewart, 2007: 2)da routinely exceed the intentions with which they are undertaken.
variety of experiences that are not quite emotions and cannot be Openness of denition makes room for potential. Affectively
easily classied as such. Affects are not like emotions or any other speaking, this can be understood by looking at Deleuzian theories
formal structures that have been socially categorized, such as ide- of expression, in which expression is a movement from the force of
ologies, worldviews, or systemic beliefs, but more like Raymond that which is expressed, whether linguistic or extra-linguistic, to
Williams structures of feeling, which do not have to await de- content, the concrete form this expression takes, mediated by the
nition, classication, or rationalization before they exert palpable process of their passing into each other: in other words, an
pressures and set effective limits on experience and on action immanence.[a] gap between content and expression (Massumi,
(Williams, 1977: 132e133). This distinction between affects as un- 2002a: xviii). What happens in this gap is crucial, since the force
dened intensities and emotions as categorized feelings is impor- of expression has no concrete existence, only dynamic potential,
tant, as it is precisely amorphousness and a lack of denition that until it is captured by a content-expression articulation, as in a
opens affect to a form of ethical potentiality more denite un- net (xx). Coming to rest momentarily in a concrete object such as
derstandings of emotion foreclose. a body, expression becomes more denitely signied, allowing its
Tripping, an affectively-mediated experience, alerts us to this content to emerge, but also limiting its potential by restricting its
difference and its signicance. A trip is primarily felt rather than circulation. In other words, once expression stops its process of
understood, and imparts mainly affective, or sensuous knowl- immanent movement and becomes static, or captured without the
edgeda knowledge that is difcult to communicate in any coherent chance of renewal (as in a concrete denition), all dynamic po-
way, rendering itself largely non-narrativizable. Trips are like af- tential is lost.
fects in that they do not have to await denition to exert palpable Returning to Stewarts Ordinary Affects, it is easy to see how
pressure on those who undergo them. Deleuze and Guattari affects, knowable only as a vague something that is happening,
emphasize this affective dimension of tripping in their description make the world tentative, charged, overwhelming, and alive,
of the trips accompanying phenomena, such as hallucination, in rendering it a beginning dense with potential (Stewart, 2007:
which something one sees, hears, or realizes actually presuppose 128e9). Because nothing is dened, the potential for something
[s] an I feel at an even deeper level, which gives hallucinations their new to take place is enormous. Discussing Deleuzes model of
object (Deleuze and Guattari, 2004a: 20). A trip is an affectively- expression, Brian Massumi points out that the actual denition
based (I feel) event that exposes levels of meaning beyond those says too much in being born: it annuls the potential, bringing a
available in the realm of everyday experience, ones that do not current of expression to the end of the stream (Massumi, 2002a:
necessarily make analytical sense. xxxii). If denition turns formless affective expression into content,
It is difcult to name or dene precisely what occurs during a such as a discernible emotion, it is clear that dynamic potential
trip, where the body becomes the Body without Organs: a cannot exist in an affective model using denite emotions as its
connection of desires, conjunction of ows, continuum of in- starting point. Once captured in the content nets of specic emo-
tensities (2004b: 179). In tripping there are affective intensities tions, affects lose their capacity for movement and change.
that cannot be easily pinned down for analysis, momentary feelings This is not to say that emotions do not have any radical po-
that pass before they can be fully grasped as disparate emotions. tential, only that their potential functions differently than that of
Many writers have argued that as an occurrence that is strange, affects and their undened somethingness which is the focus of my
M. Cichosz / Emotion, Space and Society 10 (2014) 55e62 57

exploration. Feminist scholars have written about the mobilization conscious perception of it (Gregg and Seigworth, 2010), and not
of concretely dened outlaw emotions such as anger and something subject to any conscious effort, including the exertion of
bitterness and their political potential (Ahmed, 2004; Campbell, attention. There is certainly a gap, and this gap between expression
1994; Jaggar, 1989; Lorde, 1997). Similarly, feminist psychoana- and content poses a problem: how to pay attention to something
lysts such as Julia Kristeva have argued that affects (drives) can that has no denition, as of yet? To that which hardly exists, but is
only hold true potential after they have been actualized through nonetheless already there.
denition (Kristeva, 2002). Megan Boler argues that drawing dis- It is worthwhile to consider that though the potentiality
tinctions between affect and emotion can serve to re-gender inherent in affect may not be directly accessible to experience, it is
emotion within a binary framework and ignore the potential not exactly outside of conscious experience, either. Massumi
emotion holds for forming its own radical lines of ight (Boler, (2002b: 36) argues that while affect is amorphous, it cannot but be
2012). Not all understandings of affects potentiality are the perceived, alongside the perceptions that are its capture, such as
same, and I have chosen to focus on this particular conceptuali- emotions. Stewart makes a similar argument, claiming that the
zation of affects as lacking denition and containing immanent ordinary texture of the everyday registers perceptible intensities.
potential because it best facilitates my discussion of attentiveness Though eeting, such intensities can be seen, obtusely, in circuits
as an ethical practice, particularly within the context of Wallaces and failed relays, in jumpy moves and the layered textures of a
work. scene, sometimes even registering as a physical trace (Stewart,
2007: 4). Clearly, there are moments in daily life where it is
2. Why attentiveness? possible to register the movement of affects and their immanent
potential, even if it is in something small like a resonance or
What designates attention to affect and its ows as an ethical shudder, a shock or side perception, or any other fragment of
project? Of all possible stances one could take in relation an un- unfolding sensory experience that does not yet make sense in
derstanding of affect as lacking denition, in motion, and con- symbolic terms.
taining immanent potential, why is attentiveness particularly My notion of attentiveness, then, entails a mode of being that is
important? Further, if the existence of such potential is dependent less concerned with rational intentionality, which is only a step
upon affects remaining amorphous and undened, knowable only away from the desire to classify an undened impulse, and more
as a something that is happening, why is it worthwhile to pay concerned with living in a state of openness to all sorts of sensa-
attention to them at all? And how does a conscious act such as tions, even ones that cannot be immediately understood or do not
paying attention t into a model in which much that is affective is necessarily feel good to us. Rather than trying to know affects in a
also pre-subjective? way that pins them down as static objects of analysis, or
In short, attention to affect is implicated in ethics because attempting to catch such sensations at the very moment of their
thinking about affect is another way of thinking about potential, and incipience in some utopian effort to eliminate the preconscious
potential is a way of conceptualizing changednot only that which is gap (which would be impossible, anyway), attentiveness requires
possible, or which we can imagine happening, but also that which is us to simply be aware that something is happening, an undened
indeterminate and radically new. Change depends upon the something that may require a response from us, or not. This is not
fostering, tending to, and strategic actualization of the potential a utilitarian approach, as it does not contain the expectation that
found in affect. Massumi explains that an ethics of potential any given affective relay will contain some kind of insight, or
provide an opportunity for critique (which is another mode of
is a basically pragmatic question of how one contributes to the
dampening potential). It merely requires that we be effective
stretch of expression in the worlddor conversely prolongs its
conductors who can recapitulate and foster conditions of emer-
capture. This is a fundamentally creative problem. Where
gence, creating room for the new.
expression stretches, potential determinately emerges into
Attention and attunement are ethical modes of being towards
something new. [.] To tend to the stretch of expression, to
affect because they ensure we are both conscious of affects
foster and inect it rather than trying to own it, is to enter the
movement and in a position to foster the continuation of potential
stream, contributing to its probing: this is co-creative, an
immanent in this movement. The act of fostering this potential is a
aesthetic endeavour. It is also an ethical endeavour, since it is to
way of opening ourselves to change, whether personal or political.
ally oneself with change: for an ethics of emergence[, .] an
Paying attention to subtle, vague, or ordinary manifestations of
ethico-aesthetic paradigm. (2002a: xxii)
affect allows us to be conduits to affective ows without monop-
The individual is involved in this ethics of emergence to the olizing them through denition or categorization, only tending to
extent that they foster and afrm or capture and nullify the in- and furthering their stretch in an openness and commitment to the
tensity of affects potential. The paradigm is ethical because the potentiality of the everyday.
fostering of potential is necessary for change, and it is aesthetic in Stewart (2007: 127), who also suggests that close ethnographic
that it demands us to think creatively about how to foster this attention is a tting mode of approaching an undened and
potential. Potential moves from body to body as affect, and if it is emerging present, reminds us that the vague and unnished
not incarnated in an individual body capable of renewing it, it quality of the ordinary is not so much a deciency as a resource.
would cease to be expressed[,] it would dissipate, unperceived, While it is tempting to say that attention and its intentionality have
like the lightning ash you just missed seeing (xxix). On the most no place in affect, which is unpredictable and unquantiable, to do
basic level, the question of an ethics of potential is the question of so would be to leave aside the question of ethicsdindeed, to ignore
how well ones stance, attitude, and mode of being facilitate the a vast offering of immanent potential present in the most mundane
existence of potential, and thus the existence of change on a daily, recesses of the everyday. If we choose to leave ethics out of affect in
moment to moment level. And how better to foster the stretch of an effort to preserve it in some kind of pure, anti-intentional form,
expression without owning it or giving it any concrete form than we inevitably come to the conclusion that all that can be said about
by simply paying attention, and being aware of its movement? affect is that it happens, and attempt to describe how it happen-
But attentiveness and affect appear to be at odds. Affect, espe- sdboth of which are intellectually interesting, but neither of which
cially when understood as an ambiguous something, is generally is particularly ethical. Ethics requires honouring the impulse, no
thought to be a pre-subjective phenomenon that precedes ones matter how vague, that involves us as agents of change, and not
58 M. Cichosz / Emotion, Space and Society 10 (2014) 55e62

damping down potential before it has a chance to emerge, which is routinely does (Thompson, 1998: 84), is to become over-
tantamount to a refusal of the new. whelmeddindeed, possesseddby surprise.
Tripping, then, whether physically as over a curb, psychically as
3. Ethical attentiveness in practice on drugs, or metaphorically as in any intensied state of con-
sciousness, is a break in the repetition of the everydayda mistake,
How does an ethics of affective attentiveness look in practice? albeit a productive one. It is a moment in which a slippage in
Thinking of the trip conceptually, as a mode of experience capable repetition might, in Judith Butlers terms, ope[n] the way for an
of radically shifting ones attention in unforeseen ways, is helpful to inauguration of signifying possibilities that exceed those to which
understanding how attentiveness can be ethically productive on a the term has been previously bound (Butler, 1997: 94). Michaux
daily, moment to moment level. calls mescaline an accelerative, repetitive, agitating, accentuator,
Take, for instance, habit, the bodys best defense against the new. overthrower of all reverie, interrupter and a demonstration of the
Massumi (2002b: 11) identies habit as an acquired automatic self- discontinuous (quoted in Plant, 1999: 138). Tripping mandates an
regulation, one that encourages us to dampen affects potential by openness to surprise, and to sensations that are new, possessing the
disregarding the singular contours of the arriving impulse: dis- power to forcibly disrupt habits of inattention.
missing its potentially torturous anomalies as functionally insig- Habit, of course, is related to power and its increasingly com-
nicant (2002a: xxxi). In other words, the singular, unique affective plex, shifting mode of operation in a postmodern world. A radical
impulse that hits any given body as a force of expression becomes shift in ones practices of attention, such as that involved in trip-
disregarded through habit and its accompanying inattention, a lack ping, is ethically productive not only in disrupting habit, but also in
of attunedness that prompts us to carelessly or unconsciously offering us a concrete theory of how it is implicated in and foun-
choose the calming alternative of directing this potential-laden dational to powers ows in a way systemic explanations do not
impulse into something familiar, closed, and easily dened. account for. Stewart writes:
Habit and its predictability are fundamentally at odds with the
Models of thinking that slide over the live surface of difference
ethical project of fostering change precisely because habit requires a
at work in the ordinary to bottom-line arguments about bigger
commitment to inattention. Megan Boler argues that inscribed
structures and underlying causes obscure the ways in which a
habits of emotional inattention, the embedded, cultural habits of
reeling present is composed of heterogeneous and noncoherent
seeing and not seeing, are comfort zones of dominant cultural
singularities. (Stewart, 2007: 4)
values we inhabit unconsciously (Boler, 2004: 122). Such habits
involve a building up and solidication of certain desires resulting in In other words, totalizing shorthand terms like neoliberalism,
a limited capacity to attend to uncomfortable or difcult knowl- advanced capitalism, and globalization explain only macro-level,
edges and sensations, which are disregarded and consequently systemic aspects of power structures while ignoring the paradox-
dampened in their potentiality by shutting down any opening that ical fact that these larger systems, though they appear xed, con-
might have facilitated the existence of something new. Signicantly, crete, and immutable, are actually composed of vague sensations
Boler suggests that the most effective way of combatting such habits present in the everyday. Disregarding these undened intensities
of emotional inattention is through a pedagogy of discomfort, which that seem gone almost as soon as they are felt results in a view of
disrupts emotional habits and unquestioned attachments and en- power as something that has already happened, rather than as a
courages an often uncomfortable re-evaluation of ones unconscious number of immanent forces constantly assembling and reassem-
mode of relating to the world. Quoting Buddhist psychologist Mark bling, coming together. If one considers, as Stewart does, that the
Epstein, she argues that the more we bring our attachments into animate circuit of affective movements is the very contact zone
awareness, the freer we become, not because we eliminate the at- where the overdeterminations of circulations, events, conditions,
tachments, but because we learn to identify more with awareness technologies, and ows of power literally take place, and where
than with desire [my emphasis] (120). forms of power and meaning, very much like habits, become con-
Crucially, this is not an easy process, but one that mandates tained in singularities (2007: 3), then affect and its vagueness
disruption, discomfort, and a destabilization of all that is taken for actually have the potential to ll gaps left by totalizing structural
granted in ones daily reality. Breaking the complacency of habit explanatory mechanisms.
requires a major shift in attention and a new awareness of the par- Power, like affect, is a thing of the senses, irreducible to ideology,
ticulars of the materiality of the everyday, allowing these emergent structure, or any other concretely dened concept. Recognizing this
singularities to unsettle us and making their capture through un- and keeping ones senses in a state of affective attentiveness is an
conscious modes of classication difcult. I want to emphasize that I excellent (and thoroughly ethical) way of remaining attuned to its
see attentiveness here not in a grand, nebulous sense, but as rooted minute, moment to moment functioning without which the total-
in the ordinary, where small undulations of potential reside, hidden. ized systems that often become isolated objects of analysis could
Through an ethical attentiveness to the mundane, we see that the not exist. It is also a mode of sensing openings, moments of dif-
world is in a state of constant dynamic change, no matter how ference that involve us in change. Benjamin, having just taken
minute, and through this recognition it is possible to imagine how hashish, writes that waiting to feel the drugs effects is as if the
things might be different than they currently are. whole world was holding its breath: always the same worlddyet
If habit is the predictable and determined, the trip is the inde- one has patience (Benjamin, 2006: 100). Patience that something
terminate variation par excellenceda repetition with profound new will emerge if we pay attention closely enough. Patience
difference. Tripping facilitates a major shift in attention that allows culminating in a dull feeling of foreboding and uneasiness;
one to suddenly see things in a new, previously unconsidered way, something strange, ineluctable, is approaching (117)dthe affective
one antithetical to the entrenched nature of habit. Daily life, as force of expression that must be attended to, and fostered.
Michel Foucault knew, is comprised of a multiplicity of force re-
lations that are omnipresent, come from everywhere, and are 4. The terrible power of attention: affect, attentiveness, and
permanent, repetitious, inert, and self-reproducing (Foucault, tripping in Wallaces This is Water and The Pale King
1990: 92e93). To trip, on the other hand, whether by stumbling
over the curb on ones way to the streetcar or by nding oneself To concretely demonstrate these connections between affect,
suddenly in the grip of a serious Fear, as Hunter S. Thompson attention, and tripping as a conceptual framework, I turn to David
M. Cichosz / Emotion, Space and Society 10 (2014) 55e62 59

Foster Wallaces The Pale King and This is Water. Though it may thing about an academic education, at least in my own case, is
appear counterintuitive to look through a ctional text to under- that it enables my tendency to over-intellectualize stuff, to get
stand something about real world affective encounters, I contend lost in abstract thinking instead of simply paying attention to
that ction is not divorced from lived reality, but actually contains whats going on in front of me (46e48).
vast repositories of sociological, affective information different than
In other words, the work of shifting ones attention is not
those available through other modes of knowing.
necessarily rational. It is affective work easily endangered by over-
While certainly privileged, ethnography is not the only method
intellectualization or a slide into critique, that tempting mode of
we have for understanding the rich texture of the everyday. That
potential-dampening intellectual ownership. Further, it requires
we do not consider the ctive a legitimate source of information in
attention not to large overarching structures, but to the mundane
sociological contexts says more about our arbitrary distinctions
quality of boredom, frustration, and the grind of actual life routine,
between fact and ction than about the potential of literature,
day after week after month after year (73). It is an attentiveness to
which can address uid, difcult to pin down truths that might not
concrete materiality, the dullness of which contains what is so real
otherwise be available to us (see Gordon, 2008). Fiction deserves
and essential, so hidden in plain sight all around us (131)daffect
serious consideration, particularly when it comes to addressing
and its immanent potential, omnipresent yet hardly there.
affect, that elusive not yet formed thing. If one hopes, as I do, to
The Pale King is Wallaces nal and unnished novel, published
focus on relays not directly accessible to experience, then there are
posthumously in 2011. Very much like This is Water, it is a text
few more appropriate places to look than in a novel, that wonderful
thematically concerned with the terrible power of attention and
medium that asks us to slow down and pay attention as it eshes
what you pay attention to (Wallace, 2011: 91). It establishes this
out the intricacies of ordinary encounters in ways difcult to
focus through its subject matter: the United States Internal Revenue
replicate in real time.
Service (IRS), its employees, and its bureaucratic practices, the
Wallace is an American ction writer and essayist who, until the
functioning of which no one will pay attention to because no one
time of his death in 2008, had been much concerned with attention
will be interested, because, more or less a priori, of these issues
and its ethics in his work. This focus on attentiveness is present in
monumental dullness (84). Dullness and boredom are the sources
nearly all his texts, which foreground it thematically and ask the
of a psychic pain that is challenging because it fails to provide
reader to exercise it by engaging with the work in difcult,
distraction from a deeper pain, that of grappling with difcult truths
demanding, and sometimes painful ways. Perhaps no text centres
or uncomfortable knowledges present in daily life and necessary for
Wallaces concern with attention better than This is Water, a
breaking inscribed habits of inattention. Indeed, Wallace argues
commencement speech he delivered to the 2005 graduating class of
that there is great ethical potential in negotiating boredom as one
Kenyon College on a subject of his choosingdthe only such address
would a terrain, its levels and forests and endless wastes (85). In
he ever made. The speechs subtitle, Some Thoughts, Delivered on a
Wallaces novel, the IRS functions not as a symbol of bureaucracy or
Signicant Occasion, about Living a Compassionate Life, links its
tedium, but as an allegory for the difculty and ethical value of
main theme, critical awareness, or being conscious and aware
choosing to pay attention to what is hidden in the texture of the
enough to choose what you pay attention to (Wallace, 2009: 54), to
ordinary. As a novel that is not only about attention, but also de-
compassion, and thus to an ethical orientation towards the world. In
mands that readers attend to it through Wallaces signature textual
this speech Wallace argues for the value of the totally obvious (15),
strategies of long, unbroken sentences, extensive multi-page foot-
emphasizing that the most important realities in daily life are the
notes, and a non-linear story, The Pale King is an excellent text to
ones most difcult to see, describe, and pay attention to. For Wallace,
examine in relation to themes of attention and affect.
being attentive to the value of the obvious requires taking seriously
The excerpt I have chosen to discuss is one of several in which
that what is truly important is not so much the capacity to think, but
employees of the Service narrate how they came to work for the
rather the choice of what to think aboutdin other words, the choice
IRS. In this particular segment, Chris Fogle, an employee who has a
to make a move towards ethical attentiveness.
penchant for long-winded explanations that contain far more detail
Positioning attention as intimately connected with the totally
than most people might deem necessary, describes his decision to
obvious links it directly to habit. Wallace describes habit as
work as an accountant as part of a major shift in attention that
immensely limiting and fundamental to shoring up interior modes
occurred in his life after a number of closely connected events,
of selsh inattention:
including the matter of recreational drug abuse during this period,
Everything in my own immediate experience supports my deep and the relation of certain drugs to how [he] got [to the IRS] (177).
belief that I am the absolute center of the universe, the realest, Tripping as a radical mode of shifting attention is crucial within
most vivid and important person in existence. We rarely think Fogles narrative. He explains that the
about this sort of natural, basic self-centredness, because its so
ickers of deeper awareness, whether drug-induced or notdfor it
socially repulsive, but its pretty much the same for all of us,
is arguable how much that ultimately mattersdprobably had
deep down. It is our default setting, hardwired into our boards at
more of a direct effect on my life and directions change and my
birth (36e38).
entering the Service in 1979 than did my fathers accident, or
Attentiveness is an ethical effort because it requires us to do the possibly even more than the dramatic experience I underwent in
difcult work of getting free of this natural, hardwired default the Advanced Tax review class that I had sat in on by mistake (189).
setting, staying alert and attentive instead of becoming hypnotized
Fogles narrative shows how a trip, or intense affectively-
by the constant monologue in ones head. Not surprisingly, this is
mediated experience, in this case drug-induced (though this is
uncomfortable work, as challenging entrenched habits requires
more of a signpost than a requirement, as we will see), can be part of
inhabiting a more ambiguous and often unsettling sense of self,
learning to consciously shift attention by prompting one to do
such as that outlined by Bolers pedagogy of discomfort.
difcult, habit-altering workdin Fogles case, tedious work within
Signicantly, Wallace asks how much of this work of atten-
the IRS.
tiveness requires actual knowledge or intellect:
Recalling his college years, Fogle describes a time that now
The answer, not surprisingly, is that it depends what kind of seems as unfocussed to him as he was back then, fuzzy and abstract.
knowledge were talking about. Probably the most dangerous He explains that he not only had trouble paying attention to
60 M. Cichosz / Emotion, Space and Society 10 (2014) 55e62

anything going on outside his immediate sphere, but also did not settings, the very worship and centring of self that Wallace sees as
know how to focus his attention in any meaningful way, wasting antithetical to living ethically. This is
psychic energy on entrenched habits. There is pleasure in routine,
[.] the kind of worship you just gradually slip into, day after
and habits of inattention can masquerade as games. Stewart calls
day, getting more and more selective about what you see and
these sensory games: modes of supercial, banal attentiveness in
how you measure value without ever being fully aware that
which you can check yourself out of the ow of things while
thats what youre doing. (Wallace, 2009: 114)
remaining seemingly attuned (42). Fogle created a number of
sensory games in his youth, one of which involved counting the Such a centring of self is a way of refusing ethical potentiality
words in a text instead of actually reading them, as if these two and treating the everyday not a resource, but as a playground for
modes of attending were interchangeable. For example, Here ones own pleasure, thus siding with the ease and gratication of
came Old Yeller to save me from the hogs would equate to ten habit.
words which [he] would count off from one to ten instead of its Fogles shift in attentiveness came with Obetrolling, his radi-
being a sentence that made you love Old Yeller in the book even cally consciousness-shifting trip experience. Obetrolling is Fogles
more (160). He emphasizes that he did so almost unconsciously, name for taking Obetrol, a drug chemically related to Dexedrine
skimming over any potential for meaning in a practice of habitual and Ritalin, substances prescribed to increase the users awareness
inattentiveness. and focus. Unlike pot, which all but destroyed his ability to
In another sensory game, Fogle recalls smoking pot after high concentrate, Obetrol put Fogle in a state of doubling, or extreme
school classes, watching television and eating Tang out of the jar attentiveness that manifested as being intensely aware of seem-
with his nger until he looked down and could not believe how ingly mundane details, such as sitting upright in a dark green easy
much of it he had consumed. The activity was totally meaningless: chair with a cigarette burn on the right armrest, and the cigarette
Its like I was dead or asleep without even being aware of it, as in burn being black and imperfectly round. Doubling, as its name
the Wisconsin expression didnt know enough to lay down suggests, also involved a second level of awareness: noticing the
(Wallace, 2011: 158). This example is important, as it highlights the changes and being affected by them, and by the fact that [he] knew
framework of the trip as metaphorical rather than literaldhere [he] was noticing them. That [he] was aware of the awareness
Fogles pot smoking, though certainly drug-oriented, was not in any (2011: 183). Fogle explains that stated so openly, this amount of
way conducive to ethical attentiveness. Drugs are not inherently detail might seem tedious or insignicant, but was actually indis-
radical or liberatory, as is obvious here, where attention is not at all pensable to the process of emerging from the inattentive drift of his
shifted, but loosened and synced up with habit. Thinking of trip- life at that time. As though I was a machine, he says, that sud-
ping allegorically, as a conceptual framework, means emphasizing denly realized it was a human being that didnt have to just go
the psychic elements of a trip rather than its common sense link- through the motions it was programmed to perform over and over
ages with drugs per se. (182). As if he had awakened to the affective ow of moment to
As he aged and entered college, these sensory games became moment existence, and seen that in it lay the potential to disrupt
what Stewart (2007: 94) calls oating games: habitual modes of unconscious patterns.
taking pleasure in irony and critique for their own sake. Seeing A surprising number of things can be gleaned from attentive-
himself as a hip nonconformist, purposefully unfocussed and ness to ordinary surroundings. For instance, Fogles rst serious
nihilistic, Fogle took great pleasure in attempting to own and pin understanding that power is a thing of the senses, whose circuits,
down, rather than foster, undened potential. In his most elabo- and ones implication in them, are visible in singularities, such as a
rate oating game, Fogle and his equally nihilistic roommate dorm rooms walls. Having never studied his walls colour or
gathered at their dorm room window each evening, staring out at texture before, Fogle remarks that
a podiatric clinic with a rotating sign in the shape of a foot to
[i]t was kind of striking. Their texture was mostly smooth, but if
watch it nish its automated rotation at the end of the night. If the
you really focused your attention there were also a lot of the
sign stopped with the foot facing away from them, they would go
little embedded strings and clots which painters tend to leave
to library and study,
when theyre paid by the job and not the hour and thus have
but if it stopped with the foot or any signicant part of it facing motivation to hurry. If you really look at something, you can
[their] windows, [they] would take it as a sign (with the almost always tell what type of wage structure the person who
incredibly obvious double entendre) and immediately blow off made it was on (182).
any homework or supposed responsibility [they] had and
Seemingly insignicant details contain the minutiae of powers
instead go to the Hat, which at that time was the currently hip
operation, hidden everywhere in plain sight. For those attentive
UIC pub and place to hear bands, and would drink and play
enough to be aware of them, such details bring with them un-
quarters and tell all the other kids whose parents were paying
comfortable knowledge, the kind required to do the difcult work
their tuition about the ritual of the rotating foot in a way that
of breaking inscribed habits of inattention. Fogle notes that his
[they] all appeared nihilistically wastoid and hip (163).
awareness of belonging to an institution whose existence is
Here attention is channelled into banality, reected in Fogles dependent upon the labour of less privileged others he would not
admission that he can remember neither the name of the clinic nor normally consider is not necessarily pleasant, but it is real and
his roommate. important, and available to him in the affective texture of his very
Fogle certainly practiced forms of attention, but none that were room. It involves an uncomfortable decentering of self, and having
too heavy or sustained. His lack of attention to his affective in- to consciously feel and be aware of these inner reactions instead of
vestments during his youth and college years allowed habits of just having them operate in [him] without quite admitting them to
inattention to form and solidify, shaping his daily routines. He [him]self (184).
interpreted these pervasive modes of inattention as conscious Decentering oneself and questioning old habits during a trip
choices to play ironic games, or be part of a college scene he opens a space for new possibilities. For instance, listening to his
thought he was somehow above due to his self-perceived status as roommate trying to impress a girl on the phone while Obetrolling
a nonconformist. By allowing his attention to be unconsciously makes Fogle aware that not only does he feel contempt for the
pulled in this way, Fogle operated on his hard-wired default roommates effort to convey false hipness, but he is also
M. Cichosz / Emotion, Space and Society 10 (2014) 55e62 61

[.] uncomfortably aware of times that Ive also tried to project the analysis, but rather on its status as a powerful conceptual frame-
idea of myself as hip and cynical to impress someone, [.and] it work for thinking through (and experiencing, in Fogles case) what
makes me see similarities and realize things about myself that it means to allow ones conscious attentive and affective states to
embarrass me, but I dont know how to quit doing themdlike, if I radically shift.
quit trying to seem nihilistic, even just to myself, then what would The trip serves as an instruction manual, a conceptual tool that
happen, what would I be like? [emphasis in original] (184). can help us understand the openness and attentiveness necessary
to ethically orient ourselves as bodies willing to foster the stretch of
The answer is not clear, and the prospect of being other than one
affects potential. It is difcult to practice a mode of consciousness
is used to being is frightening, but even asking this question, rather
one nds alien, or jarring, without some sort of model for reference.
than unconsciously identifying with nihilism, is a major step for-
Obetrolling was important to Fogle not because drugs are necessary
ward for Fogle. Here tripping opens him to a mode of becoming
to attain states of affective attentiveness, but because without them
through attentiveness, and what he becomes exceeds anything he
his awareness of such states would have been nonexistent. I like
could have imagined.
now to think of the Obetrol and other subtypes of speed, he
Massumi argues that attention to the movements of affect and
explains,
its potential is nothing less than the perception of ones own vitality,
ones sense of aliveness, of changeability (often signied as as more of a kind of signpost or directional sign, pointing to
freedom) [emphasis in original] (Massumi, 2002b: 36). Further, what might be possible if I could become more aware and alive
the perception of this self-perception, its naming and making in daily life. In this sense, I think that abusing these drugs was a
conscious, is what allows affect to be effectively analysed (36), not valuable experience for me, as I was basically so feckless and
in a way that captures it, but in a way that fosters and afrms its unfocused during this period that I needed a very clear, blunt
potential through attentive modes of being. Signicantly, Fogle type of hint that there was much more to being an alive,
remarks that Obetrolling made him feel alive, like he owned him- responsible, autonomous adult than I had any idea at the time
self instead of just renting, and could nally direct his attention in (186).
meaningful ways. This involved discovering there were depths in
Crucially, Fogle does not continue Obetrolling to attain this daily
him and in his ordinary surroundings that exceeded
aliveness, but thinks of the experience allegorically, as meaning
[.] just the ordinary psychological impulses for pleasure and something other and more than literally consuming narcoticsdas a
vanity that [he] let drive [him]. That there were depths to [him] metaphor for what being attentive requires of us psychically. I think
that were not bullshit or childish but profound, and were not here of Benjamins profane illumination: a materialistic, anthro-
abstract but actually much realer than [his] clothes or self-image, pological inspiration, to which hashish, opium, or whatever else
and that blazed in an almost sacred wayd[.] and that these can give an introductory lesson (Benjamin, 2006: 132e3). Intro-
realest, most profound parts of [him] involved not drives or ap- ductory because the point is not to transcend daily life through
petites but simple attention, awareness, if only [he] could stay intoxication, but to use the experience of intoxication dialectically,
awake off speed (187). as a signpost from which we can learn something that might illu-
minate our day to day, profane existence in a totally new way.
Tapping into this vitality of daily life is an ethical act in and of
itself, and does not require that something practical, or utilitarian,
Indeed, Fogles major life-changing experience occurs not dur-
immediately come of this practice. It is not abstract, but grounded
ing one of his trips, but afterwards, when he accidentally stumbles
in the most innitesimal details of materiality, and involves moving
into an Advanced Tax lecture while searching for the location of one
away from selsh impulses and drives. Tripping and the extreme
of his nal exams. The lecture is understandably over his head,
changes in consciousness it mandates carry the potential for those
since he has not even nished Intro Accounting yet, but Fogle
who undergo them to form new sensory habits, such as watching
emphasizes the content of the lecture does not matter to him so
and waiting, learning to make a record of ones own ordinary
much as his awareness of its effects on himdan awareness he could
attention to things.
not have had without an attention to minute, unformed affective
ows. He allows himself to be open and attentive to this new
If only he could stay awake off speed. I solved the secret of the experience, one he might have previously disregarded, in his
universe last night, writes Arthur Koestler, but this morning I habitual cynicism, as unhip, because he has been so primed for
forgot what it was (quoted in Plant, 1999: 131). Anybody who has experiencing it this way, as [he]d already had a kind of foretaste or
ever taken a drug and tripped knows this feelingdthe frustration of temblor of just this experience shortly before through Obetrolling
trying to remember why that surreal, highly affective journey (Wallace, 2011: 220). Having been primed to practice ethical
seemed so profound at the time but now does not make much attunedness through tripping, Fogle goes on to live it in the most
sense. Part of the frustration of tripping is its stubbornly non- sober, mundane way possible: by becoming a Certied Public Ac-
narrativizable nature, which poses a distinct problem: how to countant for the IRS, where attention to the ordinary constitutes a
make anything productive out of an experience that is difcult to way of life.
make sense of, let alone remember? Fogle admits that when he Tripping inspires a something to be done, a longing for something
came down from the Obetrol he could barely recall any of the vivid moredthe desire and willingness to repeat potential-laden expe-
details he had been so intensely aware of, which now seemed rience in the future. Fitz Hugh Ludlow, one of the rst writers to
covered with a mental fuzz: record their experiences with hashish, was sure hed seen enough
wonder to last him a lifetime after his initial hashish trip. However,
The memory of the feeling of suddenly coming awake and being
with time he found that the memory of the wondrous glories
aware felt vague and diffuse, like something you think you see at
which [he] had beheld wooed [him] continually like an irresistible
the outer periphery of your vision but then cant see when you try
sorceress until he was forced to reconsider and decided to trip
to look directly at it. Or like a fragment of memory which youre not
again, and again, and again (Ludlow, 1857: 45). Michaux recorded a
sure whether it was real or part of a dream. (Wallace, 2011: 185)
similar feeling of restlessness that remained with him after eight
But whether he could remember or not is irrelevant, since the hours (that is to say a century), with mescaline. He could not stop
value of tripping does not depend on its recollection, or rational thinking, thinking, these variations, these variations of intensity, of
62 M. Cichosz / Emotion, Space and Society 10 (2014) 55e62

speed, these variations that hed experienced. They were some- through the circulation of affects immanent potential, the world is
thing so immense, unforgettable, unique, that [he] thought, that always qualitatively changing. Indeed, frameworks that point out
[he] did not stop thinking (quoted in Plant, 1999: 147). Obetrolling the importance of attentiveness involve us in this change on a
certainly got Chris Fogle thinking, and did not let him rest until he moment to moment basis in a way that is both impossibly simple
found his way into the obscure world of the IRS. and incredibly profound.
Tripping here is not about intoxication for its own sake, or even
about drugs. To trip is to be forcefully served with a reminder of
References
what ethical attentiveness looks like in practice. Because with-
drawing into habits and concerns of the self is a very real danger of Ahmed, Sara, 2004. The Cultural Politics of Emotion. Routledge, New York.
daily life, as Wallace takes such pains to explain, we all need such Alexander, Anna, Roberts, Mark S., 2003. High Culture: Reections on Addiction and
Modernity. SUNY P, Albany.
reminders from time to time. Tripping is a method, not an end in
Benjamin, Walter, 2006. In: Eiland, Howard (Ed.), On Hashish. The Belknap Press of
itself, and trips, as intense, unexpected affectively-mediated psy- Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
chic experiences, can take many forms: reading a really great book Boler, Megan, 2004. Teaching for hope: The ethics of shattering world views. In:
that forces one to slow down; meditating; running until awareness Liston, D., Garrison, J. (Eds.), Teaching, Learning and Loving: Reclaiming Passion
in Educational Practice. Routledge, New York, pp. 117e131.
is narrowed to such particulars as breathing, pace, and sound; Boler, Megan, 2012. Assembled Emotions and Mutant Affects: Towards a Semiotics
looking at a piece of art; or practicing a dwelling-in-place of of (Un)domesticated Feeling. University of Toronto, Dept. of Theory and Policy
making a conscious effort to watch, listen, and sense non-verbally Studies, Toronto. Circulated Draft.
Butler, Judith, 1997. The Psychic Life of Power: Theories in Subjection. Stanford
(Carbaugh, 1999). Though such experiences cannot be lived University Press, Stanford.
constantly, and are by their nature eeting, they have the power to Campbell, Sue, 1994. Being dismissed: The politics of emotional expression. Hypatia
open us to new possibilities and encourage us to form better habits 9 (3), 46e65.
Carbaugh, Donal, 1999. Just listen: Listening and landscape among the blackfeet.
of attentiveness. Western Journal of Communication 63 (3), 250e270.
Deleuze, Gilles, Guattari, Felix, 2004a. Anti-Oedipus. Continuum, London.
5. Attention as ethics in an inattentive world Deleuze, Gilles, Guattari, Felix, 2004b. A Thousand Plateaus. Continuum, London.
Foucault, Michel, 1990. The History of Sexuality. In: An Introduction, vol. 1. Vintage
Books, New York.
There are strong connections between affect, an ethics of Gordon, Avery, 2008. Ghostly Matters: Haunting and the Sociological Imagination.
attention, and the trip as a conceptual framework that can University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.
Gregg, Melissa, Seigworth, Gregory (Eds.), 2010. The Affect Theory Reader. Duke
demonstrate links between the two. While attentiveness may
University Press, Durham and London.
initially seem banal and not worth considering as an ethical stance, Jaggar, Alison M., 1989. Love and knowledge: Emotion in feminist epistemology.
it actually constitutes a concrete, practical orientation towards Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 32 (2), 151e176.
affect that can be practiced on a day to day, moment to moment Kristeva, Julia, 2002. Intimate Revolt: the Powers and Limits of Psychoanalysis (J.
Herman, Trans.). Columbia University Press, New York.
level, fostering potential on the same scale that power work- Lorde, Audre, 1997. The uses of anger. Womens Studies Quarterly 25 (1/2),
sdthrough the senses and how we allow (or dont allow) affect to 278e285.
relay through them. Ludlow, Fitz Hugh, 1857. The Hasheesh Eater: Being Passages from the Life of a
Pythagorean. Harper and Bros, New York.
In the context of a Western society driven by the speed of cap- Massumi, Brian (Ed.), 2002a. A Shock to Thought: Expression After Deleuze and
italism, internet, and mass media, there appears to be little room Guattari. Routledge, New York.
for attention. Even a simple task like writing a paper becomes Massumi, Brian (Ed.), 2002b. Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation.
Duke University Press, Durham.
fragmented through the presence of multiple windows, screens, Plant, Sadie, 1999. Writing on Drugs. Faber and Faber, London.
and points of focus. In such a context it is worthwhile to note, as Poe, Edgar Allan, 1902. The Complete Works of Edgar Allan Poe. In: Margin-
Wallace does, that the so-called real world will not discourage aliadEureka, vol. XVI. Thomas Y. Crowell & Company, New York.
Redeld, Marc, Brodie, Janet Farrell (Eds.), 2002. High Anxieties: Cultural Studies in
you from operating on your default settings, because the so-called Addiction. University of California Press, Berkeley.
real world of men and money and power hums along quite nicely Stewart, Kathleen, 2007. Ordinary Affects. Duke University Press, Durham.
on the fuel of fear and contempt and frustration and craving and the Thompson, Hunter S., 1998. Fear and Loathing in Las Vegas: a Savage Journey to the
Heart of the American Dream. Vintage Books, New York.
worship of self (Wallace, 2009: 115) that are the products of
Wallace, David Foster, 2009. This is Water: Some Thoughts, Delivered in a Signi-
inscribed habits of inattention. In this context, signposts, or cant Occasion, About Living a Compassionate Life. Little, Brown and Company,
methodological frameworks highlighting the value of attention, are New York.
precisely what we need. Though such conceptual tools are not total Wallace, David Foster, 2011. The Pale King. Little, Brown and Company, New York.
Williams, Raymond, 1977. Marxism and Literature. Oxford University Press,
solutions to the ethical problem of fostering change, they are New York.
certainly a concrete starting point from which we can imagine that Wolfe, Tom, 1968. The Electric Kool-Aid Acid Test. Picador, New York.

You might also like