You are on page 1of 60

ISSUE 123 DECEMBER 2017/JANUARY 2018 UK £3.75 USA $7.99 CANADA $8.

99

PhilosophyNow
a magazine of ideas

Derrida, Plato &


Xenophobia

Kant & The


Human Subject

Santa & The


Problem of Evil

Prejudice &
Perception
LOUIS ALTHUSSER
AVAILABLE
IN ENGLISH
FOR THE
FIRST TIME
Translated by G. M. Goshgarian
Paperback & eBook | £21.99

How to be a Marxist in Philosophy Philosophy for Non-Philosophers


9781474280549 9781474299275

www.bloomsbury.com/philosophy @BloomsburyPhilo

The Ultimate Guide Series


Out Now!
UK £6.99 USA $12.99 CANADA $13.99
Philosophy Now are excited to announce
The Ultimate Guide The Ultimate Guide series: each issue a
Philosophy Now
collection of the best previously
ISSUE ONE: ETHICS
published articles we have on a given
topic, conveniently all in one place.
When apes have
their day in court

Virtue ethics and


the New Testament
Issue One, on Ethics, is your go-to
Find out: What kind
guide for moral philosophy.
of ethicist are you?

Available now at philosophynow.org/shop


and selected retailers.

ETHICS
Philosophy Now
02

9770961597055

a magazine of ideas
Philosophy Now ISSUE 123 Dec 17/Jan 18
Philosophy Now, EDITORIAL & NEWS
43a Jerningham Road, 4 The False Mirror Anja Steinbauer
Telegraph Hill,
London SE14 5NQ 5 News
United Kingdom
Tel. 020 7639 7314 PREJUDICE & PERCEPTION
editors@philosophynow.org 6 Xenos: Jacques Derrida on Hospitality
philosophynow.org Peter Benson considers Jacques Derrida’s ideas about migrants
Editor-in-Chief Rick Lewis 8 Perfectionism & Hate Speech Law
Editors Anja Steinbauer, Grant Bartley Shaun O’Dwyer turns to a Japanese way of fighting hate speech
Digital Editor Bora Dogan
Graphic Design Grant Bartley, Katy
11 Homelessness & the Limits of Hospitality
Baker, Anja Steinbauer Anya Daly shares her ideas and her first-hand experiences
Book Reviews Editor Teresa Britton 14 Prostitution & Instrumentalisation
Film Editor Thomas Wartenberg
Marketing Manager Sue Roberts Rob Lovering critiques one argument against prostitution
Administration Ewa Stacey, Katy Baker 18 An Education In Diversity?
Advertising Team
Jay Sanders, Ellen Stevens
Christina Easton asks if liberal values can be forced on people
jay.sanders@philosophynow.org GENERAL ARTICLES
UK Editorial Board
Rick Lewis, Anja Steinbauer,
Bora Dogan, Grant Bartley Anti-Prejudice 20 What’s So Bad About Smugness?
Emrys Westacott is pleased to have avoided being smug
US Editorial Board Challenging ideas, Pages 6-19 22 The Rise of the Intelligent Authors
Dr Timothy J. Madigan (St John Fisher
College), Prof. Charles Echelbarger, Lochlan Bloom asks if computers will conquer creativity
Prof. Raymond Pfeiffer, Prof. Massimo 24 Santa Claus and the Problem of Evil
Pigliucci (CUNY - City College), Prof.
Teresa Britton (Eastern Illinois Univ.) Jimmy Alfonso Licon says, “Merry Christmas, ho ho ho!”
Contributing Editors 26 Kant and the Human Subject
Alexander Razin (Moscow State Univ.)
Laura Roberts (Univ. of Queensland) Brian Morris looks at the results of Kant’s attending to humanity
David Boersema (Pacific University) 31 Defending Humanistic Reasoning
UK Editorial Advisors Paul Giladi, Alexis Papazoglou & Giuseppina D’Oro explain
KANT & FRIEND © RON SCHEPPER 2017

Piers Benn, Constantine Sandis, Gordon


Giles, Paul Gregory, John Heawood why physical science doesn’t have a monopoly on explanation
US Editorial Advisors 34 Seeing the Future in the Present Past
Prof. Raymond Angelo Belliotti, Toni
Vogel Carey, Prof. Walter Sinnott-
Siobhan Lyons looks at how we see the future through the present
Armstrong, Prof. Harvey Siegel REVIEWS
Cover Image Kant & Friend by Ron
Schepper 2017 editor@textura.org 46 Book: Ultimate Questions by Bryan Magee
reviewed questioningly by Grant Sterling
Printed by The Manson Group Ltd 47 Book: Aesthetics and the Sciences of Mind
8 Porters Wood, Valley Road Industrial
Estate, St Albans AL3 6PZ edited by Currie, Kieran, Meskin and Robson
reviewed artistically by John Greenbank
UK newstrade distribution through:
Intermedia Brand Marketing Ltd
Humanising 50 Film: The Big Lebowski
Tel. 01293 312001 Philosophy Matt Qvortrup admires the Dude’s philosophy
US & Canadian bookstores through: p.26, p.31, p.54 etc REGULARS
Disticor Magazine Distribution Services 30 Philosophical Haiku: Laozi (Lao Tzu) by Terence Green
695 Westney Road S., Unit 14,
Ajax, Ontario L1S 6M9 37 Question of the Month:
Tel. (905) 619 6565 How Can I Know Right From Wrong?
40 Brief Lives: Henry David Thoreau
Australian newstrade distribution:
Gordon & Gotch pty Martin Jenkins surveys an anarchist naturalist individualist
Level 2, 9 Rodborough Road 43 Letters to the Editor
French’s Forest, NSW 2086
Tel. 02 9972 8800 54 Tallis in Wonderland: Death and the Philosopher
Raymond Tallis on philosophical attitudes to non-being
The opinions expressed in this magazine 56 Philosophy Then: When Your Favorite Philosopher Is A Bigot
do not necessarily reflect the views of
the editor or editorial board of Peter Adamson suggests using their ideas against their bigotry
Philosophy Now.
POETRY & FICTION
Philosophy Now is published by 29 Photography in the Eighteenth Century
Anja Publications Ltd
ISSN 0961-5970
Peter Keeble gives Kant a camera and watches what develops
56 The Truth
Subscriptions p.52 Santa and Evil Kaya York gets to grips with a universal demon
Shop p.53
A thought for Christmas, p.24
December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 3
The False Mirror
Editorial A brief history of prejudice.

M
en can’t multitask; women can’t resist shopping; the he merits your respect; you grow in age and knowledge; you
English have a sense of humour; the Germans perceive that this man is a quack, made up of pride, interest,
don’t; philosophers spend their lives navel gazing; and artifice; you despise that which you revered, and prejudice
politicians can’t be trusted; and civil servants are boring. yields to judgment.” The French revolutionaries did not share
Stereotypes, preconceived ideas, prejudices: they are this optimism that we will outgrow prejudice as we mature.
ubiquitous. Sometimes they are annoying, sometimes funny, They took ‘prejudice’ to denote all kinds of errors of the
sometimes devastating. To philosophers they are the ultimate mind, which, in the worst cases, could only be eradicated by
challenge. means of the guillotine!
Philosophy has its demons to fight. Having always put an Most Enlightenment thinkers, you will be relieved to learn,
emphasis on a commitment to truth, philosophers have been favoured less bloody ways of dealing with prejudice.
quick to identify the obstacles that stood in their way of Immanuel Kant distinguished between preliminary opinions
honouring this obligation. Though they couldn’t always agree and prejudice. Both are purely subjective, but there is nothing
on the origins, scope and definition of prejudice, it, in all its wrong with forming a preliminary view of an issue as long it is
forms, emerges as one of their archenemies. recognised as such, as a kind of work in progress. The
The first philosophical musings about prejudice started in problem with prejudices is that they are preliminary opinions
the classical age. Cicero talks about prejudice (praeiusticium) as that are mistaken for final conclusions. However, prejudice is
the opposite of truth, associated with error. However, he not just an intellectual mistake; it has a serious moral
makes clear that rather than being the result of ignorance, component as well. Kant tells us that prejudice is a position
prejudice is born out of manipulation. In a legal context he that we take with respect to a ‘generalised other’, a moral
explains that it means that jurors have listened to a particular client who needs to be taken into account in our thinking.
account of a case over and over again, so that once a trial Through imagination we need to be able to understand the
happens the lawyer who is arguing that version of the case has perspective of this ‘other’. To be free of prejudice is thus only
very little work to do to convince them of the veracity of his possible for someone who “can easily regard the matter from
words. a very different point of view”, who can overcome her ‘logical
The Enlightenment put particular emphasis on the egoism’ and relativise her self interest.
problem of prejudice. Unfortunately, it lost sight of Cicero’s If prejudice can be overcome, can it not be avoided
valuable insight into the connection between manipulation altogether? Following Martin Heidegger, Hans-Georg
and prejudice. Prejudice came to include a whole range of Gadamer showed that all understanding is ‘permanently
erroneously acquired positions. Francis Bacon went so far as determined’ by what he calls pre-understanding. In the end, he
to argue that our natural understanding is a “false mirror”of says, all understanding is always “reflection of a given pre-
the world, as prejudice is a natural condition to which we are understanding.” This means that whenever I need to under-
all prone: “The human understanding when it has once stand someone or something I approach it with a certain pre-
adopted an opinion (either as being the received opinion or as understanding. Why is this so unavoidable? The reason lies
being agreeable to itself) draws all things else to support and not in some genetic disposition but in our own past.
agree with it. And though there be a greater number and Prejudices are based on our ‘historical reality’; in other words,
weight of instances to be found on the other side, yet these it if you have a past, you also have prejudices.
either neglects and despises, or else by some distinction sets This issue of Philosophy Now starts with a collection of
aside and rejects, in order that by this great and pernicious articles which examine prejudice, hospitality towards
predetermination the authority of its former conclusions may strangers, and the different ways in which we as human beings
remain inviolate.” perceive one another. So, what are the lessons to be learned
“Prejudice” (préjugé) became a fashionable term before and here? Most, though not all, philosophers seem to believe that
during the French Revolution, a tool for condemning both prejudice is cognitively impossible to avoid but that it can be
religious tradition and the socio-political status quo. Voltaire rationally and/or morally overcome – although this may be
illustrated the difference between prejudice and mature trickier than we realise. As always, critical thinking is
judgement: “But it is through prejudice that you will respect a required. And once we properly apply critical thinking, we
man dressed in certain clothes, walking gravely, and talking at soon see that while it is true that men can’t multitask, women
the same time. Your parents have told you that you must can resist shopping. … Prejudiced, moi?
bend to this man; you respect him before you know whether Anja Steinbauer

4 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


• Human brains to connect to cloud storage!
• Mini human brains implanted in rodents!

News
• Psychologists study moral intuition
News reports by Anja Steinbauer.

Brain organoid ton, DC in November. One moral length would reduce the individual differ-
concern is that the human cerebral ences in the judgments they made. Ward
organoids could grow in size and complex- explains: “We consistently found that
ity within lab animals, to the point where people who are more prone to rely on
we need to seriously talk about mini-brain intuition condemned these actions …and
consciousness. what we found is that after people deliber-
ated, in general they did condemn these
Merger 2: human brains & machines actions less, but people who strongly
At a recent session of the Council on relied on their intuitive instincts
Foreign Relations on the future of Artifi- condemned these actions more harshly
cial Intelligence, the author, inventor and than others.”
Merger 1: human brains & animals futurist Ray Kurzweil predicted that
Four years ago scientists first developed a “medical robots will go inside our brains The Third Sex
method of growing stem cells into minia- and connect our neo-cortex to the smart In Germany the Federal Constitutional
ture versions of human brains called brain cloud” by the year 2029. This prediction is Court decided in November that in future
organoids. These ‘mini brains’, until now part of Kurzweil’s conviction, shared by it will be possible for new parents to offi-
grown in the lab, have many of the same other experts in the field, that no part of cially register the sex of their baby (and
characteristics as living human brains at an our lives will remain unaffected by AI. for individuals to register their own sex) as
early developmental stage. Their structural Kurzweil is the main prophet of the Singu- either “female”, “male” or… “X”. A
similarity and the fact that they react in a larity – the idea that self-improving artifi- further legal option will be to omit an
similar way to stimuli such as drugs means cial intelligence will create a situation entry concerning sex from the birth regis-
that they are extremely useful for research within the next few decades in which expo- tration form altogether. This decision
into (for instance) Alzheimer’s Disease, nentially accelerating technological change reflects the view of the German constitu-
since opportunities for empirical studies of becomes almost too fast to comprehend. tional judges that persons who consis-
living, fully-developed, human brains are Rather than AI endangering human tently do not feel themselves as belonging
obviously very restricted for ethical survival as Stephen Hawking recently to either gender should not be disadvan-
reasons. A new development has now warned, Kurzweil envisages a merger of taged in their fundamental rights. Austria
given rise to moral reservations concern- humans and AI: “My view is not that AI is is also considering the question and is due
ing organoids. Two teams of scientists going to displace us. It’s going to enhance to announce its decision in 2018.
have experimented with inserting these us. It does already.”
mini brains into the brains of rodents. The Philosopher István Mészáros Dies
team of Professor Fred ‘Rusty’ Gage at the (Im)moral Intuitions Marxist philosopher István Mészáros died
Salk Institute in California has successfully Is gut feeling a good guide to moral evalu- on 1 October 2017 aged 86. In Budapest,
implanted human brain organoids into ation and decision-making? A new study the young Mészáros was a student of
mature mouse brains, where they survived compared the effect of relying on intuition Georg Lukács and an opponent of Stalin-
for up to two months. Meanwhile Dr Isaac rather than deliberation on the resulting ism. After the end of the Hungarian
Chen and his researchers at the University moral outcomes. Research psychologists Uprising in 1956, Mészáros fled his home
of Pennsylvania have implanted human Sarah Ward and Laura King of the country and subsequently accepted
organoids into the secondary visual University of Missouri presented study lectureships at universities in Italy,
cortices of eleven mature rats. The mini participants with a series of scenarios and Canada and the UK. He was professor of
brains, which measured 2 mm across, in each case asked them to judge whether philosophy at the University of Sussex for
again survived for around two months and the action described was wrong. The 15 years. In his influential work Marx’
formed numerous axons linking them- researchers found that people who mostly Theory of Alienation (1970) he argued that
selves to the rat brains, some up to 1.5 mm relied on their moral intuitions tended to distinguishing between an earlier and a
long. Cells in the organoids showed activ- make harsher moral judgements and be later Marx was a mistake. After the
ity when the scientists shone light into the less likely to reconsider their views, even if collapse of the Soviet bloc, Mészáros
rats’ eyes, suggesting that the mini brains the behaviour under consideration caused believed capitalism could still be over-
became functional within the rats brains. no actual harm to anybody. Then they come and his book Beyond Marx (1995)
Both teams reported their work at a Soci- investigated whether asking people to made an important contribution to the
ety for Neuroscience meeting in Washing- reason about the scenarios at greater discussion of the future of socialism.

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 5


Prejudice &
Xenos: Jacques Derrida on Hospitality
Peter Benson tackles xenophobia with the help of Jacques Derrida and Plato.

J
acques Derrida knew a thing or two about being an out- tive of foreign ideas. Having stepped back, Socrates does not speak
sider. He was born of Jewish parents in 1930 in Algeria, again for the entire dialogue. In becoming silent Socrates reveals
at that time a French colony. Hence he was from birth a that the place from which he usually speaks is one appropriately
French citizen, although he did not set foot in France occupied by a stranger. That is, when he is acting as the philo-
until he was nineteen. In 1942, by a decree of the wartime Vichy sophical enquirer, Socrates himself speaks as a stranger in his own
government, his citizenship was revoked because he was Jewish world, questioning those things that others take for granted.
– without him being made a citizen of any other country. The Although not all strangers are philosophers, any viewpoint
major effect of this was his expulsion from the school he had alien to our own can help us become aware of the perspectives
previously been attending. So he was an Algerian who couldn’t we habitually and unthinkingly adopt. Obviously this doesn’t
speak Arabic; a Jew who was not a religious practitioner (nor mean that we should immediately change our opinions to those
could he read Hebrew); and an eventual immigrant to France of the stranger; but the more diverse perspectives we are able to
as a pied-noir (the derogatory phrase used for the French from comprehend, the less narrow and dogmatic our views will be. This
Algeria). These circumstances provided him with no solid sense interaction is a two stage process: first, an opening up to the other
of national identity. His subsequent academic career was pur- person in order to understand what they are saying; and only then
sued largely in unconventional institutions, and, in his later years, considering the criticisms that might be made of this new view-
involved a great deal of travelling abroad. As a result, he was point. A too rapid jump to this second stage is a common fault.
often the appreciative recipient of hospitality. American univer- This process is why Plato found dialogue to be the most appro-
sities, in particular, frequently provided him with opportunities priate form for philosophy, since dialogue cannot take place unless
to teach and conduct research. He often spoke warmly of their one first invites a stranger in, showing them hospitality rather
welcoming environment. His books were read more widely in than hostility. They may or may not bring us something of intel-
their English translations than they were in France. lectual value, but without that initial hospitality we will never
Hard thought is always necessary to distinguish, from within a know. In the New Testament ‘Letter to the Hebrews’ (13.2) we
particular situation, factors of universal relevance. But the state of are reminded: “Do not forget to show hospitality to strangers, for
being an outsider, far from being a deterrent to philosophy, can thereby some have entertained angels unaware.”
be the very place from which philosophical questions are most
readily raised. Furthermore, perhaps all of us today are immi- Derrida’s Hospitality
grants of one kind or another. I have lived in Britain all my life Raising these issues today, over ten years after Derrida’s death,
and yet, with the substantial changes in society over that period, we will all be aware of their relevance to events and circum-
it is no longer the same country I was born into. I have thus, even stances filling our newspapers. In 1996, in his essay On Cos-
by staying in one place, become a kind of immigrant – a bemused mopolitanism, Derrida wrote about the rights of asylum-seekers,
entrant into a new country just as surely as those who have physi- refugees, and immigrants, paying attention to practical propos-
cally moved from their own land. All of us need to make the best als as well as general principles. In particular, he discussed a pro-
we can of such changing circumstances. The countries we have posal, current at that time, to establish cities of refuge that would
lost had numerous faults, along with their admirable qualities. be open to all, of any nationality or none. Here too he evoked a
Only those with very selective memories could deny this. Biblical precedent (from Numbers 35:9-32) advocating cities to
which anyone could flee from persecution.
The Philosophy of the Stranger Nothing came of this idea, and today the sheer magnitude of
In his 1996 seminar Of Hospitality, Derrida discusses Plato’s dia- the flow of refugees from the chaos of the Middle East would
logue The Sophist. This opens with Socrates being introduced make such an approach impractical. Politics, diplomacy, charity,
to a visitor to Athens from Elea in southern Italy, the residence and hard work will all be necessary, and philosophy has only a
of several famous thinkers, such as Parmenides. Socrates small contribution to make to this crisis. But that contribution
expresses great pleasure in meeting this stranger. The Greek can still provide guidance to the other efforts, and it is in this that
word for ‘stranger’ is xenos, also meaning ‘foreigner’. From this Derrida’s discussions of hospitality are of particular value. What’s
we get our word xenophobia. Socrates, by contrast, expresses a more, they exemplify a general feature of Derrida’s political
strong sense of xenophilia. He wishes to hear the stranger’s views, thought whose significance has not always been recognized.
in the hope that they might open new perspectives on philo- There’s a dilemma which Derrida asserts to be an inescapable
sophical questions. feature of the concept of hospitality, which we see vividly revived
To facilitate this, Socrates steps back from his usual central in each successive refugee crisis, and in every discussion about
role in Plato’s dialogues and hands his place over to the stranger, immigration. On the one hand, there is a moral imperative to
who then talks with Socrates’ friend Theaetetus. This stranger show hospitality, especially to people in distress or fleeing from
is never named in the dialogue; he remains simply a representa- danger; and on the other hand, the total abandonment of bor-

6 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Perception
of course on particularities of circumstance. There is
no simple calculus we can apply to resolve each
dilemma, no one definitive way to respond appropri-
ately in each particular case. However, both sides of
the dilemma must always be kept in mind. The ide-
alistic claims of an unrestrained hospitality, though
impossible to follow as a law, must never be com-
pletely silenced by claims of impracticality.

Derrida on Political Dilemmas


In his later writings Derrida repeatedly uncovers
similar dilemmas inherent in the central terms of
our contemporary political thinking, such as Justice,
Democracy, and Human Rights. He does this not
to dismiss these concepts, but to show the doubled
attention that each requires of us. Failures in these
fields occur when one side of the dilemma tem-
porarily obliterates our awareness of the other.
Another common contemporary example is in the
dilemma between freedom and public safety. Unfor-
tunately, Derrida’s mode of analysing these con-
cepts, through the process of ‘deconstruction’, does
not provide immediate answers to urgent questions.
Nevertheless, it yields a more clear-sighted aware-
ness of how responsive action must begin, and shows
that we cannot evade our responsibility by the use
of general formulaic solutions.
Take the case of Democracy, for example: the
value of this notion begins to deteriorate as soon as
people imagine that they have achieved a fully-func-
tioning democracy in the institutions they have estab-
lished. For it is under the cloak of this complacency
Jacques Derrida, that factions begin to utilize those same democratic
institutions as the means for attaining and maintain-
Gail Campbell
ing their own power. There is no fixed solution which
2017 will permanently eradicate this problem. Rather, our
laws and institutions need to be continually modi-
ders would obliterate the home into which they are being fied towards greater and greater democratic inclusiveness and
invited. All borders have some degree of permeability; but if it transparency, without imagining that this process can ever reach
becomes absolutely open, then the border itself is abolished, perfection. We can only commit ourselves to a ‘democracy to
and there is no longer any place of safety – any home – to enter. come’, to use Derrida’s phrase, rather than to any current inad-
Derrida sets this dilemma out clearly in Of Hospitality: “How equate approximation of democracy.
can we distinguish between a guest and a parasite? In principle, And so it is with hospitality too. We should never plump our-
the difference is straightforward, but for that you need a law; selves up with the bland conviction that we are a hospitable people.
hospitality, reception, the welcome offered, have to be submit- Rather, we must be constantly alert as to how we can become
ted to a basic and limiting jurisdiction” (p.59). ‘Hospitality’ more hospitable, whilst avoiding a catastrophic collapse of the
assumes the ability to provide a safe haven, a shelter from storms, region of safety we envisage in the word ‘home’. So Derrida’s is
and like a biological membrane, the border must inevitably be not a philosophy that offers definitive answers to these dilem-
selective when allowing itself to be crossed. If refugees fleeing mas, since such an answer would necessarily be wrong, if we are
from persecutors find their way through an opening, it cannot dealing with a true dilemma. Rather, it alerts us to the fact that
be equally open to those pursuing them. Every opening to others we are always in the situation of never having done enough. The
implies associated closings. As Derrida explains: “Between an hospitable person or country should be seeking at all times to be
unconditional law or an absolute desire for hospitality on the more hospitable, alert to any opportunities to move in this direc-
one hand and, on the other, a law, a politics, a conditional ethics, tion, never saying, “we’ve done enough, we can’t do more,” rather,
there is a distinction, radical heterogeneity, but also indissocia- always seeking practical ways to do more than we have.
bility. One calls forth, involves, or prescribes the other” (p.147). © PETER BENSON 2017
The particular balance between these two indissociable aspects Peter Benson is no stranger to philosophy, having studied it at
of the notion of hospitality, openness and closedness, will depend Cambridge University.

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 7


Prejudice &
Perfectionism &
Hate Speech Law
Shaun O’Dwyer on reconciling free speech with protection against hate speech.
n this era of growing ethno-nationalism and xenophobia speech advocates whenever perfectionism is invoked to promote

I in Europe and America, and indeed, worldwide, debates


over hate speech are intensifying. Decent people argue
that the terrifying rhetoric of extreme right wing groups
online and on the streets – and escalating confrontations –
demonstrate the necessity of hate speech laws.
hate speech law. The free speech advocates will complain that
hate speech law is itself unacceptably coercive and paternalistic
– that it requires the state to abandon the value-neutrality that
it ought to occupy in a diverse liberal society, in order to play
favorites with values or ideas of the good life that are the sub-
Supporters of freedom of speech have responded that the ject of reasonable disagreement between citizens. One such point
non-coercive speech of all should be protected – including the of disagreement concerns whose idea of the good life should be
free speech of racists, neo-Nazis, and bigots. In diverse liberal considered so detrimental for the overall good of society that
societies, they argue, it is inconsistent for the state, or even pow- its expression must be regulated or prohibited.
erful social media platforms such as Facebook, to protect some However, I have in mind a mild liberal perfectionist approach
expressions of ideas while banning others merely because some to hate speech – call it ‘perfectionism lite’ – which envisages a
groups object to it. It is also likely, they argue, that hate speech non-coercive role for the state in encouraging the good life of
laws or bans can be weaponized against their advocates, such its citizens. So rather than criminalizing hate speech, doing which
that polemical ideas by minority activists or leftist radicals can impinges upon another good the state also regards itself as bound
also be prohibited when their right-wing or authoritarian ene- to uphold – the freedom of speech – the state passes laws exhort-
mies turn hate speech prohibitions to their own advantage. ing citizens to stand up to hate speech.
The stalemated debate between these two positions suggests As a free speech liberal I have my own qualms about perfec-
a sort of ‘incommensurability of values’ that Isaiah Berlin once tionism lite, but I think it worthwhile to explore how it could
wrote about – between liberty on the one side and human dig- both justify hate speech law whilst also opposing criminalizing
nity and civic equality on the other. They’re all prized and rec- hate speech.
ognized to have tremendously beneficial consequences when As it turns out, there is an example of non-coercive hate
realized in law and in custom. Yet an increase in free speech speech law to hand which can help us think through this ques-
often involves some diminishing of dignity. Freedom for the tion, for in 2016 the government of Japan passed just such a law.
swaggering bully takes away equality and dignity for those at Two to three years ago racist demonstrations against resi-
the bottom of the playground pecking order. Conversely, dent ethnic Koreans (Zainichi) had become almost daily occur-
enforcing equality and respect for dignity involves some dimin- rences in Japan. The rage behind these demonstrations was
ishment in liberty. The would-be bully keeps his thoughts and stoked by a combination of political issues, including Japanese
urges to himself, but perhaps so do many others, as the vigilant disagreements with South Korea over colonial and wartime his-
headmistress casts her shadow over a quieter, seemingly more tory, growing diplomatic tensions with North Korea, and resent-
egalitarian playground. ments over the perceived ‘special rights’ given to Zainichi. Ultra-
I want to suggest that a compromise between freedom and right-wing organizations demonstrated outside Zainichi schools
dignity over the problem of hate speech might be possible. My or in the Korea Towns of Tokyo and Osaka, displaying or shout-
approach is inspired by a philosophy called perfectionism. Perfec- ing slogans such as “Exterminate all Koreans!”; “We came here
tionists typically hold that there are objective values or goods to kill North Koreans!”; “Cockroaches!”; “Kick these low-life
whose promotion contributes to morally valuable ways of life, Korean maggots out of Japan!”, while similar abuse proliferated
nurturing the ‘better angels’ of human nature; and also that objec- on internet forums. A former leader of one such ultra-rightist
tive moral value means some ways of life are more valuable than outfit stood in Tokyo’s 2016 gubernatorial election, attracting
others. Many (but not all) moral perfectionists think that the state 1.74 percent of the vote – a still unnerving total of 114,000 votes
has a role in promoting the better ways of life by passing legisla- – on an anti-immigration ‘Japan First’ platform.
tion and distributing resources to enhance different goods or pro- Subsequently, debates about the criminalization of hate
mote different values, in areas such as welfare, education, the arts speech took place amongst politicians, scholars and media com-
and sciences, employment, and civic morality. For such perfec- mentators, especially since international organizations such as
tionists, laws against hate speech make sense in terms of promot- the United Nations urged Japan to pass such laws. However,
ing more mutually-respectful ways of living in diverse societies. these debates were framed by a strong awareness of speech free-
doms, since Articles 19 to 21 of Japan’s post-war constitution
A New Way Of Opposing Hate Speech provide robust protections for freedom of conscience, speech,
Perfectionism has a respectable pedigree in liberal thought and religion. Judicial experts and politicians cited these articles
extending back to John Stuart Mill and Immanuel Kant; but to highlight the difficulties of criminalizing hate speech.
this pedigree is not enough to save it from the objections of free The hate speech law that was finally passed in 2016 reflected

8 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Perception
this awareness. Although this legislation admits the “tremen- speech act is the one uttered by marriage celebrants who, in
dous pain and suffering” that “unfair discriminatory speech and pronouncing a couple to be married, make it so. In the 1980s
behavior” inflicts upon resident foreigners and their descen- and 90s, some feminist philosophers argued that pornography
dants in Japan, it provides no criminal law remedies: instead it is a speech act that subjugates and silences women; and since
directs national and local governments to use publicity cam- that time, race and gender theorists have explored how hate
paigns and education to “increase public awareness of the neces- speech works (or fails to work) as a speech act to subordinate
sity of eliminating unfair, discriminatory speech.” I wonder if people of colour and sexual minorities.
such legislation could provide inspiration for perfectionist- Although not all of these theorists favour criminal law reme-
minded hate speech statutes in nations which, like Japan, have dies for hate speech, there is some consensus on how hate speech
strong constitutional protections for freedom of speech? works as a speech act. Imagine a white man outside a segregated
swimming pool in the South of the United States in the mid-
Difficulties with Criminalizing Hate Speech twentieth century, looking menacingly at some black people
Many Japanese progressives want hate speech to be criminal- passing ‘too close’ to him and snarling “no n-----s allowed.” He
ized, and are not satisfied with the hate speech law as it cur- is doing something in saying this: he is enforcing a legal ban
rently stands. I’m inclined to think it should be left as it is, since against black people entering the pool. In doing this he is sup-
the strongest arguments in favour of criminalizing hate speech posedly ‘putting them in their place’ as an inferior class of per-
do not stand up to scrutiny, as I intend to show. sons. Such statements also have the intended effects of intimi-
One way to define and justify hate speech law which some legal dating people into deferential obedience and pre-emptively
philosophers recommend, is through comparison with defama- silencing opposition. We need not even imagine the white man
tion and libel law. Defamation involves publically making untrue there: a sign bearing the same message will do a similar job.
statements calculated to harm a person’s reputation and dignity. On this understanding hate speech is a speech act which
Hate speech, according to these legal philosophers, can be under- oppresses vulnerable minorities, puts them in an inferior place,
stood as a group libel or defamation – that is, as untrue, abusive, inflicts fear, humiliation, and insecurity on them, and silences
dehumanizing, threatening and insulting speech calculated to them. So the argument here is that hate speech should be crim-
damage the social standing and dignity of people as members of a inalized in recognition of the harms that it does and causes, and
particular group, and thus stir up hatred against them. The degree to prevent the subjection of minority groups.
of damage this inflicts upon the collective dignity of a group, and Obviously, substantial institutional and social props need to
the damage such speech does to civic order through the accumu- be present for hate speech acts to work so effectively. Imagine a
lation of public statements asserting, directly or indirectly, that white man pulling that same stunt outside a public pool today.
members of that group do not deserve equal status as citizens or Without the backing of racist institutions, conventions and laws
as human beings, warrants a criminal law remedy, they argue. – and lynch mobs – such speech acts can no longer work as they
One objection to this idea of hate speech as a ‘group libel’ is were intended to. There may still be intimidation and fear; but
that claims about damage to collective dignity and standing can more overwhelmingly, there will be defiance, outrage, condem-
be used to criminalize many kinds of group criticism, as a means nation of the incident on national and social media, public denun-
to shutting down freedom of speech. These include ‘defama-
tion of religion’ laws to protect religious groups from insults
against their faith, including satire or criticism; and Turkey’s
Article 301, which proscribes ‘insults to the Turkish nation’ –
such as public statements asserting the truth of the Armenian
Genocide.
Defenders argue that hate speech laws are different because
they are intended to protect vulnerable minorities. Such
minorities have long memories of discrimination, subjugation,
or even genocide, and are historically vulnerable to speech that
PROTEST © FIBONACCI BLUE 2016

diminishes their social standing, rendering them insecure and


fearful for their survival.
This response will not satisfy critics, who may point out that
such a rationale could be reverse-engineered by white nation-
alists and religious sectarians eager to present themselves as
minorities vulnerable to persecution. This might appear to be
an absurd objection, but it is unwise to consider ‘absurdity’ only
from the point of view of a philosophy discussion, rather than,
say, a national election campaign harnessing populist, ethno-
nationalist resentments.
Another sophisticated way to define hate speech is to think
of it as what linguists and philosophers of language call a ‘speech
act’. Speech acts do not simply describe: they are meant to do Protest against hate speech
something or have an intended effect. A classic example of a

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 9


Prejudice &
ciations by government officials, and, possibly, arrests of the per- to justify coercive state intervention, and that there are also pru-
petrators under anti-intimidation statutes. dential reasons for opposing such laws, because of their ques-
Although these are good and necessary developments, it tionable efficacy, and because they can be abused. They will
makes a problem for describing hate speech as an oppressive also likely agree that given its malignant, discriminatory intent,
speech act in modern liberal democracies, in that it’s difficult to which conflicts with important values such as the dignity and
prove that minority groups are so homogeneous that hate speech equality of all citizens irrespective of creed or ethnicity, etc,
will uniformly work against them, forcing them into the infe- hate speech is a serious moral problem for liberal societies. But
rior, subjugated and injured status that warrants criminal sanc- they will still disagree on how to deal with it.
tion against their abusers. That is, under defamation law, or So I will conclude with some cautious remarks in favour of
criminal laws covering threat and intimidation, it is in principle Japan’s hate speech legislation, and summarize some objec-
relatively straightforward for individuals to go to court and pre- tions that free speech advocates like myself might still have to
sent their case that they have suffered injury to their reputations, it. In the year since its passage, this law has proven effective in
or been intimidated by prejudiced abuse and threats. Things are incentivizing local government and police authorities to use
less straightforward for groups comprising hundreds of thou- existing statutes against more menacing hate speech, online or
sands, or millions, of people, perhaps definable as a historically on the street. Moreover, in sending a signal to wider society
vulnerable minority, but divided by opinion, values, wealth, occu- that hate speech is officially condemned, it is encouraging civil
pation, and social status. Compare the case of a tenured African- society activists, including from minority groups, to organize
American professor at a leading American university who is sub- counter-protests and impose moral penalties on those who
jected to a racial slur by a white student, but is backed up by col- express hate. Coincidentally or not, anti-Korean demonstra-
lege anti-racism codes, and supported by colleagues, adminis- tions have halved in the past year, and so has the intensity of
trators, and the student body, with that of an impoverished work- the language used in them.
ing-class African-American teenager subjected to the same slur Substantial objections remain, however. First there is the prob-
by a white policeman confronting him on a street. lem of paternalism, implicit in the sort of hate speech law that
Many contextual factors, beginning with differences or sim- perfectionism lite supports. For instance, in declaring that the
ilarities in social and legal power between abusers and the public needs to undergo education and consciousness-raising
abused, can influence how much hate speech actually works as campaigns to help eliminate hate speech, Japan’s hate speech law
intended, or backfires on the abusers. In light of such doubts, appears to judge citizens incapable by themselves of conducting
liberal opponents of hate speech law can mobilize the ‘harm their lives in a morally upright fashion, instead assuming that they
principle’ to reject criminalization of hate speech. The harm need to be educated to do the right thing. Liberal critics of per-
principle says that the state is only warranted in using coercion fectionism argue that such judgements are unacceptable, since
against citizens to prevent the citizens from coercing or harm- they deny to citizens what Jonathan Quong has described as “their
ing their fellow citizens. But it is often not clear how much hate moral status as free and equal citizens.”
speech harms on a collective scale. Second, the strong language used to denounce hate speech
Yet even if it’s hard to identify a common denominator for in the Japanese legislation – “unfair speech and action… will
the harms hate speech does to internally diverse minorities, surely not be tolerated” and “tolerating (its existence) is impermissi-
things will be much worse if governments do nothing to ban it. ble” – may leave the door open for mission creep towards coer-
Hate speech acts may not always work as intended; but their cive measures to eliminate free speech that is argued to be hate
malignant intent remains, and will be recognized as such, con- speech, generating the sort of problems we’ve looked at.
tributing to fear and insecurity amongst minority groups, espe- Third, the formulation of any hate speech law puts in the
cially when those speech acts escalate into violent physical acts. hands of the state the power to define which minority groups
However, in our era of renewed nationalism, there are signs are affected by it. In the case of Japan’s hate speech law, they
that criminal hate speech laws are not working as intended. For are defined as “persons originating exclusively from a country
instance, Canada’s criminal hate speech laws are stringently or region other than Japan or their descendants” and this defi-
defined yet rarely enforced, and there have been modest nition refers most obviously to Japan’s Zainichi minority. Such
increases in hate crimes there in the past three years, especially a definition can provoke objections over who it excludes, such
against Muslims. France has more frequently enforced crimi- as indigenous people, or religious minorities, and whether there
nal hate speech laws, but anti-Semitic and anti-Islamic hate are convincing reasons for such exclusions.
crimes and xenophobic political movements have all sharply These objections may not be decisive, although they do moti-
increased there in recent years. Germany has ‘incitement to vate my own wariness about even perfectionist lite justifications
hatred laws’, but it has struggled to cope with rises in violent for hate speech law. Still, I remain open-minded that these
hate crimes and hate speech in the 1990s and in more recent objections could be neutralized by carefully formulated, non-
years, and it too has witnessed a rise in xenophobic and anti- coercive hate speech statutes proposed wherever there is robust
immigration political movements. constitutional and social support for speech freedoms.
© SHAUN O’DWYER 2017
The Japanese Way Shaun O’Dwyer is an associate professor in the Faculty of Languages
Both free speech advocates and perfectionist promoters of non- and Cultures at Kyushu University, Japan. He has published widely
criminal hate speech laws can agree that hate speech does not on topics such as pragmatist philosophy and modern Confucian
represent a clear enough case of collective harm or oppression thought, and moonlights as a journalist in his spare time.

10 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Perception
Homelessness
& the Limits of Hospitality
Anya Daly says we’ll solve homelessness only when we see it as our problem.
“No face can be approached with empty hands and closed home.” nantly on arguments. For phenomenology, the world is not
“The need of the other is my spiritual need.” reducible to propositions, and so it depends on a wide reper-
Emmanuel Levinas toire of philosophical methods – detailed descriptive analysis
and evocations as well as arguments. Philosophical understand-
oming home on the tram my gaze met that of a young ing, for phenomenology, is as much a ‘showing’ as a ‘telling’.

C man shouldering a carry-all – heavy, and torn in


parts. I looked away quickly. Clearly that carry-all
carried all his belongings, and, I hoped, food for the
wet, icy night ahead under the bridge. I knew I was going home
to company and a hearty soup. Part of me wanted to suggest he
The Lived Experience of Homelessness
The problem of homelessness first hit me when I was living in
Paris when there was a huge housing crisis. At one point there
were tents all along the Canal Saint Martin and filling the Place
come back and share soup with us; but the greater part was fear- de la République. There were many, many beggars on the streets.
ful: he could be dangerous, perhaps a drug user, and even if nei- I remember for the last months of one winter I would cross the
ther of these, how could we then turn him out into the cold canal at a small bridge under which lived an old man and a young
again? The limits of my hospitality – my fear. woman. In the morning I would regularly see her preparing her-
This article explores the issue of homelessness from the per- self for her work day – doing her hair, putting on her make-up,
spective of someone who has experienced homelessness, as and tidying away her bedding. Clearly, she had a job but the
someone who has worked with the homeless and heard the sto- salary could not cover rent. That was shocking for me, espe-
ries of ‘our friends on the street’, as a mother distressed to see cially when I learnt of the rich people who had many vacant
other mothers’ children, no matter their age, in such dire cir- apartments they did not want to rent, either because they were
cumstances, and as a philosopher driven to interrogate the waiting for the rental market to give higher returns or because
hidden assumptions and beliefs motivating our choices, judg- it was more advantageous for them to just keep the apartments
ments, and behavior. I wish to stress that homelessness must be empty, solely as investments.
addressed from the philosophical perspective not only with In my fifth year in France I moved to Toulouse and there
regard to the individual, but also with regard to the individual suffered a life-threatening accident. On my return to Australia
as belonging to the ‘we’. This ‘we’ must include all the people I was homeless because I was unable to work. Fortunately for
involved, from the homeless person laying out her swag under me, I had family and friends who ensured I always had a roof
the bridge, to the policy-makers earning fabulous salaries. I’ll over my head. That year I lived in six different situations before
propose that a deeper understanding of what’s called ‘double gaining affordable housing. Even in the comparatively favor-
incorporation’ is a crucial step towards galvanizing political will able situation of being cared for, I was deeply shaken in my sense
to implement solutions that have already been identified. of self because of the loss of independence, because I had no
The first part of this article will relate my experience with base that was mine. So once I had regained my health I volun-
regard to homelessness to provide context. The second part will teered with the Salvation Army, raising funds, and also with the
examine some philosophical considerations around the notion Orange Sky Laundry, a mobile laundry service for the home-
of ‘home’. I am taking a phenomenological approach to this less established by two young Brisbane men and run entirely
discussion, not an analytic approach which depends predomi- with volunteers. It now operates in fourteen cities in Australia.
The service is as much about the conversations as getting the
laundry done. The site I worked at in Melbourne was in the posh
part of the central city, in what is known as the Paris end of Collins
Street. In fact we parked the van and set up our chairs directly
outside Dior, adjacent to a small terrace area that the homeless
people had taken over. They called it ‘the community kitchen’,
since from there they organised collections of food donations
from the various cafés around the inner city. Of course the busi-
nesses were not happy about this – these destitute people were
occupying prime real estate – and eventually the city council
cleared out all their belongings, removed the seats, and installed
plant boxes. So what had been effectively the equivalent of a home-
base for them was destroyed. Some were given emergency accom-
modation, but most had to find another place to doss.
It felt good to be doing something. The practical aid, the sol-

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 11


Prejudice &
idarity, and the sympathy were clearly appreciated; and, I must
confess, it did help to somewhat relieve my own distress and
guilt about their desperate and, more often than not, deterio-
by Melissa Felder
rating lives. To an extent, we are all complicit in this terrible
injustice. We have allowed the neoliberal agenda to override
our consciences, to override our fellow-feeling, and to allow us
to conveniently ignore the core value of ‘fair play’. Most cer-
tainly we can say that some of these people have contributed,

PLEASE VISIT SIMONANDFINN.COM


sometimes significantly, to their own wretched situations; but
nonetheless, the systemic injustices are pervasive and perni-
cious. The paths to sleeping rough are numerous: domestic vio-
lence; sexual abuse; debt; psychiatric problems; unemployment;
underemployment; the bank foreclosing on the home or farm;
PTSD following military service; incapacitating accidents; drug
and alcohol addiction; not having the means to get back to a

SIMON + FINN CARTOON © MELISSA FELDER 2017


home country; having relied on the support of friends and family
one time too many; family break-up; housing which is danger-
ous because of drugs and violence, etc. This is clearly not a ‘one
size fits all’ problem; it is various and multifaceted.
In August 2016 I participated in a one-day workshop titled
‘Homelessness and Housing Insecurity’. One observation from
the only participating anthropologist was the need to consider
factors upstream from the outcome of homelessness: nothing less
than critiquing the economic system which has without question
set the stage for it, and for many other social injustices which in
turn feed into the injustice of homelessness. But in my view we
need to go even further upstream to look for causes in our con-
ceptions of ourselves; specifically, in the persisting delusion of our
radical separateness from others. This individualistic view of self
underpins the sense of entitlement of many (not all) of the wealthy,
who refuse to help. While the opposing view of interdependency is
slowly gaining currency, it has yet to filter through to tangible
outcomes with policy-makers, politicians, the big end of town,
and the general public. Homelessness is not just a problem for
the individual enduring it. It has direct consequences for the wider
society, including for you and me. And simply, we must ask our-
selves, what kind of society do we want to live in?
So with this in mind, in the next part of this article I wish to
venture into the philosophical questions concerning the nature
of the self with regard to this issue of homelessness. I will do so
by drawing on the work of key figures in the phenomenologi-
cal tradition – notably Levinas, Merleau-Ponty, and Scheler. gathering the self, thus providing our launching place for our activ-
ity in the world. Finally, home is a place of interiority – of safety,
Self, Place, Belonging & Hospitality intimacy, and welcome. It is home in these last two senses that I
In his book Totality and Infinity (1961, trans 1969), in the chapter wish to explore: home as the shelter from external threats, and as
titled ‘Dwelling’, Emmanuel Levinas offers an extended medita- a place to recollect the self – to revive and to gather resources
tion on the notions of ‘dwelling, habitation, home and hospital- needed to venture into the world and contribute to society.
ity’. For Levinas, hospitality operates in two domains – the ethi- As Levinas writes: “To dwell, is not the simple fact of the
cal and the political. Within the ethical domain, the individual anonymous reality of a being cast into existence, as a stone one
has a moral obligation to give shelter under their own roof. In casts behind oneself; it is recollection, a coming to oneself, a
the political domain, as citizens of a country, to be hospitable we retreat home with oneself as in a land of refuge, which answers
must welcome all those who truly seek refuge into our homeland. to a hospitality, an expectancy, a human welcome” (p.156). Here
Levinas sets out various conceptions of ‘home’. Home is an we can see Levinas expressing a view common to many philo-
implement which offers protection from the elements and enemies; sophical and psychological traditions, of home as being a symbol
as an implement it may also be a source of pleasure, such as when for the self. And there is an inside and an outside to this self.
using a good tool can provide immense satisfaction. Home may He says: “Man abides in the world as having come to it from a
also be considered a possession which is convertible into money. private domain, from being at home with himself, to which at
Levinas also describes home as the place of recollection – a place of each moment he can retire… he goes forth outside from an

12 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Perception
inwardness. Yet this inwardness opens up in a home which is ‘I’ perspective and the ‘we’ perspective. When identification
situated in the outside – for the home, as a building, belongs to centers solely on the ‘I’, the person is dominated by individual-
a world of objects” (p.152). ism and competition. However, when the sense of self embraces
Like the embodied self, the home has both an interior and an the ‘we’, the values become collective ones and the orientation
exterior; and as there are doors and windows for the home, so is characterized by cooperation. The more the circle of ‘we’ is
too there are also the self’s expressive doors of face, gesture and widened, the more the subject is available to others. The sub-
language. Neither the home nor the self are impenetrable inte- ject with the ‘we’ orientation identifies as being one among
riorities, entirely separate from others and the outside world. others, as belonging – whether at the level of family, commu-
These challenges to the interiority and exteriority divide are nity, species, or at its most expanded, as one sentient being
also key to the thought of another French phenomenologist, among others. Empathic responsiveness is not guaranteed, how-
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, who argues for an intrinsic interde- ever, because if the ‘we’ is defined narrowly and constrained
pendence between self and other.in his book The Phenomenology only to certain others – to family, race, the religious commu-
of Perception (1962). For Merleau-Ponty, subjectivity is an inter- nity, etc – the excluded do not arouse any sense of fellow-feel-
subjectivity, and otherness is a category both internal to and con- ing, and in fact they may rather incite fear, aversion, hatred and
stitutive of the self. It is due to this self-alienation internal to the aggression. We see this also with the stigmatization of the home-
subject that other selves, alter egos, and all interactions with less. Despite their tragic circumstances, they are not recognized
other people, become possible. as deserving of a place, of belonging: they are excluded. And it
This way of thinking about our intersubjectivity can provide is this alienation even more than the physical discomforts of
a useful means of inquiring into homelessness. It is clear that sleeping rough and the challenges of survival that leads to the
something philosophically interesting is going on in our pro- psychological deterioration of the homeless. They are living
found distress with regard to the plight of the homeless. I pro- within a society to which they do not belong, and from which
pose it is because the sight of homeless people challenges our there is no welcome. This, I propose, because of the double
sense of entitlement and also our sense of self and belonging. incorporation, is a violence towards them at the most basic level
It makes us recognise how fragile these things in fact are; that of their sense of self. And this is why so many homeless people
we too could potentially become victim to any number of the display symptoms of compounded trauma, combining the
misfortunes, such as have been visited on those living under impacts of whatever led them to the streets in the first place
bridges and on streets. with their rejection and exclusion from the wider society.
There is also the fear of those living an unrooted life, without So the question is, how can we get especially the politicians
community and therefore without the demands and constraints and the big end of town to expand their sense of ‘we’? Albert
of social belonging. The homeless person becomes truly alien. Einstein captures exactly the core of the issue when he writes:
As philosopher Anthony Steinbock has proposed in his article
‘Homelessness and the Homeless Movement’ (Human Studies, “A human being is part of a whole, called by us ‘universe’ – a part
17 (2), 1994), drawing on the phenomenologist Edmund Husserl, limited in time and space. He experiences himself, his thoughts and
our own ‘homeworlds’ are co-constituted by the ‘alienworld’ of feelings, as something separated from the rest… a kind of optical
the homeless. The homeless do not belong to our community; delusion of his consciousness. This delusion is a kind of prison for
they do not share our culture, our values, our social etiquette, us, restricting us to our personal desires and to affection for a few
our ways of eating and urinating. This is why our efforts are usu- persons nearest to us. Our task must be to free ourselves from this
ally inadequate to addressing the problems of homelessness: one prison by widening our circle of compassion to embrace all living
of the dangers for any intervention is that the homeless person creatures and the whole of nature in its beauty.”
becomes a project of the helper intervening; and then what (Letter from Einstein to a father on the death of his son, 12/02/50.)
inevitably comes into play is an almost coercive normalizing of
the homeless person. The challenge is to offer support in a way Homeless people are citizens with rights to vote; but their
that does not violate their autonomy, nor render them predictable, other basic human rights are not being respected: the right to a
controllable, and acceptable according to our own standards. home, a shelter from the elements and from external threat, a
base from which to carve out a place in the working world and
The Double Incorporation the social world. Homelessness is my problem and your prob-
Here I want to engage with the key phenomenological idea that, lem. Solutions to homelessness lie not just in social action,
just as Merleau-Ponty asserted, subjectivity is an intersubjec- policy, or economics, but most fundamentally in our concep-
tivity; or as the German phenomenologist Max Scheler describes tions of ourselves and our society. When we can break out of
the double incorporation of the ‘I’ within the ‘we’ and the ‘we’ the prison of the delusion of our separateness, and meet these
within the ‘I’ in The Nature of Sympathy (1913, trans 2009): “com- others in solidarity, then the political will to address homeless-
munity is in some sense implicit in every individual, and that ness, and many other social injustices, will be found.
man is not only part of society, but that society and the social © DR ANYA DALY 2017
bond are an essential part of himself: that not only is the ‘I’ a Anya Daly has recently published Merleau-Ponty and the Ethics
member of the ‘we’, but also that the ‘we’ is a necessary member of Intersubjectivity (Palgrave Macmillan, 2016). She currently
of the ‘I’” (pps.229, 230). holds an Irish Council Postdoctoral Research Fellowship at University
This view rejects the idea of the isolated, atomistic subject, College Dublin, and is working on a project concerning the subjective
and instead says that in the core of our subjectivity is both the bases of violence, destructiveness and ethical failure.

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 13


Prejudice &
Prostitution & Instrumentalization
Rob Lovering argues that a popular argument against prostitution doesn’t work

s you are undoubtedly aware, prostitution is illegal other reason). More specifically, to be used as a mere means to

A throughout much of the world. You might also be


aware that opposition to its criminalization is on the
rise. Amnesty International endorsed its decriminal-
ization not long ago, followed by numerous organizations such
as the World Health Organization, UNAIDS, Human Rights
an end is to agree to behavior – be it one’s own or another’s –
to which one, as a rational moral agent, cannot rationally agree.
(‘Rational moral agent’ – hereafter just ‘agent’ – is an ethical
jargon term for someone who is capable of making, and acting
on the basis of, moral and nonmoral judgments.) On this under-
Watch and, particularly noteworthy for us, philosophers such standing, to use oneself or to allow oneself to be used as a mere
as Peter Singer, Philip Pettit, and Patricia Marino. Recent means to an end is to agree to behavior to which one, as an
cover stories for New York Magazine and The New York Times agent, cannot rationally agree.
Magazine have asked: ‘Is Prostitution Just Another Job?’ and The mere is important, because we all use people as a means
‘Should Prostitution Be a Crime?’ to our ends; by letting them do us any service – cook us a meal,
So how strong are the reasons for treating prostitution as a for instance. The question is whether that is all we’re treating
crime? Some people advocate the continued prosecution of them as. I should also reiterate those final three words, empha-
prostitution on grounds to do with the safety or well-being of sizing the second: cannot rationally agree. Whether one is using
its participants, or its effects on the wider community. How- oneself or allowing oneself to be used as a mere means to an
ever, another reason also frequently given is that prostitution end turns on whether one can rationally agree to the use to
is immoral. As Donna Hughes, a professor of women’s stud- which one is being put. If not, then one is thereby instrumen-
ies, puts it, “Most existing laws concerning prostitution were talizing oneself.
formulated on the assumption that prostitution is immoral For example, suppose someone sincerely desires that others
activity, with women being the most immoral participants.” always, invariably tell her the truth. In doing so, she cannot
(Making the Harm Visible, 1999). The question naturally arises: rationally agree to behavior that prevents others from telling
Is prostitution immoral? Various philosophers have put for- her the truth. For were she to agree to that, then she would be
ward arguments for thinking so, one of the most notable being desiring contradictory things which, in virtually any sense of
that by engaging in sexual activity with someone for payment, the word, is not rational. So were she to agree to behavior that
the prostitute instrumentalizes himself or herself. (Henceforth prevents others from telling her the truth, then she would be
in this article I’ll limit myself to a single set of gender-specific allowing something that contradicts one of her own most fun-
pronouns: she, her, and herself). Let’s call this the instrumen- damental ends; so she would be allowing herself to be used as
talization argument for the immorality of prostitution. But a mere means to an end, and thus instrumentalizing herself by
what does this even mean? Well, here are two main under- denying her own nature as a rational agent.
standings of what it means to instrumentalize oneself: Given this understanding of instrumentalizing oneself, the
first instrumentalization argument against prostitution may be
(i) To use oneself, or to allow oneself to be used, as a mere understood as claiming that by engaging in sexual activity with
means to an end; or someone for payment, the prostitute agrees to behavior to
(ii) To block, damage, or destroy one’s self-integration. which she, as an agent, cannot rationally agree. Whether this
version of the instrumentalization argument is sound turns on
Let’s examine these two understandings of instrumentaliz- whether this claim is true.
ing oneself more closely, and in the process examine the ver- So is it? Not at first glance. After all, in agreeing to engage
sion of the instrumentalization argument that goes with each. in sexual activity with someone for payment, the prostitute is
not, at the same time and in the same respect, also not agree-
Being Used as a Mere Means to an End ing to engage in sexual activity with someone for payment,
The version of the argument that relies upon the first under- which would be a contradiction and hence irrational.
standing of instrumentalizing oneself has its roots in the ethi- But perhaps the prostitute necessarily desires something else
cal theories of Immanuel Kant. Kant’s famous Categorical that engaging in sexual activity with someone for payment pre-
Imperative says that it is wrong to use a person purely or merely vents, which would also be irrational. If so, then this version of
as a means to an end, since to do so is to treat them not as a the instrumentalization argument could be sound.
person but as an object. This is so, Kant adds, even if the person A number of potentially necessarily desirable things could
in question is yourself. What exactly is meant by using oneself be proposed here, but for the sake of space let’s consider just
or allowing oneself to be used as a mere means to an end is an one, which might however be thought fundamental to the issue
issue over which much ink has been spilled, but one common at hand. It might be that the prostitute necessarily desires that
understanding of it is for oneself to agree to ends to which one her agency be respected. It’s possible that engaging in sexual
cannot in principle agree (by coercion, manipulation or for any activity with someone for payment prevents respect for one’s

14 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Stop Violence Against Women, Farshaad Razmjouie, 2017
Perception

agency. With that in mind, two more questions arise: Does a for her agency! And by paying the musician for her work, her
prostitute necessarily desire that her agency be respected? And, employer accepts her chosen conditions of cooperation and
if she does, does prostitution deny respect for her agency? thereby respects her agency. Engaging in an activity with or
Addressing the first question would involve a complex dis- for someone for payment, then, does not appear to prevent
cussion of the nature of agency; so for the sake of argument, respect for one’s agency in principle.
let’s just assume that a prostitute does necessarily desire that As for whether engaging specifically in sexual activity with
her agency be respected. This brings us to the second ques- someone for payment prevents respect for one’s agency, once
tion: Does engaging in prostitution prevent respect for one’s again, arguably it does not. To begin with, given that in gen-
agency? eral, engaging in an activity with someone for payment does
Not necessarily. An effective way of demonstrating this is not prevent respect for one’s agency then neither does engag-
in steps: the first step being determining whether in general ing in sexual activity with someone for payment if all else is
engaging in an activity with someone for payment prevents equal. But it might be argued that all else is not in fact equal.
respect for one’s agency; and the second step being that of But why think this? What is it about sexual activity that pre-
determining whether engaging particularily in sexual activity cludes the prostitute from preserving respect for her agency
for payment prevents respect for one’s agency. when she engaging in it with someone for payment?
Arguably, engaging in an activity with someone for payment One argument here starts with the claim that when the pros-
does not in general prevent respect for one’s agency. On the titute engages in sexual activity with someone for payment she
contrary, engaging in an activity with someone for payment, (temporarily) sells her body, and ends with the claim that she
instead of, say, for free or because one is coerced, seems partly thereby treats herself as if she were an object rather than an agent.
to arise out of one’s own respect for one’s agency. The pur- Although there’s a lot more to this argument than meets the
chasing of one’s services also confers respect upon one’s agency. eye, let’s keep things simple and ask, is it true that when some-
When, say, a professional musician requires that she will be one engages in prostitution, she temporarily sells her body?
paid for her work, she does so in part out of respect her own To determine whether it is, let’s first consider what selling
agency. Indeed, a requirement to be paid would be bewilder- things other than one’s body usually involves.
ing (to say the least) if it were not rooted in any way in respect Ordinarily, when someone sells something – say, a bicycle

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 15


Prejudice &
– she requires payment in exchange for the transfer of owner- advanced by some ‘new natural lawyers’ (these are ethicists who
ship of the bicycle from herself to the purchaser. Perhaps what believe in ‘new natural law theory’ rather than practitioners of
the selling of the prostitute’s body involves, then, is the (tem- the law). These philosophers contend that by engaging in sexual
porary) transfer of ownership of her body. I’m confident you activity with someone for payment, the prostitute reduces her
will agree that this is scarcely credible. As countless philoso- bodily self to the level of an instrument for her conscious self,
phers have argued, people, and with them their bodies, do not and thereby blocks her self-integration (what this blocking
seem to be the sorts of beings that can be sold or owned, morally might involve will be addressed shortly).
speaking at any rate. Whatever else the use of the prostitute’s To provide empirical support for the contention that the
body for prostitution might involve, then, the transfer of own- prostitute reduces her bodily self to the level of an instrument,
ership of her body is not a part of it, ostensibly. To be sure, consider the following description of prostitution provided by
the client might end up treating the prostitute as if he owns former prostitute and retired philosophy professor, Yolanda
her body. But that he might do so is no indication of, nor does Estes. Writing of sexual activity between a prostitute and her
it accord him, actual ownership of the prostitute’s body. client, Estes remarks:
Perhaps, then, what the selling of the prostitute’s body
involves is not the temporary transfer of ownership of her body, “[The prostitute’s] yielding to any sensations that might arise in
but the temporary transfer of command over her body. their sexual activity, responding either with frank displeasure or
This transfer of command might be limited or unlimited. with genuine arousal to what is happening in and to her body, jeop-
Beginning with the latter, instead of arguing the issue let’s cut ardizes the integrity of her relationship with the client, others, and
to the chase and suppose that the transfer of unlimited com- herself. To avoid this danger … she must detach herself from the
mand over the prostitute’s body does prevent respect for her bodily events without, for all that, losing control over her body.”
agency. However, this does not commit us to holding that pros- (The Philosophy of Sex, ed. Alan Soble and Nicolas Power, 2008, p.357)
titution prevents respect for a prostitute’s agency, since pros-
titution (usually) does not involve the transfer of unlimited In other words, the prostitute renders her own body an
command over the prostitute’s body. For instance, it is stan- instrument separate from her inner self in order to preserve
dard practice for a prostitute to forbid her client from engag- the necessarily limited, tightly defined nature of her relation-
ing in certain acts – for example, condom-free intercourse – ship with her client as well as to protect herself. But is it true
and to require the client to agree to terminate sexual activity that she thereby blocks her self-integration? And even if she
at her discretion (Women Working, Eileen McLeod, 1982, does, is prostitution thereby immoral?
pp.38-42). Of course, as before, the client might end up treat- In order to answer the first question, clearly we need to know
ing the prostitute as if he has unlimited command over her what self-integration involves. Consider the following exam-
body. But once again, that he might do so is no indication of, ple of a self-integrated act provided by new natural lawyers
nor does it accord him, actual unlimited command over the Robert George and Christopher Tollefsen (written, allow me
prostitute’s body. to stipulate, from George’s perspective):
So does limited command over the prostitute’s body prevent
respect for her agency? Seemingly not. Firstly, limited com- “When I wish to eat an apple, I reach out and take it; I then take a
mands are limited. Accordingly, the client can, and often does, bite. Thus, I see, reach for, touch, and taste the apple. In all these
respect the prostitute’s agency by regulating his command over actions, consciousness – mind – and body are fully integrated. My
the prostitute’s body in accordance with the limits put forward seeing is not like the inner presentation of a picture. My reaching
by the prostitute herself. Failing to do so would be assault. out does not consist of an inner attempt, and then an external reach.
Moreover, requesting that somebody perform certain Nor do touch and taste consist of an external sensation and then an
actions or services in return for payment does not in itself pre- internal one. Internal and external are integrated in all these hap-
vent respect for the seller’s agency, if we disregard for a moment penings.”
the nature of those actions. If it did then, implausibly, virtu- (Embryo: A Defense of Human Life, 2008, p.71)
ally every kind of service would prevent respect for the seller’s
agency. Beauticians, accountants, decorators, surgeons, none According to George, then, his eating this apple involves
could sell their services without preventing respect for their his desiring (conscious component) to eat (bodily component)
agency. But that is very hard to believe. an apple, which gives rise to his eating (bodily component) and
Much more could be said about this version of the instru- tasting (conscious component) an apple, thereby fulfilling his
mentalization argument: for instance, might engaging in sexual desire (conscious component) to do so. In this his conscious
activity with someone for payment be immoral even if one can and bodily components are fully integrated because they func-
rationally agree to do so? But this will have to suffice. tion as an interrelated, harmonious whole: in short, they func-
tion as one.
Prostitution As Self-Disintegration Now consider, instead of the eating of an apple, the actions
Let’s turn now to the second version of the instrumentaliza- that a prostitute performs during sex with a client. Each con-
tion argument, which relies upon understanding ‘instrumen- sists, surely, of a conscious desire to act (conscious component),
talizing oneself’ as being to block, damage, or destroy (here- followed by the physical action itself (bodily component), fol-
after, simply to ‘block’) one’s self-integration. lowed by experiencing (conscious component) and so on. Again,
This version of the instrumentalization argument is the conscious and the physical components of the act are inter-

16 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Perception
performed for the purpose of fulfilling that conscious state and
producing other bodily and conscious states (to appease and to
experience the effects of doing so). So even reluctantly eating
an apple in order to appease a coercer, then, involves conscious
and bodily components that are ostensibly integrated. To be
sure, George’s eating of an apple under such conditions is not
fully voluntary. But this does not seem to block his self-inte-
gration, since an act that is not fully voluntary is not one and
the same as an act that is unfree or disharmonious.
And even if engaging in sexual activity with someone for
payment did block one’s self-integration, it is arguably not
thereby immoral. Or rather, if reducing one’s bodily self to the
level of an instrument for one’s conscious self and thereby
blocking one’s self-integration were immoral, then many activ-
ities we previously believed to be morally permissible would
(implausibly) be immoral too. Take being on the receiving end
of a (non-sexual) massage. Many people do so for the sheer
feeling of it, thus reducing their bodily selves to the level of
instruments for their conscious selves. Is being on the receiv-
twined and integrated into a seamless whole. ing end of a massage thus immoral? If it is, so much the worse
Naturally you might object that, appearances aside, the pros- for this version of the instrumentalization argument, I say.
titute does not, in fact, desire to perform those actions at all; Of course, the individual on the receiving end of a massage
she does so only because she desires the payment that comes may not have to combat responding to it with either “genuine
from doing it. But George and Tollefsen’s example of a self- arousal” or “frank displeasure” and, in turn, be forced to “detach
integrated act says nothing about the strength of or the reason herself from the bodily events without, for all that, losing con-
for George’s desire to eat an apple. Nor should it, I submit, as trol over her body,” as Estes contends the prostitute does. So
neither aspect seems to bear upon whether an act blocks one’s perhaps it is the specific way in which the prostitute reduces
self-integration. her bodily self to the level of an instrument that renders pros-
Regarding the strength of George’s desire to eat an apple, titution immoral. But this, too, is implausible, because this spe-
let’s take the worst-case scenario: that, contrary to the narra- cific way of instrumentalizing oneself is not unique to prosti-
tive; it’s not just that George has no desire to eat an apple, tution. Consider mind-numbingly boring jobs such as paper-
George strongly desires not to eat an apple. Does George block filing, or horribly disgusting jobs such as cleaning portable toi-
his self-integration if he goes ahead and eats one anyway? Not lets. If those who perform such work are to avoid responding
necessarily. If, for example, George desires something that “with frank displeasure” they must, paraphrasing Estes, detach
eating an apple provides, such as nourishment, and he eats an themselves from the bodily events without losing control over
apple in order to fulfil that desire, then it seems his doing so her bodies. Yet there nevertheless seems to be nothing immoral
does not block his self-integration, despite the fact that he about performing either job. And as for responding with gen-
strongly desires not to eat an apple, as it were for its own sake. uine arousal, consider that some theater productions contain
After all, his bodily activity (eating an apple) is a response to scenes involving simulated sexual activity. If the actors are to
his conscious state (the desire for nourishment), performed for avoid responding with genuine arousal (and they should, as a
the purpose of fulfilling that conscious state and producing marvelous scene from the movie Birdman illustrates) they must
other bodily and conscious states (to be nourished and to expe- detach themselves from the bodily events without losing con-
rience the effects of being so). Indeed, if his eating an apple trol over their bodies. Again, there seems to be nothing immoral
under such conditions did block his self-integration, then many about their doing so.
other everyday activities would suddenly turn out to be prob-
lematic for the same reason. For example, many people exer- A Modest Conclusion
cise because they desire something that doing so provides – Much more can be and has been said about the instrumental-
namely, physical health – despite the fact that they otherwise ization argument for the immorality of prostitution, and there
strongly desire not to exercise. But the idea that exercising under are many other arguments for the immorality of prostitution.
these conditions blocks one’s self-integration is implausible. I’ll conclude, then, on a modest note: To the extent that oppo-
As for George’s reason for eating an apple, this, too, seems sition to prostitution is rooted in the above versions of the
not to bear upon his self-integration. Whether he does so to instrumentalization argument for the immorality of prostitu-
acquire nourishment, experience pleasure, or even appease a tion, to that extent we have reasons to be wary of it.
coercer, his doing so does not appear to block his self-integra- © DR R. LOVERING 2017
tion. Let’s consider just the most extreme of these, to appease Rob Lovering is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the College of
a coercer: a fruitarian extremist with a gun who orders George Staten Island, City University of New York. His book A Moral
to eat an apple. George’s bodily activity (eating an apple) is a Defense of Recreational Drug Use is available from Palgrave
response to his conscious state (the desire to appease his coercer), Macmillan.

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 17


Prejudice &
An Education In Diversity?
Christina Easton asks if a liberal education can be forced on non-liberal communities.
he great liberal philosopher John Stuart Mill (1806-

T 1873) declared it “almost a self-evident axiom” that


all children must be educated. Modern liberals tend
to agree that education should be compulsory for
minors in some form. However, here the agreement stops and

BEACHED AMISH © PASTEUR 2007


some seemingly intractable problems arise. Education is seen
as a means to liberty in later life; but what, for instance, should
we say or do when imposing education conflicts with someone’s
present liberties? And how can the liberal be consistent in valu-
ing a diversity of views while advocating compulsory education,
since the moment we state which education must be compul-
sory, we bring in a controversial vision of ‘the good education’,
which may not be agreed upon by all who are forced into it?
Amish at the beach
These issues came to a head in the famous court case of Wis-
consin v. Yoder (1972). A number of Amish parents, represented The trouble with these views is that whilst they are liberal in
by Yoder, objected to the Wisconsin state law that requires the sense of being open to a variety of views of the good life, in
school attendance until age sixteen. The Amish did not object another sense they are deeply illiberal. Although they recognize
to schooling up until fourteen, as this could take place in local that there is disagreement in society about which view of the
Amish schools. But the further two years entailed attending good life to accept, they ignore the fact that there is also dis-
non-Amish High School, exposing the children to an ethos in agreement on the more fundamental question of whether we
conflict with Amish values. Instead of High School, Amish should be valuing autonomy and diversity. So Feinberg justifies
teenagers continued their education informally within the com- a diverse education by appealing to people maximising their
munity in agricultural work for men and domestic work for chances for self-fulfilment, but he assumes that this requires the
women. The court ruled in favour of Yoder, arguing that the exercise of autonomy to pursue diversity. Yet from an Amish per-
Wisconsin law violated the parents’ right to freedom of reli- spective, exposure to diversity could lead to moral compromise
gion by preventing them bringing up their children in the sep- and even rule out eternal fulfilment in the afterlife, and so would
aration and simplicity essential to Amish life. thereby not maximise self-fulfilment. Feinberg’s view is there-
fore far less neutral than he believes. Indeed, Mill’s vision of nur-
Liberal Differences Of Opinion turing “open, fearless characters” is no doubt anathema to Amish
Many liberals think that the court judgment should have gone parents, who generally value submission and meekness. So whilst
the other way. In their view it is justifiable for the state to impose it may be clear to some liberals that exposure to diversity will
a law requiring that Amish children be exposed to diverse values benefit Amish children by enriching their available options, this
and ways of living. In On Liberty (1859), Mill extols the value justification will have little appeal to the Amish themselves. It
of diversity in contributing to society’s long-term happiness: may even appear to them that forced exposure to diversity
just as different environmental conditions are required for the amounts to indoctrination into liberal values.
optimal growth of different plants, so will a variety of ‘experi-
ments of living’ enable different people to be the best that they Public Agreement
can be. Modern liberals use a similar idea to argue that it would The political philosopher John Rawls (1921-2002) argued that
be wrong to assume that Amish children are all the same, and if liberals are really concerned with respecting people in the face
so they need to encounter a variety of options and decide what of disagreement, then any coercive education policy should be
best suits their character. A similar opinion was voiced by Jus- justified with public reasons – reasons which are acceptable to
tice Douglas, delivering the dissenting opinion in court. He the public as a whole, and which therefore do not refer to con-
appealed to “the right of students to be masters of their own troversial views of the good life. He criticised Mill for resting
destiny,” and argued that to keep an Amish child from experi- his liberalism “in a large part on ideals and values that are not
encing High School means “the child will be forever barred generally…shared” (‘The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus’,
from entry into the new and amazing world of diversity that we Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 1987, p.6). So can liberals, in the
have today.” More recently, the legal philosopher Joel Fein- spirit of Rawls, justify exposing children to diversity against the
berg has also argued in favour of the Wisconsin law on the basis will of their parents in a way that appeals only to public reasons?
that the liberal state should be neutral, meaning that it “would Firstly, they might say that if citizens are to get along in spite
act to let all influences, or the largest and most random possi- of their disagreements, there needs to be exposure to diversity.
ble assortment of influences, work equally on the child, to open In order to see disagreement as reasonable – or at least, to see
up all possibilities to him” (Freedom and Fulfillment, 1992, p.85). that those with whom you disagree are not entirely irrational –

18 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Perception
you need to engage with those with whom you disagree. Such
encounters also provide opportunities for the cultivation of

TWO WAYS TO GET THERE © GADJOBOY


mutual respect and solidarity. This appeal to peaceful co-exis-
tence could be seen as a ‘public reason’, for peaceful co-exis-
tence seems to be something that every reasonable person would
want, regardless of their specific views of the good life.
Secondly, Rawls argued that education should develop one’s
ability to “participate in [society’s] institutions”. Being an active
citizen in the democratic process requires at least some basic skills
of rational deliberation; and one important way that these skills are Amish school run
gained is by engaging thoughtfully with different points of view
and people with different values and backgrounds. knowledge be monitored by public examinations. Elsewhere,
Given public reasons such as these, perhaps Rawls would Mill talks about the need for a meaningful right of exit from
argue that the state should override the wishes of Amish par- Mormon communities – which might lead us to think that he
ents for their childrens’ educational isolation. That his view would want Amish children to have an similarily informed aware-
could have such implications is indicated when he writes that ness of alternatives. This might perhaps be fulfilled by the Rum-
“The unavoidable consequences of reasonable requirements for springa, a practice in many Amish communities whereby older
children’s education may have to be accepted, often with regret” teenagers are allowed to leave temporarily to experience alter-
(Political Liberalism, 2005, p.200). native ways of life before making a decision about their future.
Whatever the verdict on Mill, we can still press the point
Rawls versus Mill against Rawls by arguing that the public reason defence for impos-
Liberals today often prefer this Rawlsian-type justification, since ing liberal education can hardly be called ‘neutral’. For the public
by appealing to what all reasonable citizens value it is ‘more reason defence to work, exposure to diversity must be generally
neutral’ than justifications appealing to autonomy and diver- viewed as more important than values that necessitate a life of
sity, and is therefore better able to cope with the disagreement separation. Yet this is precisely what the Amish want to resist.
that is a feature of modern democracies. They may accept the public reasons, but believe these to be out-
“Hold on!” says the defender of Mill: “When Rawls says that weighed by their religious reasons. So justifying the Wisconsin
his liberalism ‘requires far less’ for education than Mill’s liberal- state law by appeal to public reasons might be neutral in avoid-
ism, this implies that Mill has a more demanding view of edu- ing relying on controversial views, but it fails to be fully neutral,
cation. Yet this simply doesn’t fit with what Mill said.” In fact, since it requires rejecting some important Amish beliefs.
Mill didn’t have a precise view of what type of education was
necessary. Rather, he wanted the state to “leave to parents to Changing The Culture
obtain the education where and how they pleased” (On Liberty, Whatever view we take, reflecting on this case helps us realise
1859, Ch. V, para 13). He wanted diversity of education, not the that liberals need to be more cautious in making claims to neu-
education in diversity suggested by the above justifications. Indeed, trality, and more honest about where they fail in this aspiration.
he argued that “A general State education is a mere contrivance We must also make sure that our arguments attend to the real-
for moulding people to be exactly like another” (ibid). ity of the situation. Both the Millian and Rawlsian arguments
One might respond by saying that this isn’t what Mill should invoked the importance of diversity, yet the modern High
have said if he is to be consistent. Indeed, some of Mill’s own School is not simply a melting pot of different ways of life and
comments lead us to think that his minimum education require- an impartial reflector of all values. Rather – as Chief Justice
ments would not be fulfilled by the Amish education in agricul- Burgerpointed out – High Schools tend “to emphasize intel-
tural, carpentry and home-making skills, since he says that chil- lectual and scientific accomplishments, self-distinction, com-
dren should be taught the knowledge required to draw conclu- petitiveness, worldly success, and social life.” Moreover, peer
sions on matters of controversy, and even suggests that such pressure, and, particularly amongst teenagers, the need to con-
form, are likely to promote homogenisation of views. So if lib-
erals are to be able to consistently defend compulsory atten-
dance in state-provided education, school culture would itself
first have to undergo some dramatic changes. Schools would
need to both exhibit and actively promote a diverse range of
PARKING AMISH © JUHA_JOUSI 2012

ways of life, as well as provide opportunities for majority values,


such as individual self-achievement, to be questioned. The chal-
lenge for head teachers and policy-makers is to implement
strategies that protect minorities from extraordinary pressure
to conform without them having to resort to separation.
© CHRISTINA EASTON 2017
Christina Easton is a doctoral researcher in Philosophy at the
London School of Economics. Visit personal.lse.ac.uk/davisce2/ or
Amish shopping trip follow her @ChrEaston.

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 19


What’s So Bad About
Smugness?
Emrys Westacott asks whether it really is a terrible moral failing.
Elaine: “I hate smugness. Don’t you hate smugness?” liberal media, he does not, in fact, really describe smugness.
Cabdriver: “Smugness is not a good quality.” What he describes, and what he finds objectionable, isn’t the
self-satisfaction of liberals who are convinced they are right on
o goes a popular snippet from Seinfeld. In a 2014 arti- issues like climate change, or gay rights. Rather, it’s the con-

S cle in The Guardian titled ‘Smug: The most toxic insult


of them all?’ Mark Hooper opined that “there can be
few more damning labels in modern Britain than
‘smug’.” And CBS journalist Will Rahn declared, in the wake
of Donald Trump’s 2016 electoral victory, that “modern jour-
tempt they show toward Trump supporters whom they dismiss
as racist, sexist, ignorant, and backward. It is possible, of course,
to be smug and arrogant, or smug and contemptuous. But it’s a
mistake to assume that smugness necessarily entails these atti-
tudes. The successful punter described above is smug, but he
nalism’s great moral and intellectual failing [is] its unbearable needn’t display arrogance or feel contempt for those less fortu-
smugness.” nate.
But what is smugness? What, exactly, do people find objec-
tionable about it? And is it really such a terrible moral failing, Why Do People Find Smugness Objectionable?
worthy of being described as “unbearable”? Self-satisfaction and feeling superior to others in some respect
are not in themselves objectionable. In fact, for most of us they
What is Smugness? are often unavoidable. Presumably Einstein felt pretty pleased
The best way to get an initial handle on a concept like smug- with himself when he learned that observations made during
ness is to bring forward a few concrete examples. Here are four: an eclipse in 1919 had vindicated his general theory of relativ-
ity. And ordinary mortals typically feel self-satisfied and supe-
• Someone on a very high income says, “Yes, I am well com- rior when they win a game of Scrabble, earn a promotion, receive
pensated, but I like to think I’ve earned it, and that I’m an award, or are proved right about some disputed piece of trivia.
worth it. As a general rule, I think it’s fair to assume that It would be a stern moralist who would send us to hell for har-
pay reflects merit.” boring such feelings.
Yet ‘smugness’ is clearly a pejorative term. So just what is it
• A parent whose children have been admitted to prestigious about smugness that people find objectionable? This is surpris-
universities, talking to one whose child is at a less selective ingly hard to pin down.
college, says, “It’s nice to know that one’s kids will be taught One might think that smugness is especially unbearable when
by real experts in the field, and that their classmates will be it is unjustified. The proverbial case of the privileged scion born
at their intellectual level.” on third base and thinking he’s hit a triple comes to mind. But
is it really the lack of warrant that galls us here? Consider the
• A punter who has won $500 at the race track backing a rank smug crank who smiles sadly at our blindness to the fact that
outside can’t help smirking at the crestfallen faces of his the end of the world is nigh. He, too, is deluded; but we are
friends who all backed the favorite. more likely to return his pity than view him with moral disfa-
vor. In fact, if we are honest with ourselves, justified smugness
• A couple regularly preen themselves on their healthy and may be harder to take than the kind that rests on self-deception
ecologically responsible eating habits. and illusion. For in the latter case, we have the consolation, or
at least the hope, that history or reality will eventually vindi-
Smugness is not arrogance. Arrogant people typically dis- cate us and pop the smugster’s bubble.
play a sense of their own importance and superiority with little Smugness is perhaps most objectionable when it is episte-
subtlety: they strut; they are dogmatic; they are dismissive of mologically justified but morally inappropriate – in less techni-
others. Smugness shares with arrogance a high degree of self- cal language, when it involves an “I was right and you were
satisfaction and a sense of some kind of superiority over others, wrong and now you’re screwed!” situation. Trivial examples of
but it typically manifests itself quietly and indirectly, without such situations punctuate the interactions of every normal
brashness. Muhammad Ali, who called himself ‘The Greatest’, household (“I did tell you that you were too old for that kind
was undeniably sure about his own superiority as a boxer, and of dancing.”) But it becomes distasteful if the misfortune suf-
he was called many things – arrogant, loud-mouthed, lippy – fered is severe (“I gave up smoking, he didn’t; now he’s got lung
but I don’t recall anyone describing him as smug. cancer and I’m running half-marathons.”) I would say, though,
Nor need smugness involve contempt for others. When Will that in such cases it is not so much the smugness that is repre-
Rahn sets about describing the “unbearable smugness” of the hensible as the lack of that sympathetic concern which ought,

20 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


placency in the body language. Note, though, that this is closer
to an aesthetic objection than to a moral criticism, more like a
complaint about the dorkiness and bad connotations of plus
fours and tweeds rather than an ethical critique of grouse shoot-
ing.
Note, further, just how weak all the above objections to smug-
ness are. Even if the smugness is unjustified, is accompanied by
PLEASE VISIT WORLDOFBOFY.COM

a dose of sinful pride, triggers a few feelings of inadequacy, and


offends our taste, it still seems to be a vice without teeth, doing
no-one any great harm. Indeed, one could go further. What
does it say about me that I am displeased, even angered, by the
mere spectacle of someone enjoying the relatively harmless plea-
sure known as smugness? Wouldn’t I be a better person if this
didn’t upset me, just as I’d be more admirable and happier if I
BEARING CHILDREN IMAGE © BOFY 2017

was free from envy? Better, surely, to be the kind of person who
takes pleasure in the happiness of others so long as it does not
come at another’s expense.

Is Smugness Really So Bad?


These reflections lead naturally to the question: Is smugness
ever really so awful as to be ‘unbearable’ (the adjective to which
it is commonly yoked)? After all, it doesn’t usually do those who
encounter it any actual harm. Nor are smug people prevented
by their smugness from achieving happiness. On the contrary,
happiness surely requires a certain degree of self-satisfaction. A
Woody Allen type, whose only regret in life is that he isn’t some-
body else, will always be discontented.
in a morally healthy individual, to check any inclination to be Imagine this. At your beautiful daughter’s first birthday party
smug. there are many guests, including twelve good fairies who arrive
Smugness, as we have said, involves self-satisfaction and bearing wonderful gifts. Suddenly a thirteenth fairy shows up,
some sense of superiority. This may well be accompanied by, angry that she was not invited, and curses your daughter. “She
and can certainly foster, other failings: most obviously, a lack may be beautiful,” she cries, “but when she is fifteen she will
of humility, and an unwillingness to be self-critical. Here we prick her finger on a spindle and become thoroughly evil!” You
approach familiar moral ground. Thomas Aquinas argued that are horrified. For one’s child to turn out evil is the worst fate
pride is the original sin, the worst sin, and the source of all other imaginable, worse even than their death. But the twelfth fairy,
sins, and numerous theologians have taken the same line. Yet who has not yet bestowed her gift, steps forward and says, “I
smugness, while it is at odds with humility, surely falls far short cannot negate the curse entirely, but I can modify it. Your
of overweening pride. (And we might observe, in passing, that daughter will not become evil; but she will acquire one moral
it is hard to imagine a form of smugness more extreme than that failing that she will have her whole life long. You must choose
of those religious believers who are utterly convinced that they which it is to be from the following list: cruelty, callousness,
number among the blessed while everyone else is damned.) dishonesty, insincerity, cowardice, ungenerosity, unkindness,
Another reason we might object to smugness is that we just bigotry, greed, avarice, sloth, lecherousness, gluttony, or smug-
plain don’t like someone else either being or feeling superior ness.”
to us. This is understandable. It probably has an evolutionary Who wouldn’t choose smugness as the least toxic and the
basis. But notice, it isn’t a moral argument against smugness; most bearable of all these evils?
it’s just an explanation of a psychological fact. The accompany- I am not defending smugness. It may be a minor failing, but
ing moral argument would be that smugness is objectionable it is, admittedly, often an undesirable trait. We should distin-
because it causes others to feel inferior, and feeling inferior is guish, though between actions and feelings. We can work at
an unpleasant experience. This is essentially a utilitarian argu- not exhibiting smugness in our words and deeds; it is much
ment (utilitarians assign a negative value to displeasure) and it harder to avoid feeling smug in some situations, just as it can be
can perhaps be given some weight – although I suspect most hard not to feel envy or jealousy. Still, over time even our feel-
people will actually deny that encountering smugness excites ings can to some extent be trained. And those of us who do suc-
feelings of inferiority in them. ceed in avoiding smugness are surely entitled to feel quite
One could also argue that the smug individual simply pre- pleased with ourselves.
sents us with a displeasing spectacle. I’m inclined to think that © EMRYS WESTACOTT 2017
this is closest to what most of us find objectionable about smug- Emrys Westacott is Professor of Philosophy at Alfred University in
ness. We simply don’t like that self-satisfied smirk, that self- Western New York. His most recent book is The Wisdom of Fru-
congratulatory inflection in the voice, that self-assured com- gality (Princeton University Press, 2016).

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 21


The Rise of the Intelligent Authors
Lochlan Bloom wonders what writers will do when
computers become better writers than humans.
ver the past century the pursuit of facts has come This analysis of the interaction between a reader and a text

O to be the central goal of human progresss, with the


dominant perception being that facts are important
while fiction is at best superfluous. Yet there is
increasing evidence that we as humans live our lives in a realm
of fictions. It seems we are preconditioned to accept stories and
will only get more finessed as we add more readers and more
computing power into the system. As Harari writes in a Finan-
cial Times article, “Soon, books will read you while you are read-
ing them. And whereas you quickly forget most of what you
read, computer programs need never forget” (August 26th,
embed them in the deepest fabric of our societies – for exam- 2016). Soon the algorithms will know exactly which tracts push
ple, stories of nationhood, society, economics, or religion. And your buttons. They will know what you enjoy reading better
yet the ability to determine facts is now normally seen as the than you do. Whether you want a thrilling yarn about swords
more vital human trait: facts are important, fiction is superflu- and sorcery, or a enlightening philosophical novel, developed
ous. Reading a book or watching a film of an evening is some- AI will understand precisely which stories you will react to, and
thing to do to relax after a hard day of productivity, a hard day will be able to tailor recommendations to you personally.
discerning the facts in whatever area of work you are engaged.
But as the philosopher-historian Yuval Noah Harari claims The Next Step for Authorship
in an interview, “We cooperate with millions of strangers if and If we take this thought even further, we can see it is not unlikely
only if we all believe in the same fictional stories. The human that once these machine learning tools become available we will
superpower is really based on fiction. As far we know we are then set about re-engineering them so that the machines become
the only animal that can create and believe in fictional stories. the authors themselves. The algorithms may not ‘understand’
And all large scale human cooperation is based on fiction” what they are writing, but they will be able to calculate exactly
(youtube.com/watch?v=JJ1yS9JIJKs). what to write to engage our interest, and will construct person-
Here I want to argue that the coming rise of artificial intel- alised novels accordingly.
ligence presents a threat to our way of life not only because it In November 2016 Google announced upgrades to its Trans-
is very likely we will become much worse than machines at late service which bring it closer than ever to the way humans
determining facts, but also because we will, in all likelihood, use language – analyzing text at the phrase level rather than word
become worse than machines at creating fictions. by word. As Barak Turovsky, product lead at Google Translate,
wrote in a blog post, “Neural translation is a lot better than our
Recommendations for the Useless previous technology, because we translate whole sentences at a
Machine learning algorithms connected to global networks of time, instead of pieces of a sentence… This makes for transla-
sensors and data sources will increasingly outperform us when tions that are usually more accurate and sound closer to the way
it comes to assessing what is factually correct, whether that relates people speak the language.”
to stock market movements, the best way to run a company, or Once this approach is refined and improved it is certainly not
the emotional state of a person. At present it takes professionals implausible that a machine would be able to produce a whole
years of training to identify facts within their profession, and to book. What’s more, a machine could write a book virtually instan-
understand what is a real issue and what is not. So if in the future taneously. It could write a hundred books. Millions. One for
nobody is trained because machines can analyse the information every customer on demand. An endless series of sequels tailored
better than any human, how then could anyone sensibly discuss just for you. A made-to-measure novel for your individual per-
what is fact and what not?In relation to this Yuval Noah Harari sonality right now; your ideal read for your mood at the time.
talks about the rise of a ‘useless class’ incapable of doing any- In these circumstances it would be impossible for any human
thing better than machines; and although there is no certainty author to compete commercially. What author could possibly
how technology will play out, it seems undeniable that in future make a living? How would a human author produce a best-seller,
a huge majority of people, from radiographers to economists, when a machine can produce a million perfectly designed per-
will not be needed to do the sort of fact-based jobs we do today. sonalised novels in a fraction of the time? The algorithm will
This shift is also likely to be radical when it comes to the most know what you have already read, what you yearn for, what will
commonly accepted form of fiction, the novel. appear new and fresh to you, and what will appear stale. Who
Already we are approaching a state where a machine’s under- would even bother reading the less personalised work? Well,
standing of what we read is beyond that of the author in many there may be a sub-culture that enjoys artisanal books, hand-
areas. Amazon can already collect data from millions of Kin- crafted by a human author; but ultimately those books will just
dles and analyse how a particular reader interacts with a text not be as enjoyable to read. What then would be the purpose of
in terms of which bits we read quickly and where we slow down writing fiction in a world where machines can do it so much
or stop, and extrapolate this data to provide recommendations better? Will that bring an end to the human desire to create fic-
based on our personality. tion through the act of writing?

22 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


PLEASE VISIT WWW.STEVELILLIE.BIZ
AUTHORS OLD & NEW © STEVE LILLIE 2017
An Axe for the Frozen Sea Within head, what are we reading for? So that it will make us happy, as you
“The fact is that poetry is not the books in the library... Poetry is the write? Good Lord, we would be happy precisely if we had no books,
encounter of the reader with the book, the discovery of the book.” and the kind of books that make us happy are the kind we could write
Jorge Luis Borges, Poetry (1977) ourselves if we had to. But we need books that affect us like a disas-
ter, that grieve us deeply, like the death of someone we loved more
One possibility is that we will utilize the tools provided by than ourselves, like being banished into forests far from everyone,
AI to forge a new form of writing. After all, the writing process like a suicide. A book must be the axe for the frozen sea within us.
is not about becoming better at typing, or copy-editing, or learn- That is my belief.”
ing a series of plot rules or character development concepts. It Franz Kafka, Letter to Oskar Pollak, 27th January 1904
is (or should be) about precisely those things that machines are
now improving at – pushing our emotional buttons. The ques- The technology will soon have the power to enable the more
tion is not whether the machines will become better than adventurous readers to craft their own path through a con-
humans at eliciting a given response, which we assume they will, stantly evolving literature. With the aid of computer tools,
but which responses we choose the machines to elicit; and so I people could even write their own sacred texts, their own books
suggest that the job of the author in the AI age will be determin- of awakenings. Imagine if every book you read gave you a
ing the best sets of responses to aim to create. For some the novels moment of awakening – provided the axe to the frozen sea
they choose will be potboilers, containing formulaic, unchal- inside – instead of spending hours ploughing through books
lenging thrills; but for others – those seeking an epiphany or a that you realize too late are a waste of time. This can happen
deeper consciousness of the world – the tools to create machine if our reading habits themselves became part of the act of cre-
written fiction will be a core part of literature and their explo- ation – an organic never-ending exploration of the possibility
ration of consciousness. of language.
© LOCHLAN BLOOM 2017
“I think we ought to read only the kind of books that wound or stab Lochlan Bloom is a British novelist, screenwriter and short story
us. If the book we're reading doesn't wake us up with a blow to the writer. His debut novel The Wave is out now.

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 23


Santa Claus & the Problem of Evil
Jimmy Alfonso Licon engages in a little Santodicy for Christmas.
here are many profound philosophical issues involv- that suffering is the product of people exercising their free will;

T ing Santa. For example, we might wonder how we


know that Santa doesn’t exist. That is, although it
seems obvious that there is no Santa, the reasons
usually given for this disbelief are less sound than is often appre-
ciated. In this article I want to explore an argument against
after all, if humans have the ability to choose between good and
evil actions, then some of them will choose to do evil. And
because the ability to choose, even if the choice is evil, is
supremely valuable, God must not interfere; if He did, then it
would undermine the value of freely making good choices. For
Santa that shares a number of features with the problem of evil example, we think that people who are compelled to do the right
that has long troubled theologians. This argument against Santa thing are not morally praiseworthy; they are only praiseworthy
is one way we can know that he doesn’t exist, but without the if they could have chosen to do evil, but chose the good instead.
same vulnerabilities that the usual reasons have. The main thrust of the problem involves there being many
instances of suffering that don’t seem to do a bit of good for
Bad Arguments Against Santa anyone. The philosopher William Rowe famously gave this
First let’s survey some of the usual reasons people give for think- example: “Suppose that in a forest somewhere, there is a fawn
ing that there is no Santa. that has been struck by lightning. She lies on the forest floor for
Some say that disproving the Santa belief is a simple matter a couple of days in agony, until death relieves her suffering”
of visiting the North Pole and looking for him. There would (‘The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism’, Ameri-
be no Santa to be found. However, it could be that Santa’s work- can Philosophical Quarterly 16 (4), 1979). If there is a perfectly
shop is disguised to avoid detection, even by the most sophisti- good God, then it would be in His nature to prevent needless
cated methods; after all, Santa is supposedly capable of doing suffering; and if He is all-powerful, then He would be able to
all sorts of other extraordinary things. So, even if Santa resided prevent it. So why doesn’t He?
there, he might not be easily detected. The problem of evil is only a mystery if there really is such a
Others say that it would be impossible for Santa to deliver person as God. The problem we explore in the next section has a
gifts to children around the globe within the space of a single similar structure: it is only a mystery why there are vast num-
night. This is only a difficulty if we think that Santa is an ordi- bers of good children who receive no gifts whatsoever if there
nary human. But that can’t be right. Santa cannot be merely really is such a person as Santa.
human; after all, he relies on flying reindeer for transportation!
If Santa had extraordinary powers, then he might be able deliver Santa and the Problem of Moral Desert
gifts, the world over, in such a short time. We might for exam- We should start with the essential nature of Santa; that is, the prop-
ple suppose that Santa has the ability to slow down time. erties that an individual must have if they are to qualify as Santa.
Other people might object that clearly, guardians and family One plausible essential property of Santa is that he distributes
members provide the gifts come Christmas time. Unfortunately, gifts on the basis of moral desert. When philosophers use the term
while they’re often responsible for buying the gifts, this is insuf- ‘moral desert’, they mean what people deserve based on their
ficient to prove that all gifts come from them. However, the actions. For example, it is plausible that someone who robs a bank
claim is not that Santa is the only source of gifts at Christmas. deserves to be punished: there is a sense in which they’ve earned
Rather, Santa is only supposed to be the source of some gifts. their punishment. So it is also plausible to suppose that an essen-
So, although we know that there is no Santa, it is less obvi- tial property of Santa is that he rewards good children with gifts,
ous how we know this is so. This situation of not knowing how but doesn’t so reward naughty children. There’s some evidence
you know is quite common. For example, you might know that for this suggestion in popular culture, for example, in the lyrics
it’s going to rain in the morning, but without having any idea from the song ‘Santa Claus is Coming to Town’:
why it’s going to rain. But after reviewing the problem of evil,
I’ll argue that a similar problem provides a good reason for how “He sees you when you’re sleeping; he knows when you’re awake.
we know there is no Santa. He knows if you’ve been bad or good, so be good for goodness sake.”

The Problem of Evil So Santa is essentially someone who delivers gifts to children
Philosophers right back to Epicurus (341-270 BC) have grap- based on whether they deserve them. Thus we should expect that
pled with the problem of whether it’s possible to reconcile the the distribution of gifts come Christmas morning would respect
existence of widespread and horrendous evil (plagues, torture, the moral desert of the recipient if there were a Santa. Suppose then
genocide...) with the existence of an all-powerful, perfectly that only bad children received gifts. This unfair pattern of gift
benevolent God. distribution would then itself be good reason to suppose that
Atheists hold that needless suffering is good reason to doubt there was no Santa.
that there is an all-powerful, perfectly good God. But theists However, there’s a catch. If you recall, I said that part of our
have a number of responses to the problem of evil. Some argue conception of Santa is that he’s responsible only for some of the

24 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


gifts that children receive. Children on the naughty list don’t such a prediction is false.
receive gifts from him; and yet many of them receive gifts
anyway. So, with respect to the distribution of gifts among chil- The appeal to mystery and magic, even if correct, shouldn’t
dren, there is a confounding factor: parents who give their give do much to shake our confidence in either (1) or (2).
their children gifts even if they are naughty. Second, if the appeal to mystery and magic were compelling
To correct for this factor, we have to focus on whether there enough to overcome our evidence for (1) and (2), then it would
are good children who don’t receive any gifts whatsoever. That is, also be compelling enough to defeat nearly any claim we could
we would predict that if Santa exists, then good children would at make about Santa. That is, if he is so mysterious that his reasons
least receive gifts from him. But instead we find that there are mil- are beyond comprehension, then nearly all Santa-talk would be
lions of good children around the world who receive nothing. unfounded: in other words, if we don’t understand Santa’s moti-
We might formulate the argument as follows: vations at all, then it’s difficult to say anything about him with-
out the possibility that it be contradicted by something we don’t
A. If there is a Santa, then all deserving children would receive know. But we seem to say all kinds of things about Santa. So
something for Christmas. there isn’t much reason to take this kind of objection seriously.
B. But there are plenty of deserving children who receive noth- In conclusion, although there are a number of reasons people
ing for Christmas. So, give for how they know there is no Santa, many of these rea-
C. There is no such person as Santa. sons are not as convincing as they first appear. However, if we
put the issue in terms similar to the problem of evil, then there
So the pattern of distribution of gifts among good children is a more fruitful way to think about how we can know that there
is a serious evidential challenge to Santa’s existential status. is no Santa. Hopefully, this exercise is also a reminder that issues
which we think are mundane or obvious, are often less so upon
Problems with the Problem closer examination.
Someone might respond that around the holiday season it is © JIMMY ALFONSO LICON 2017
common to find in a shopping mall a Santa asking children what Jimmy Alfonso Licon is a philosophy doctoral student at the Univer-
they want for Christmas, without regard for whether they have sity of Maryland, College Park. He works primarily in epistemology,
been bad or good. This could imply that delivering gifts to chil- metaethics, and Santology.
dren because they’re children might instead be central to our con-
ception of Santa. If so, this would be a difficulty for the argu- • Thanks to Glen Licon (my brother) for helpful feedback on
ment against Santa from moral desert. If part of our concep- an earlier draft.
tion of Santa is that he delivers gifts indiscriminately, then the
fact that Santa doesn’t appear to be responsive to moral desert
does not count against the existence of Santa.
However, another feature of our shared conception of Santa
is that, just as in the mall case, he indiscriminately inquires of
every child what they want for Christmas. Santa is fair to every
child that he meets, in that he gives them each a chance to feel
that they’ve been heard, and perhaps it is also an opportunity
to remind them that they should be good if they are to expect
any gifts from him. But notice that asking children what they
want, and actually delivering it, are very different.
Perhaps someone else might object that there’s so much
about Santa that we don’t understand, and he might have com-
pelling reasons for not delivering gifts to some good children.
That is, although he usually delivers gifts to good children, there
are other mitigating reasons that might override him doing so;
however, because Santa is so mysterious, we would be unable
to comprehend those reasons (some theists say similar things
about God in response to the problem of evil).
There are a couple of problems with this objection.
First, while aspects of our modern conception of Santa allow
that he is mysterious and magical, this doesn’t seem relevant to
evaluating the problem of moral desert.
That problem is comprised of two components:

(1) The prediction we would make if Santa were real as to the


pattern of Christmas gift distribution among good children
based on Santa’s desert-respecting nature.
(2) The empirical evidence from our everyday experience that

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 25


Kant &

RON SCHEPPER 2017 (YOU CAN CONTACT HIM AT EDITOR@TEXTURA.ORG)


The Human
Subject

COVER ART BY
Brian Morris compares the ways

KANT & SKULL: PHILOSOPHY NOW


Kant’s question “What is the human
being?” has been answered by
philosophers and anthropologists.

ccording to many recent texts, anthropology is the the human subject by studying anthropology, (ethnography),

A study of ‘what it means to be human’. This was


Immanuel Kant’s definition of anthropology, and
Kant (1724-1804) was one of the founding ancestors
of the discipline, along with Rousseau, Herder, and Ferguson.
Drawing on the insights of both the Enlightenment and
sociology, psychology, ethology, and now evolutionary biology,
than by engaging in speculative academic philosophy about
human beingness, in the style of Husserl, Heidegger, or Derrida.
Throughout history, and in all cultures, people have
responded to Kant’s fundamental question ‘What is the human
romanticism, anthropology has since its birth had a ‘dual her- being?’ in very diverse ways; even denying that humans have
itage’ (Maurice Bloch) combining humanism and naturalism. In any relation with the material world, as extreme gnostics do.
terms of method, it combines scientific explanations of social and Or Hare Krishna devotees exclaim, ‘You are not your body’.
cultural phenomena with hermeneutics or biosemiotics. Yet Indeed, there has been a long tradition in Western philosophy
although certain people write of some great divide or schism that identifies the subject/self with consciousness. Anthropolo-
within anthropology, it has always had, in spite of its diversity, a gists have long emphasized and illustrated the diversity of cul-
certain unity of vision and purpose. It employs a universal per- tural conceptions of the human subject (see my Anthropology of
spective that places humans firmly within nature. Anthropology the Self, Pluto, 1994); but even within the Western intellectual
has therefore always placed itself at the interface between the tradition there exists an absolute welter of studies that have
humanities and the natural sciences, especially evolutionary biol- attempted to define or conceptualize the human subject in dif-
ogy. In many ways it is an inter-discipline, held together by plac- ferent ways. Western responses to Kant’s fundamental ques-
ing an emphasis on ethnographic studies, which involve a close tion have been extremely diverse and contrasting, and I want
experiential encounter with a particular way of life or culture. to briefly discuss three approaches: the essentialist, the dualist,
Both Karl Popper and Mario Bunge described anthropology as and the Kantian triadic ontology of the subject.
the key social science, for it is unique among the human sciences
in putting an emphasis on cultural differences (Herder). This The Human Essence
means it can offer a cultural critique of much of Western culture The first approach tends to define the human subject or self in
and philosophy, while at the same time emphasizing our shared terms of a single essential attribute. The following essentialist
humanity (Kant), thus enlarging our sense of moral community. characterizations of humanity are well known: Homo economicus
Kant suggested that the most important question in philoso- (‘economic man’), Homo faber (‘the tool-making primate’), Homo
phy was not that of truth (epistemology), goodness (ethics), or sapiens (‘wise man’), and Homo ludens (‘man the player’). Aristo-
beauty (aesthetics) – the topics which so fascinate academic tle famously defined humanity as Zoon logon echon – ‘the animal
philosophers – but rather the anthropological question, ‘What is endowed with reason’. (The tendency to group Aristotle
the human being?’ He also suggested that this question could together with the likes of Descartes, Kant and Heidegger as an
only be answered empirically, and not by resorting to, say, meta- advocate of a dualistic metaphysic is, however, somewhat mis-
physics. This implies, of course, that we can learn more about placed, because Aristotle, as Ernst Mayr always insisted, was

26 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


fundamentally a biological thinker. Aristotle certainly knew a
lot more about the diversity of animal life than did the preten-
tious Jacques Derrida and his cat.) Robert Ardrey, in contrast,
defined humanity as the ‘killer ape’; while Julien La Mettrie
and Richard Dawkins seem to envisage the human person as
simply a biological machine. A more recent controversial
account of humans depicts them in rather Hobbesian fashion
as a wholly predatory and destructive animal: Homo rapiens (John
Gray). Such misanthropy is debatable, and is simply an update
of Friedrich Nietzsche’s notion that humans are a ‘pox’ on a
beautiful earth. Many twentieth century deep ecologists have
expressed the same negative sentiments, that humans are ‘aliens’
or ‘parasites’ on the rest of the biosphere; and thus famines, the
AIDS epidemic, and malaria, were extolled as a way of reduc-
ing the human population. Such anti-humanism was long ago
critiqued by the social ecologist Murray Bookchin.
The list of what is deemed to be the essential characteristic
of the human species seems virtually endless. But significantly,
such interpretations based on a single essential characteristic
tend to gravitate to two extremes. On the one hand, there are
those scholars who firmly believe in the existence of a univer-
sal human nature or essence. Generally adopting a highly indi-
vidual-centered approach, the human subject is thus defined
either as a purely rational ego (as with rational choice theo-
rists), or as having innate tendencies and dispositions – as having
a universal nature that was forged through natural selection
processes during the Palaeolithic, when humans were hunter-
gatherers. Thus humans have a nature, and it is fundamentally
tribal, as Robin Fox puts it.
On the other hand, many other scholars, particularly cul-
tural anthropologists, existentialists and postmodernists, deny
that humans have an essence or nature. Such scholars often
suggest that in becoming human beings, through the develop-
ment of language, symbolic thought, self-consciousness, and
complex sociality, we have moved beyond nature to become
free of the chains of our instincts. We have become, in Ernst
Cassirer’s term, Homo symbolicum. Such a conception has often
been critiqued (by, for instance, Steven Pinker), as it implies
that the human mind is simply a ‘blank slate’ which has com-
pletely effaced human biological history and the inherited spe-
cific faculties of the human brain, and therefore, mind.

Homo Duplex
It has also long been recognized that humans are fundamen-
tally both natural and cultural beings, and that language, self-
identity, and social existence are interconnected, and have been
throughout human history. As Kenan Malik emphasized,
human nature is as much a product of our historical develop-
ment as it is of our biological heritage. Emile Durkheim
famously expressed this dualistic conception of human subjec-
tivity as Homo duplex when he wrote:

“Man is double. There are two beings in him; an individual being


which has its foundation in the organism, and a social being which
represents the highest reality in the intellectual and moral order”
(The Elementary Forms of Religious Life, 1915).

Like his mentor, Auguste Comte, Durkheim allowed little


scope for a science of psychology, let may develop. This sensibility is mani-
alone any existentialist thought. fested in a predilection for abstraction
It has long been recognized, by and geometric patterns, a flight from the
thinkers as diverse as Edmund Husserl, body, a feeling of fragmentation, a lack
Erich Fromm, and Lewis Mumford, that of empathy for others (egoism), and
there is an essential ‘paradox’ or ‘contra- alienation from the natural world – the
diction’ at the heart of human life. For postmodern condition, or the
humans as organisms are an intrinsic part schizophrenic personality lauded by
of nature, while at the same time, through Gilles Deleuze?
our conscious experience, symbolic life, What tends to be downplayed or even
and above all, our culture, we are also in ignored in dualistic conceptions of the
a sense separate from nature. In this light human subject is human uniqueness and
humans have been described by Ray- agency. It might therefore be helpful to
mond Tallis as an ‘explicit animal’. We return to Kant and his more complex tri-
have what Cicero described as a ‘second adic conception of the human subject.
nature’. This duality or dialectic is well
expressed in the famous painting in the A Triadic Ontology
Vatican by Raphael, The School of Athens, Through his philosophical writings and
which depicts Plato pointing up to the Plato and Aristotle by Raphael with regard to his profound influence on
heavens while Aristotle points down to subsequent scholarship, Immanuel Kant
the earth. imagery, pre-linguistic thought, synthe- has rightly been acclaimed as one of the
Human duality is also reflected in the sis, patterns and relations, things in con- key figures in the history of Western
fact that the human brain is composed of text, and organic life. Reason, science, thought. He had a deep interest in the
two distinct hemispheres, with distinct creativity and selfhood all involve both natural sciences, particularly physical
functions, and two very different ways of sides of the brain, and there is no simple geography, but what is less well known
being in the world. The left hemisphere relationship between the hemispherical is that he also gave lectures in anthropol-
is associated with language, symbolic differences and ethnic, class or gender ogy for more than twenty years. We are
thought, analysis, facts or things in iso- affiliations. It is significant however that told by his student Johann Herder that
lation, focussed attention, and the non- if the right side of the brain is severely the lectures were in the nature of hugely
living aspects of the world; while the right damaged, the left side becomes overac- entertaining talks. At the age of seventy-
hemisphere is associated with visual tive, and an ultra-rationalist sensibility four Kant published Anthropology from a


Human duality is
also reflected in
the fact that the
human brain is
composed of two
distinct hemi-
spheres, with
distinct functions,
and different
ways of being in
the world.
ALLAN AJIFO / CREATIVE COMMONS (CC BY 2.0)

28 Philosophy Now
”  December 2017/January 2018
Pragmatic Point of View (1798). (By ‘pragmatic’, he meant the Photography In The 18th Century
use of knowledge to widen the scope of human freedom and to
advance the dignity of humankind.) Kant, that austere, stay-at-home philosopher
In this seminal text Kant suggested that there were three dis- from back in his eighteenth century enlightenment
tinct, but interrelated, ways of understanding the human sub- would really have liked cameras,
ject: firstly as a universal species-being (mensch) – the “earthly and not just because they demonstrate
being endowed with reason” on which Kant’s anthropological how our kit, biological and mechanical,
work was mainly focussed; secondly as a unique self (selbst); and determines if we see the flower petals in his matrix of
thirdly as part of a people – as a member of a particular social a world
group (volk). (Notwithstanding the last element, Herder always as luminescent symbols of god or grainy sets of
insisted that Kant, with his emphasis on universal human fac- washed out flakes.
ulties such as imagination, perception, memory, feelings, desires
and understanding, tended to downplay the importance of lan- No, it would have shaken him
guage, poetry and cultural diversity in understanding human from the slumber of his circumscribed ways,
life. But as a pioneer anthropologist, Herder also emphasized so predicable town clocks were set to his daily walk.
that anthropology, not speculative metaphysics or logic, was Imagine him with a new interest in photography
the key to understanding humans and their life-world, that is, playfully dancing out at any time of day
their culture.) hiding behind some flowering shrub
Long ago the anthropologist Clyde Kluckhohn, following in knee-length hosiery and buckled shoes,
Kant, made a statement that is in some ways rather banal but digital Canon or Nikon in hand,
which has always seemed to me to encompass an important happily snapping startled passersby;
truth. Critical of dualistic nature-culture conceptions of the or sneaking up on shopkeepers,
human subject, Kluckhohn, along with the pioneer psycholo- shiny goods piled high behind them,
gist Henry Murray, suggested that every person is, as a species- detecting and then revealing with candid shots
being (a human) in some respects like every other person; but their cheating ways and hidden dodgy fruit,
they are also all like no other human being in having a unique all their secretest secrets,
personality (or self); and, finally, that they have affinities with shutter sound loud, flash bright
some other humans in being a social and cultural being (or to get the full paparazzi effect.
person). These three categories relate to three levels or pro-
cesses in which all humans are embedded; namely, the phylo- Every month on forays far beyond his home town
genetic, pertaining to the evolution of humans as a species- he’d trade in a lens or two for some higher spec:
being; the ontogenetic, which relates to the life history of the faster, wider, longer.
person within a specific familial and biological setting; and, Once in a while there’d be a brand new body
finally, the socio-historical, which situates the person in a spe- with more pixels to its sensor
cific social-cultural context. So Kluckholm, not unlike Kant, because, like you and me, he greedily craves
thought human beings need to be conceptualized in terms of the lure of an ever-greater approximation to reality,
three interconnected aspects: as a species-being characterized by whatever that may be.
biopsychological dispositions and complex sociality; as a unique
individual self; and finally, as a social being or person, enacting But after a while perhaps the Königsberg aldermen
social identities or subjectivities – which in all human societies would tire of seeing their moles and deformities
are multiple, shifting and relational. For an anthropologist like magnified around town in posters churned out for our
Kluckhohn the distinction between being a human individual moralist by the local apothecary.
and being a person was important, for many tribal people rec- With not a wisp of understanding the irony
ognize non-human persons, while under chattel slavery, the that they’d caught him out in some illogical anomaly,
law treated human slaves not as persons, but rather as things they’d arraign him on charges of behaving in ways
or commodities. that treated others as mere images
for his own selfish pleasure;
Conclusion and at the end of the lawsuit
Anthropologists within different cultural configurations tend the judge in exasperation would intone,
to highlight one of three aspects of human subjectivity. Neo- “Immanuel, where would we be if everyone spent
Darwinian scholars, for example – particularly evolutionary their time in such a useless pursuit?”
psychologists and sociobiologists – invariably focus on the Then in response to furtive clickings
human subject as a species-being. Emphasizing genetic or bio- from behind the philosopher’s gown
logical factors, they tend to downplay or ignore existential and he’d shout with cold command and withering frown
social factors in understanding the human subject. In contrast, “For God’s sake man, put that camera down!”
existentialists, radical phenomenologists, and literary anthro- © PETER KEEBLE 2017
pologists, put a fundamental emphasis on the unique self and Peter is a retired local government research officer and
subjective experience – Derrida’s ‘autobiographical animal’ – teacher, much of whose poetry makes use of philosophy.

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 29


Philosophical Haiku
and thus tend to completely ignore the important insights to
be derived from evolutionary biology and historical sociol-
ogy. Finally there is a group of scholars who emphasize to an
extreme that the human person is fundamentally a socio-cul-
tural being. This kind of approach is exemplified by
Durkheimian sociology, American cultural anthropology –
well reflected in the writings of Leslie White, who famously
suggested that we should study culture as if human beings did
not exist – as well as the structuralism of Claude Levi-Strauss
and Louis Althusser. It’s a current of thought that interprets
human cognition as largely determined by sociocultural fac-
tors; or, as with the postmodernists, as simply an effect of dis-
courses. It thus downplays the relevance of biological and eco-
logical factors in human life, with some scholars virtually deny-
ing human agency. They have what Dennis Wrong long ago
described as an “oversocialized conception of man.” How-
ever, each of the three approaches to the human subject – the
biological, the psychological, and the sociocultural – have a
certain validity, and a fundamental part to play in answering
the question ‘What is the human being?’ They are of limited
LAOZI effectiveness, however, if interpreted in an exclusive fashion.
(Pre-Fourth Century BCE) What is needed is an approach that integrates all three per-
spectives, since a host of causal mechanisms and generative
Going with the flow processes – biological, ecological, psychological, social and
Being at one with nature
cultural – go into making up a human being.
The way of the Dao
Throughout the twentieth century, many scholars, within
diverse intellectual traditions, did develop a more integrated

L
aozi, often written Lao Tzu – the name simply means ‘Old
Master’ – has the distinction amongst great philosophers of approach to the understanding of the human subject, recog-
probably never having existed. Still, having an uncertain exis- nizing, like Kant, the need to develop a more complex model
tence hasn't prevented his being revered by many as a deity of the subject. The sociologist Marcel Mauss, for example, in
(which is pretty much the case with God). Laozi is reputedly the author contrast to Durkheim’s concept of Homo duplex, conceptual-
of the great text of Daoism, the Dao De Ching or Tao Te Ching (Treatise ized the human subject as l’homme total, conceived as a biolog-
on the Way and Its Power). Tradition holds that Laozi lived in the sixth ical, psychological and social being; a living being with inher-
century BCE; but it might’ve been the fifth century… or the fourth (it’s ent capacities and powers and a unique self constituted through
a moot point, really, when you’re talking about someone who possibly diverse social relationships. Likewise, within the pragmatist
didn’t live at all). Whenever it was he did or didn’t live, he was certainly tradition, George Herbert Mead and C. Wright Mills empha-
esteemed, and given the title of ‘Supreme Mysterious and Primordial sized that the human being was simultaneously a biological
Emperor’, idolised by both nobility and the ordinary riff-raff. Clearly, organism, a self with a fundamentally social psychic structure,
having an uncertain existence doesn’t prevent his being revered by and a person embedded within a specific historical context.
many as a deity (that’s also pretty much the case with God). All sorts of The Marxist phenomenologists Maurice Merleau-Ponty and
legends surround the legendary Old Master, including the story that he Herbert Marcuse, the Neo-Freudian scholars Erich Fromm
gave the Buddha a few hints on how to live. and Erik Erikson (who attempted a synthesis between psycho-
Laozi (supposedly) taught that the world consists of opposites – light analysis and, respectively, Marxism or anthropology), and the
and dark, hot and cold, male and female – and that the underlying princi- cultural anthropologists Clyde Kluckhohn, Irving Hallowell
ple of the natural world is reversion: if things go too far to one extreme, and Melford Spiro, have all attempted, in various ways, to
they’ll swing back the other in due course, like a pendulum (possibly flat- convey the complex triadic nature of human subjectivity. The
tening you along the way past). The best way for us to live is to be in accor- postmodernist mantra that with the developments in biotech-
dance with this natural order, that is, in accordance with the Dao, which is nology and computer science (the web) we are ‘humans no
the natural flow of the universe, merging ourselves as fully as we can with more’ – the title of a recent text – is pure reverie [dream], to
nature. Time and effort shouldn’t be wasted in pursuing worldly posses- use a term of that rather neglected French scholar Gaston
sions – inevitably these lead only to loss and suffering. Instead we should Bachelard.
endeavour to be meek, mild, and have as few desires as possible. Rest assured, humans are still around, and anthropology is
For reasons which escape me, this is not a philosophy that appeals still a flourishing (inter-)discipline.
much to the current Western mind. © PROF. BRIAN MORRIS 2017
© TERENCE GREEN 2017 Brian Morris is emeritus professor of Anthropology at Goldsmiths,
Terence is a writer, historian and lecturer, and lives with his wife University of London. His latest book is An Environmental History
and their dog in Paekakariki, NZ. hardlysurprised.blogspot.co.nz of Southern Malawi.

30 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Defending Humanistic Reasoning
Paul Giladi, Alexis Papazoglou, & Giuseppina D’Oro say we need to recognise
that science and the humanities are asking and answering different questions.
he year is 399 BCE. Socrates has just been sentenced events dictated by natural laws. Our curiosity is satisfied when,

T to death by his fellow Athenians for allegedly cor-


rupting the youth of Athens. Sitting in his cell,
Socrates is asked by his friends to explain why he
remains in prison instead of escaping to exile.
How should Socrates’ explain it? Should he provide a phys-
rather than treating them as simply another material entity, the
explanation enables us to see the purpose of their action. Pro-
viding an account of their physiology here would not adequately
make sense of their actions.
The two varieties of explanation appear to compete, because
ical explanation; that is, an account of his bodily movements? both give rival explanations of the same action. But there is a
Or should he provide a different kind of explanation – one that way in which scientific explanations such as bodily movements
makes reference not to his physiology, but to his reasons for and humanistic explanations such as motives and goals need not
acting? Let’s have a look at the following passage from Plato’s compete. Our aim in this article is to introduce you to a highly
Phaedo to see Socrates explain the difference between the two neglected tradition in the philosophy of mind, which we’ll call
kinds of explanation: epistemological idealism, to see how scientific and humanistic
explanations can co-exist. This form of idealism is called ‘epis-
“in trying to give the causes of the particular thing I do, I should say temological’ to highlight that it has nothing to do with meta-
first that I am now sitting here because my body is composed of physical idealism, the claim that reality is made of ‘mental stuff’.
bones and sinews, and the bones are hard and have joints which divide Instead, epistemological idealism recognises that when it comes
them and the sinews can be contracted and relaxed and so... make to our explanations of reality, the aims and methods we apply
me able to bend my limbs now, and that is the cause of my sitting reflect something about our minds, rather than simply being
here with my legs bent… [But then I] should fail to mention the real about the way the world is independently of us.
causes, which are, that the Athenians decided that it was best to con-
demn me, and therefore I have decided that it was best for me to sit Scientific Naturalisms
here and that it is right for me to stay and undergo whatever penalty Since the late nineteenth century, Western philosophy has
they order.” (98c-e) adopted increasingly naturalistic views. In current Anglo-Ameri-
can philosophy, the norm is to assume a reductive form of this
Or to use another example: Why did Caesar cross the Rubi- naturalism which claims that everything can be explained just in
con? Because of his leg movements? Or because he wanted to physical terms. This position is usually called physicalism or mate-
assert his authority in Rome over his rivals? rialism. According to this version of scientific naturalism, the
When we seek to interpret the actions of Caesar and Socrates, image of the world provided by the physical sciences (basically,
and ask what reasons they had for acting so, we do not usually physics, chemistry, and biology) is all the world there is. And
want their actions to be explained as we might explain the rise philosophy must conform to science. To quote Paul Boghossian,
of the tides or the motion of the planets; that is, as physical “We take science to be the only good way to arrive at reasonable

Caesar Crossing the Rubicon by Granacci. But why?

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 31


beliefs about what is true... Hence, we defer to science” (Fear
of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism, 2006). In
this view, the task of philosophy is first to assume the method-
ological superiority of natural science, and then to develop posi-
tions which do not disagree with or upset certain background
assumptions of science. The most important of these back-
ground assumptions are that: (1) there exists a theory-indepen-
dent, external world; (2) the world investigated by physics is a
knowable world; and (3) the explanations of physics provide
complete explanations of reality.
One reason physicalist forms of scientific naturalism have
become so widely accepted is that many philosophers tend to
find it difficult to make room for complex phenomena such as
consciousness within the world presented to us by the natural
sciences. Because of this, some physicalist philosophers reduce
complex psychological phenomena down to their component
material parts – things such neural mechanisms – or even to the
very components of matter itself. They do this to easily accom-
modate complex phenomena within the natural world. To quote
Thomas Nagel, with the reductive physicalists, “there is the
hope that everything can be accounted for at the most basic 1884), and Wilhelm Windelband (1848-1915) to defend the
level by the physical sciences, extended to include biology” independence of the human sciences from the natural sciences.
(Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Concep- This approach is also found in the work of British idealists such
tion Is Almost Certainly False, 2012). as R.G.Collingwood (1889-1943) and Michael Oakeshott
However, more recently, philosophers such as John McDow- (1901-1990). They started with the claim that all knowledge
ell, Jennifer Hornsby, Hilary Putnam and Nagel himself have rests on presuppositions, and defined philosophy as the task of
taken a different approach: a non-reductive scientific naturalism. uncovering and making explicit the assumptions which govern
These philosophers argue that while the mind is indeed part of all forms of inquiry, from which they then hoped to show the
the world presented to us by the natural sciences, the complex compatibility of different forms of explanation. It is the task of
mental states involved in consciousness cannot be simply scaled natural scientists to investigate nature. But it is the task of
down to physical processes. To quote Nagel again: “There are philosophers to investigate what we must assume to make the sci-
doubts about whether the reality of features of our world such entific investigation of nature possible. Philosophers are not inter-
as consciousness, intentionality, meaning, purpose, thought, and ested in starting with the results of natural science, but with
value can be accommodated in a universe consisting at the most their presuppositions. To quote Wilhelm Windelband here:
basic level only of physical facts – facts, however sophisticated,
of the kind revealed by the physical sciences.” (ibid). “It is permissible for the other sciences to regard... general perspec-
Because it is a naturalism, and hence limited to natural phe- tives and principles as given and established. This assumption is
nomena, non-reductive naturalism holds that there is nothing sufficiently reliable for the purposes of specialised research within
‘occult’ or ‘spooky’ about consciousness, thoughts, and feelings. the discipline in question. The essential feature of philosophy, how-
However, there are (at least) two main concerns with this ever, is the following: its real object of investigation is actually these
approach. Firstly, if these phenomena are regarded as natural just [general perspectives and principles] themselves.”
because they are not supernatural, what should count as natural (History and Natural Science, p.169, 1894).
and supernatural now? Secondly if we deny that such phenom-
ena as consciousness are exhaustively accounted for by physical Now this is not to say that scientists themselves cannot
science, the problem arises of explaining how they relate to the engage in reflection on the background assumptions of science
rest of nature – the nature that is fully described by that science. and the concept of nature. But it is to say that when scientists
But wait. There is a way out of this difficulty: we drop the do so, they are doing philosophy, not science. This is because this
question about how mind and the rest of nature relate, and focus sort of investigation cannot itself be carried out using the meth-
instead on the question of what must be assumed for certain ods of natural science.
forms of knowledge to be possible. Then once we have uncov- Therefore, this approach is committed to two tiers of inves-
ered the background assumptions to our forms of knowledge, tigation: a ‘primary tier’ of empirical investigation, which is the
we can show how different forms of explanations can co-exist. work of scientists; and a ‘secondary tier’, looking into the assump-
tions behind the empirical investigation, which is the work of
Investigating Knowledge Itself philosophers. In this context, the philosopher is whoever engages in
This approach has been pre-shadowed by certain historical reflection on the background assumptions of primary tier enquiries.
philosophers we three are researching. Explaining the place of Under this view, philosophy is a separate discipline whose dis-
mind within nature in this way started with the attempts by tinctive subject-matter is the background assumptions of (say)
Wilhelm Dilthey (1833-1911), Johann Gustav Droysen (1808- natural scientific inquiry. This is an epistemological idealist phi-

32 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


losophy because it recognises that the assumptions made by dif- This relatively forgotten philosophical tradition not only
ferent forms of inquiry reflect human interests and cognitive manages to make sense of how different forms of explanation,
capacities. But this approach’s distinctive idealist tinge aims not such as the physical and the psychological, can co-exist. It also
to compete with natural science in telling us what exists. Rather, has the advantage of offering us a conception of philosophy as
it aims to spell out what we must assume for certain forms of a more independent and reflective activity, rather than merely
knowledge to be possible, and to argue that these assumptions an afterthought to an already fully formed natural scientific
are a reflection of our cognitive interests and capacities. For world picture. Thus a defence of the independence of human-
example, physical scientists are interested in prediction. Such an istic explanations goes hand-in-hand with an understanding
interest is well served by the formulation of inductive generali- of philosophy as being tasked with unearthing the background
sations, which rely on the principle that natural laws apply uni- assumptions which govern different forms of investigation.
formly so that unobserved cases will resemble previously
observed cases. Cultural anthropologists, on the other hand, are Philosophy Is Indispensable
interested in uncovering the logic behind the apparent random- Philosophy and the human sciences will never be able to tell us
ness or irrationality of human societies and customs. The assump- the age of the universe or whether silver dissolves in nitric acid.
tion of the uniformity of nature which serves the physical scien- Because philosophy and the human sciences can’t give us answers
tist so well in predicting the course of impersonal nature will to those sorts of questions, physical scientists such as Stephen
therefore be of no use to the cultural anthropologist, whose goal Hawking have presumed to dismiss philosophy: “Philosophy is
is rather to unlock the hidden logic behind actions which they dead. Philosophers have not kept up with modern developments
struggle to comprehend in the light of their own cultural norms. in science. Particularly physics” (The Grand Design, 2010). Quite
Understanding philosophy as being concerned with reflect- aside from the irony that Hawking’s put-down of philosophy is
ing on and disclosing what we must assume for certain forms itself a philosophical argument, not one relying on any particu-
of knowledge to be possible enables one to defend the auton- lar scientific evidence, we think there is a good reason for sci-
omy of humanistic explanations better than any attempt to entists to think that philosophy is alive and well: philosophy tells
defend the distinctiveness of the mental from a naturalistic us the background assumptions which govern the sciences.
standpoint. Why? Because by carefully unpacking the back- In light of the attacks on philosophy by Hawking and others,
ground assumptions of the different forms of inquiry we can a reminder of the arguments in defence of the independence
lay bare the most important difference between the natural of philosophy by Daniel Dennett is both needed and timely:
sciences and the human sciences. For example, natural science
presupposes a uniform universe governed by universal laws; “Scientists sometimes deceive themselves into thinking that philo-
on the other hand, a historian does not approach history in sophical ideas are only, at best, decorations or parasitic commen-
such a way. Another difference between the natural sciences taries on the hard, objective triumphs of science, and that they them-
and the human sciences amounts to the natural sciences aspir- selves are immune to the confusions that philosophers devote their
ing to grasp the universal, the general, whereas a human sci- lives to dissolving. But there is no such thing as philosophy-free
ence such as history aspires to make sense of the particular, of science; there is only science whose philosophical baggage is taken
unique events. on board without examination.”
Understood as an inquiry into the presuppositions of knowl- (Darwin’s Dangerous Idea, 1996)
edge rather than as a claim about the nature of reality, episte-
mological idealism succeeds in showing how it is possible for In epistemological idealism, a defence of the human sciences
different and apparently incompatible explanations to peace- goes hand in hand with an understanding of philosophy as dis-
fully co-exist. For example, the question ‘Why did JFK die?’ tinct in kind from natural science. Epistemological idealism,
would no doubt receive very different answers from a physi- then, provides a powerful defence of the autonomy of philoso-
cian and from a political historian. The physician might say phy against the recent attempts to see it as subordinate to the
that JFK died because his cranium was pierced by two bullets natural sciences. Reports of the death of philosophy rely on a
which caused fatal damage to his brain; while the political his- misunderstanding of its nature. Rather, philosophy itself is
torian may argue that JFK’s death was the result of a political needed in order to make sense of the human, as well as the nat-
conspiracy. These answers do not compete because they do ural, sciences.
not address the same why-question: the political historian looks © DR PAUL GILADI, DR ALEXIS PAPAZOGLOU & DR GIUSEPPINA D’ORO 2017
for motives, whereas the physician looks for antecedent con- Paul Giladi is a teaching and research fellow in Philosophy at Uni-
ditions. Although JFK died only once, his death can be versity College Dublin and honorary research fellow at the University
explained in multiple ways which are not incompatible if the of Sheffield. Alexis Papazoglou is Lecturer in Philosophy at Royal Hol-
explanations provide answers to different kinds of why-ques- loway, University of London, and secretary of the Hegel Society of
tions.The claim that these explanations compete arises only Great Britain. Giuseppina D’Oro is Reader in Philosophy at Keele
when we fail to see that the explanatory goals of the political University and principal investigator, with Paul and Alexis, on a
historian and those of the physician are not the same. In a sim- Templeton-funded project ‘Idealism and the Philosophy of Mind’.
ilar way, once it is acknowledged that different forms of inquiry
rest on different presuppositions and have different explana- • This article was made possible through the support of a grant from the John
tory goals, the alleged conflict between the human and the nat- Templeton Foundation. The opinions expressed in it are those of the authors
ural sciences is deflated. and do not necessarily reflect the views of the Foundation.

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 33


Seeing the Future in the Present Past
Siobhan Lyons perceives the flow of history in terms of organic growth and decay.

“This is the lesson that history teaches: repetition.” remembered in the long term, especially once decay becomes a
Gertrude Stein permanent feature of the global landscape. As author Alan Weis-
man notes in his book The World Without Us (2012), we have an
own the end of the street where I used to live in “obstinate reluctance to accept that the worst might actually

D Melbourne there was an old house that became


abandoned. For the longest time the house went
through varying stages of decay, with boards put up
over the windows, graffiti on the walls, and weeds obscuring
the litter left behind by the teenagers who would frequently
occur” (p.3). Writer Roy Scranton makes a similar claim when
he says that “we are predisposed to avoid, ignore, flee, and fight
[death] till the very last hour”, so that “much of our energy is
spent in denial” (Learning How to Die in the Anthropocene, 2015,
p.90). Hence denial is very much a part of our relations with
loiter inside the abandoned structure. ruins. We find ourselves moved by these sites almost in an effort
Our contemporary obsession with modern ruins, ambigu- to make peace with what they ultimately signify. This is partic-
ously dubbed ‘ruin porn’, has a tendency to trivialise the impor- ularly true when visiting modern ruins that have been ruined
tance of such sites, which appear out of phase with our normal by disaster or by economic downturn.
experience of the present. In her book Dispatches from Dystopia:
Histories of Places Not Yet Forgotten (2015), historian Kate Brown The Poignancy of Abandoned Theme Parks
talks instead of ‘rustalgia’ (cf nostalgia). For Brown, while some Abandoned amusement parks are even more poignant and dis-
people speak of their ‘lustful’ attraction to such sites, “others concerting in the absence of the lights and sound that once sig-
will speak in mournful tones of what is lost, what I call rustal- nalled their life. America’s Land of Oz, Germany’s Cold War-
gia” (p.149). Rustalgia both transforms and transports us, under- era Spreepark, and Japan’s Takakanonuma Greenland in the
pinning the more philosophical elements of these places, while Fukushima district, have all been abandoned and have subse-
‘ruin porn’ makes them into nothing more than objects to gape quently decayed; but in their ruin they continue to attract a
at. She thinks her term and what it draws attention to will help growing number of visitors. Why, exactly, is this the case? Why
us understand how “sketchy is the longstanding faith in the does the abandoned amusement park become a more powerful
necessity of perpetual economic growth.” image in its sparseness?
Firstly, there is a modest mythology that encircles the amuse-
Focusing On The Future ment park, constructed to be a modern dreamscape, epitomis-
Contemporary ruins such as those found in Detroit or Cher- ing human enjoyment. Its abandonment, therefore, signals a
nobyl attract thousands of ‘ruin tourists’, many of whom are reversal of this dynamic, becoming a site of radical anachronism,
attempting to engage with the existential threat these sights and thus perfectly symbolising the natural process of human
arouse. Modern ruins become a way of time travelling into the death and decay. Secondly, whether operational or not, amuse-
future within the present, giving us insight into what life may ment parks resonate on a nostalgic level, and this nostalgia is
be like without us, and inspiring in us a kind of paranoia. Sig- amplified in the amusement park’s decay since that nostalgia no
nalling the eventual decay to which we will all succumb, con- longer has an outlet. Australian writer and blogger Vanessa Berry
temporary ruins inspire fascination and fear, a furious denial of wrote of touring around Sydney’s abandoned Magic Kingdom
our immortality, and a wary flirtation with death. These sights theme park, “In these abandoned places it is easy to imagine
are fascinating to us because they prompt our asking about our oneself to be one of the last humans alive, picking over the
place in the overarching narrative of history. remains of a civilisation. Modern ruins are the delight of urban
Although a fascination with the future is not unique to our explorers, who enjoy the sense of finding value in what others
time, we have increasingly focused on it; as Arthur C. Clarke have discarded. Abandoned theme parks are particularly reso-
once remarked: “This is the first age that’s ever paid much atten- nant places” (‘Magic Kingdom’, Mirror Sydney, 2012). She also
tion to the future, which is a little ironic since we may not have observes that amusement parks were “dreamlike from their con-
one.” Modern ruins offer us a glimpse into our future. As scholar ception… To explore the rusting rides, bright paint faded, is to
Jason McGrath argues: “The posthuman gaze at modernist be inside a metaphor of lost childhood innocence.” American
ruins reminds us that, no matter how many new objects we pro- scholar Mark Pendergrast, moreover, speaks of the separation
duce, consume, and discard, those objects will in many cases far from reality that amusement parks provide, noting that Coney
outlive us and the purposes to which we put them.” Part of our Island, the New York City neighbourhood with its own amuse-
sense of denial and resistance to modern urban ruin is because ment area, “revelled in illusion. In the distorting mirrors of its
of its drastic implications regarding our everyday efforts. Thus funhouse, everyday reality was suspended” (Mirror Mirror, 2003,
sights of decay and abandonment provoke strong resistance in p.253). When we visit decaying amusement parks, however, real-
us not so much because we have a fear of death, but because we ity comes rushing back with unrestrainable force.
have a fear of insignificance – they remind us that we will not be When such places are closed down and left to ruin we can no

34 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


ABANDONED RIDE © P.J.L. LAURENS 2009

Abandoned Dadipark ride

longer take solace in the illusion of immortality that these parks ically inaccurate, the fact that many people continue to use type-
strive to promote when operative. But more than our engage- writers does not, I believe, signal a regression, but in fact
ment with our own mortality, again, these ruins disrupt our stan- reframes the argument to favour the notion of intellectual rather
dard conventions of time and history. They work to dislocate than technological progress, showing that technology and intel-
the relationship between the past and the present, incorporat- ligence are not one and the same. Yet the general narrative about
ing both the past and the future, the dead past existing simulta- the continued use of typewriters and other supposedly ‘anachro-
neously alongside living architecture. While authors, artists, nistic’ technologies is that this is backward, outdated, and
directors and poets have always attempted to depict the aesthetic strange, just like our obsession with ruins. But for a number of
nature of the future and the possibilities of apocalypse, modern authors, a typewriter is actually superior to digital technologies.
ruins show that we may already be there. As artist Tong Lam British author Will Self, for instance, says that the typewriter
beautifully but simply notes, “In a way, we are already post-apoc- forces his mind to slow down and to process thought more effi-
alyptic.” (Abandoned Futures, 2013). Indeed, when we talk of ciently, rather than having his thoughts scattered by the PC. As
social destruction, we almost always do so hypothetically, situ- journalist Neil Hallows writes, “the computer user does their
ating the end within the future rather than in the present time; thinking on the screen, and the non-computer user is compelled,
but as environmentalist David Suzuki put it in a 2007 interview: because he or she has to retype a whole text, to do a lot more
“The future doesn’t exist. The only thing that exists is now and thinking in the head” (‘Why Typewriters Beat Computers’,
our memory of what happened in the past. But because we 2008). Such thoughts give credence to William Faulkner’s idea
invented the idea of a future, we’re the only animal that realized that “the past is not dead; it’s not even past.” Certain memora-
we can affect the future by what we do today.” (Canada.com). bilia can have a present function, defying the logic of linking
objects to a certain time and place and discarding them with the
Progressing the Idea of Progress momentum of history.
If we as a global civilisation are already in the midst of our own
ruin, what does this tell us about progress? For one, that progress The Organic Nature of History
is not, as is widely believed, irretrievably linked to the future, For many, history follows a linear development: there is to all
or to newness. things a beginning, middle, and end, and we can differentiate
According to ‘technological determinists’, not only does tech- between each period.The plethora of ruins and the widespread
nology supposedly drive history, but what’s new is better than use of old technology paints a picture of society not retreat-
preceding technologies, thus linking newness to progress. By ing into an antiquated era, but rather, proceeding nonlinearly.
this logic, digital downloads are superior to vinyl records; word They show us that progress is not straightforward, and can be
processors are better than typewriters; and digital cameras are seen less as historical, and more as intellectual.
better than film-based analogue ones. Yet although an object Instead of a linear pattern of history, what we actually see is
may be technically improved, this is not necessarily an improve- that it has what French philosopher Gilles Deleuze (1925-95) calls
ment in terms of its creative capabilities. In fact, the more tech- a rhizomatic (rootlike) structure. With typewriters and decay exist-
nologically improved the gadget, the less effort required on our ing alongside digitisation and growth, our understanding of
part to create art, meaning human creativity is often actually progress becomes more about intellectual linearity, so that our
compromised. So what we are seeing is rather newness mas- ideas define and shape progress, rather than technologies and
querading as progress. Yet typewriter usage – alongside that of events in sequential time. That is, while we can’t conclusively say
vinyl and analogue photography – is on the rise, while some what history is, we can at least say what history is not: that it is not
people and organisations never relinquished them, defying the technological, and not straightforwardly chronological. Or if we
logic of technological progress. While the image of a hipster talk about chronology, we need to do so through the lens of intel-
sitting with a typewriter in Starbucks might appear chronolog- lectual history rather than the history of objects.

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 35


But as Gertrude Stein points out, if history (not the chrono- Historical Deleuzion
logical phenomenon, but our knowledge of that phenomenon) Gilles Deleuze is a particularly useful philosopher to employ
teaches us anything, it is that, paradoxically, repetition is almost a here. Deleuze discusses a phenomenon he calls ‘difference
necessary aspect of cultural evolution. Of course, this makes it dif- within repetition’. For Deleuze, “life itself is described as a
ficult to tell whether our own woes and complaints about the times dynamic and active force of repetition producing difference”
differ in any meaningful way from those of earlier generations: (Adrian Parr, Deleuze Dictionary, 2010, p.225), and in repetition
whether there is more truth to our own fears for the future than there is the ‘possibility of reinvention’, for although we repeat,
to theirs – especially when we consider the similarities of discon- we do not uniformly repeat. Thus within a cycle of occurrences
tent across centuries. Perhaps the only constant in the history of we can see subtle deviations emerging in a pattern perhaps mis-
life is disillusionment with change. As Pyotr Voyd, the central taken as pure monotony. For instance, we still show all our fears
regarding the state of our intellects – but in slightly different
ways as our concerns move from one technology to another.
Hence we should not worry that many are returning to type-
writers in lieu of their supposedly more sophisticated alterna-
tives, because this demonstrates a rebellion against the rigid
order of time; that is, with the expectations of behaviour and
actions supposedly befitting one’s time. Perhaps we should laud
those who retreat into such ‘anachronistic’ technologies, and
ridicule those who unthinkingly pursue novelty. As Friedrich
Nietzsche pointed out, the philosopher needs to be out of phase
and at odds with their own time, and should ideally be “a person
of tomorrow and the day after tomorrow… his enemy has
always been the ideal of today” (Beyond Good and Evil, 1886,
p.106). For Nietzsche, the philosopher’s task lies in “being the
Entrance to the abandoned Dadipark in Belgium bad conscience of their age.” In this sense, the philosopher, the
writer, the artist, and the poet, are called to be women and men
character of Victor Pelevin’s novel Buddha’s Little Finger (1999) outside their time. For Victor Pelevin, there are those who
says, “we are descendants of the past. The word signifies movement adapt to change – those who essentially change with the times;
downwards, not upwards. We are not ascendants” (1999, p.34). those who anticipate change, adapting to it more quickly as a
This seems to be a manner in which we constantly frame his- result; and those who make change “by creeping across to
tory. For instance, we constantly ask of our society: are we get- occupy the quarter from which they think the wind will blow.
ting stupider? Worried researchers tells us so; but then Socrates Following which, the wind has no option but to blow from that
is said by Plato to have stated 2,400 years ago: “Our youth now very quarter” (Generation P, 1999, p.36). Our task is to occupy
love luxury. They have bad manners, contempt for authority; that quarter.
they show disrespect for their elders and love chatter in place of When I think of the dilapidated house on my old street, the
exercise; they no longer rise when elders enter the room; they very concept of economy, or of culture, evaporates. On the face
contradict their parents, chatter before company; gobble up their of it there appears to be a clear and discernable difference
food, and tyrannize their teachers.” We have more or less the between the decaying house and the vibrant one next to it. But
same concern in the twenty-first century about the younger gen- they belong to the same matrix of existence, because all things
erations and their poor grammar, flagrant antisocial behaviour, that are made are always already in the process of ruin. Progress
and obsessive use of technology. We are also told to prepare for is falsely understood as a resistance to ruin; but in that we
the book’s demise at the hands of the internet; but then, Victor neglect the fact that progress exists alongside ruin – that all the
Hugo expressed the same fears for the demise of architecture at contradictory forces of time are occurring simultaneously. Just
the hands of the book; while Samuel Taylor Coleridge criticised as this house sinks into the earth, so too will the one beside it,
the novel for impairing memory. As Jill Lepore puts it, “Every eventually. This recognition helps us disobey the conventions
age has a theory of rising and falling, of growth and decay, of of time – hence our blatant engagement with modern ruins;
bloom and wilt: a theory of nature.” (‘The Disruption Machine’, hence our continued use of objects and phenomena some con-
The New Yorker, June 2014). sider obsolete. These anachronistic elements force us to engage
So is there any particular importance to our own cultural with phenomena before and beyond our own time in an effort
anxieties, or are they merely part of an inevitably repeating pat- to challenge the present. We may then be invited to see his-
tern? Is it simply that our own fears have been more easily voiced tory as something chaotically overwhelmed by the struggle
and disseminated via more efficient technologies? Is there any between the past, present and future, all within the same space.
truth to our discontent that separates us from earlier centuries And only once we understand how time really operates and
– thereby legitimising our fears – or is it simply part of one con- how to use elements outside of our own time effectively will
sistent, shared concern that is part of the same evolutionary we begin to understand the true nature of progress.
matrix, in which history is not a thing divided but a continu- © SIOBHAN LYONS 2017
ous, uninterrupted stream of sameness – in which a distinction Siobhan Lyons is a media scholar at Macquarie University, where she
between time periods is all but illusory? earned her PhD in media and cultural studies.

36 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Question of the Month
How Can I Know Right From Wrong?
???
The following responses to this basic ethical question each win a random book.

T o understand how acquire have moral knowledge, we first


need to understand what sort of thing we are talking about
when we speak of right and wrong. I want to propose a non-nat-
life; I think the principle of sanctity of life has been forsaken by
murderers. Finally take the decision.
Unfortunately valid and relevant moral principles clash, and
uralist account of morality as first put forth by G.E. Moore in his we may have to decide which one we should follow of two equally
Principia Ethica (1903). Following Moore, we can conceive of pertinent claims. My utilitarian approach is that the most impor-
morality as a sort of universal dimension. All actions fall some- tant objective is usually the one that brings the most good into
where in this moral dimension, from extremely good to extremely the world; but that is not always the case. I have a greater duty to
bad and a neutral middle. some than to others, which clashes with the duty to save more
Let me now liken morality to time. There is no physical aspect lives than fewer: but I will save my own child rather than ten
of reality to which we can point that shows time itself. But we strangers. Morality started as care of kin and we should not stray
don’t need something physical to point at to know that the passage too far from its roots. Also some principles may be intrinsically
of time occurs. Rather, time seems to impress itself upon us more important than others. Perhaps it is more important not to
because our mental faculties are designed to experience its pass- take life than to save it, so I should refuse to kill one to save two.
ing. This seems true of morality too. When we witness a murder But what if I can save fifty by killing one? Morality can be relative
and say that it’s wrong, we aren’t pointing to a physical entity of to circumstances, not absolute, and at some point the utilitarian
‘wrongness’; instead we are highlighting a value that is inherent principle wins. Analysing analogous situations where the answer
in the witnessed action. The moral dimension impresses itself on is clear is useful; seeing how they differ from the current situation
us in such a way that we can perceive moral properties. clarifies thinking. And always discuss problems both with those
One may wonder how, if we can apprehend moral facts in this you respect and with those who disagree with you. When you get
way, that there is still widespread disagreement on moral matters. it wrong, forgive yourself, and try to do better next time.
But moral facts aren’t all as simple as ‘killing is bad’ and ‘being ALLEN SHAW, HAREWOOD, LEEDS
helpful is good’. Killing can’t be absolutely wrong, since someone
may rightly kill a person to stop the detonation of a bomb in a
school. Actions have a range of different motivations and unseen
background facts. To know if something complex is moral, we
P erhaps the best way to answer this question is to take com-
monly accepted ethical notions and appraise them for the
case at hand, as accordance to a central ethical principle often
need to know not only the action but the cause, the mind-set of appears a sound basis of ethical action. One such principles is the
the person taking the action, and the intended effect. Moral Golden Rule (‘do unto others as you would have them do unto
knowledge can be derived from measuring the impressions a per- you’), variously occurring in many religious and belief systems.
son has about an action, and investigating the thinking of the per- The idea that notions such as this one are reliable indicators of
son who made the action. Some people are better at receiving ‘rights’ and ‘wrongs’ is persuasive. Some moralists believe ethical
these impressions and thus turning them into knowledge. This action arises from a sense of duty, and not from a natural predis-
isn’t to turn ethicists into priests of morality. It is, as my position to good behaviour. Recognising responsibilities to oth-
metaethics professor said, like space: someone may constantly ers, not self-interest, does seem morally positive. Furthermore,
bump their head due to a lack of spatial awareness. We can all following Kant, some theorists believe we must not treat others
gain better knowledge of morality by learning how to better read ‘merely as a means to an end’ but rather as ‘ends in themselves’,
our moral impressions. acknowledging their capacity for ethical thought. Treating peo-
JULIAN SHIELDS, MANLY, AUCKLAND, NZ ple as merely an end not a means seems ethically sound: it is altru-
istic and respectful of others; arguably very important qualities

T here is no magic formula, but there is a pathway which may


help in situations of doubt. First, ascertain the facts of a sit-
uation. Ignorance never promotes good decisions. Let others
in right ethical behaviour.
However, rigid application of ethical rules may have seemingly
unethical conclusions. The majority of people would believe it
thrust on you facts you would rather overlook. Second, and more wrong to lie in most circumstances yet right to lie in specific situ-
difficult, try to predict the consequences of the actions you might ations, such as to save a life. Secondly, an emphasis upon the impor-
take. Unfortunately even correctly predicted consequences them- tance of duty can give the impression that ethics is demanding and
selves cause unforeseeable consequences. But even the most ded- counter-intuitive, which is not entirely convincing: it seems difficult
icated non-consequentialist must consider consequences because to criticise a naturally generous person for not being truly ethical
actually conferring benefit on others is an important moral prin- because they do not act out of a sense of duty. Finally, although
ciple, if not an overriding one. Third, look at the moral principles most would agree we should respect and value others persons, we
which tell you to do one thing or the other. Those principles must may accept treating others as a means if the end is liable to have
be both valid and relevant, which is often arguable. Catholics significantly more favourable consequences. For example, many
think that divorce is wrong, but Islam makes divorce easy for men. people would agree it is right to sacrifice the life of one person if it
You think that we must respect the sanctity of even a murderer’s saves many lives, and in fact wrong not to do so. So it seems that

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 37


?? although people often have clear sentiments which tell them when
behaviour is right or wrong, they also accept that there are times
when rigid adherence to the same principles is problematic and/or
unethical, making ethics as uncertain as any other branch of phi-
losophy. This means absolute ethical judgements on right and
wrong are difficult, so important ethical debates remain unresolved.
JONATHAN TIPTON, PRESTON, LANCASHIRE
on demand. Then, without intent, my toothless gums squeezed the
nipple too hard. My mother flinched, drew away, withdrawing
food. I cried, and supply was restored. I attended to those things
and remembered: I responded to maternal actions, noted that for
some of my actions she would provide things which gave pleasure
and for others her response provided less pleasure. I learned which
things my mother valued and led to her supply of pleasure to me.
She was thus defining right and wrong. As I acquired language, I

P hilosophers can quibble over many different theories, but in


the end I would advocate a simple boo-hurrah approach to
discerning right from wrong. Okay, I’m not accounting for psy-
conceptualised these ideas and, in dialogue with her, and, increas-
ingly, with others, refined these concepts. Right and wrong are
defined socially by interactions amongst other people and me.
chopaths. Nevertheless, I would argue that the majority of They are learned. My desire for acceptance into society made me
human beings have an innate sense of disgust at immoral acts, learn and conform to its ideas of rightness or wrongness.
stemming from empathy. If you want to know if your actions ALASDAIR MACDONALD, GLASGOW
towards another individual are right or wrong, just ask yourself
if that’s how you would want to be treated. That’s the objectivity:
we’re living, aware creatures. Why complicate it more than that?
MORGAN MILLARD, URMSTON, MANCHESTER
A s an individual I am born into a society requiring adherence
to a set of rules and values by which I did not choose to be
bound. I am expected to behave in a certain way and live by certain
rules in order to live in harmony with my fellow citizens. Assuming

I t might be inferred from the question that discerning right from


wrong is essentially cognitive. Thus, employing the terminology
of Benjamin Bloom’s taxonomy of educational objectives in the
I have no psychological disorder, I begin to learn these societal
expectations from an early age, from associations with groups,
which form my cultural identity. As a member of a family, a reli-
cognitive domain, I am able to recall things deemed right or wrong gion, a country, a school, a workplace, I am taught the practices,
and I can understand why they are so. I can apply my recall and values and rules of those associations. For example, as a young
understanding of right and wrong to act appropriately in specific family member, I learn through guidance by parents that it is bad
circumstances; I can analyse behaviours and determine which are to be spiteful to siblings, and that the right behaviour sets a good
right and wrong; I can evaluate why some are right or wrong; and example to younger siblings who may learn right from wrong from
I can create more finely nuanced conceptions of rightness or me. As an adult, I am bound by an employment contract, losing
wrongness. This learning is acquired by trial and error, and my job if I breach it. As an autonomous being, I take responsibility
inferred from the reactions of other people to what I do or say. for my actions regarding my choice of associations. With exposure
But, it is an affective issue too: the reactions of others to what I to other cultures, moralities and belief systems, I may start to ques-
say or do evoke feelings in me. To use Bloom in this domain: ini- tion my learned behaviours and morals, reasoning as to whether
tially, I attend to or note particular actions that evoke responses or not I wish to maintain those associations, weighing up the con-
from others or feelings in me. I learn to respond to some actions in sequences of discontinuing with what I know, and attaching myself
some circumstances by others. I feel, too, that some responses are to new associations and groups – for example, changing religion
more valued by others or by myself. I organise some of these valued and the effect this may have on my family and friends. But in gen-
responses according to some principles. Eventually, these princi- eral, I can know right from wrong through my identity associa-
ples interlink so that my conduct is characterised by them. tions, sanctioning any resultant punishment concerning the
For example, when my mother first put me to her breast I fol- choices I make as an adult. There may be conflicts: for example,
lowed an innate need for sustenance. However, I felt pleasures of some cultures advocate honour killings, whereas others maintain
satiation, of warmth, of security. I cried when I felt hunger, or cold it is never right to kill another person. So what to do if you associate
and, later, fear. I learned that this woman provided for these needs, with a culture that advocates honour killings, but the laws of the
society in which you live do not allow this? Choosing to stray from
your original associations may result in penal punishment.
SHARON PAINTER, RUGELEY, STAFFS
PLEASE VISIT WWW.CGILLCARTOONS.COM FOR MORE.

B asically, I can’t. Not in any definitive way. Unlike laws of


physics, which govern regardless of human understanding,
CARTOON © CHRIS GILL 2017

concepts of right and wrong are constructions, products of a devel-


oping self-awareness. Reason, as Nietzsche suggests, was a late
addition to our animal instincts. To highlight the implications of
this, look at attitudes towards killing. For early humans, the crime
of ‘murder’ would be a nonsensical idea. One had to kill to survive,
making ‘murder’ an accepted hazard of daily life. Only the move
from hunter-gatherer lifestyles to settled communities lessened the
need to slaughter in self-defence, thus beginning the slow march
to recognising murder as immoral. However, there is a problem.
Many believe killing can be justified in some circumstances. Such
ambiguities mean that knowing right from wrong in any absolute
sense is impossible, even in seemingly clear-cut instances. But the
“No daddy, not what is the time; what is Time?”
same applies in other areas. No matter how abhorrent and objec-

38 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018 How Can I Know Right From Wrong?
tionably wrong I believe various crimes to be, an example of his-
torical permissibility can be found. Humans, at some point, have
accepted rape, theft and persecution without question.
As right and wrong do not exist outside the collective conscious-
ness of the planet’s population at a particular moment, it is only
possible to pass judgement in hindsight. We could argue that
changing attitudes are evidence of an inherent ‘wrongness’ in cer-
tain acts, perhaps pointing to a natural order of right and wrong
ness can only be judged comparatively, against other actions.
Then which actions? If we could name the property that distin-
guished ‘right’ actions from the rest, we would have also named
what we meant by rightness and wrongness. But if we could do
that, then we would be back to rightness and wrongness referring
to some fact, and any apparent disputes would be revealed as sim-
ply misunderstandings. But again, our failure to agree suggests
this is cannot be the case. If right and wrong are graduations of a
??
similar to discovering laws of physics. But such convictions have single system, and if we cannot place boundaries on that system,
proved false before. For millennia it was thought that religious texts then that system must contain everything. What sorts of systems
gave definitive answers; yet if a Creator were to reveal themselves contain everything, or try to? Philosophical ones. So I would argue
and say, ‘Same sex marriage is wrong’, or ‘Capital punishment is that our individual understanding of right and wrong is deter-
right’, a lot of people, including me, would have tremendous diffi- mined by our own philosophy. In so far as we have such a general
culty accepting it. Suddenly, we’d irrefutably know right and wrong, philosophy, then we already know right and wrong. If we are
but feel that many ‘right’ things were ‘wrong’, and vice versa. unsure of them, it is because our philosophy remains unformed
Some aspects of right and wrong may seem given, but for the in our own minds.
most part we have to follow our conscience. For this reason, noth- JOHN WHITE, LONDON
ing is certain. I simply have to do my best.
GLENN BRADFORD, SUTTON IN ASHFIELD, NOTTINGHAMSHIRE
W hy should we expect to be able to know right from wrong?
Morality isn’t written into the universe the way facts of

T he short answer is, I can’t. Dr Oliver Scott Curry of Oxford


University has essentially cracked the problem of morality,
based on empirical evidence from sixty cultures, present and his-
nature seem to be: it’s a matter of human choice, and people
choose to respond to moral issues in different ways. Systems such
as Bentham’s utilitarianism or Kant’s deontology have important
torical. What follows is my take on his original thoughts, so the insights but they all have drawbacks – the first for its wilful disre-
random book should go to him. gard of innocent people’s (assumed) rights, the second for its dis-
Like Rome and its hills, morality is built on seven naturally regard of consequences. But what is the yardstick against which
evolved values, held to varying degrees, whose functions are pro- we judge the apparent failings of these two systems? For posi-
moting cooperation or resolving conflict. The greatest of these is tivists, it’s a matter of psychology based on evolution and upbring-
Possession, held sacrosanct by nine tenths of cultures and the law. ing. Does this lead to relativism, with its apparent contradiction
Next come Kinship, Loyalty and Reciprocity, espoused by three that we should never intervene in another culture or criticise a
quarters. Over half of cultures rate Respect (for the powerful) and psychopath? I don’t think so. Within most polities the idea of
Humility (of the powerless). Last and least comes Fairness, valued inflicting unnecessary pain on the innocent is abhorrent. Through
by only 15%. So dosvidanya socialism, and never give a sucker an some inner instinct or psychological preference, we know (or is it
even break. The punch line is, there are no other moral values. Each believe?) that such cruelty is wrong. And we know if we follow
individual can claim their peculiar principle, plus aesthetic judg- certain rules that our society will give us outcomes that more or
ment; but only these seven values can be truly shared. less accord with our moral preferences. In many countries enough
Cultures and societies differ in the scope and priority they people share enough of these values to give a sense of common
ascribe to these seven pillars of morality. Right is what helps purpose in pursuit of morality. Why shouldn’t we seek to convince
achieve some conscious or unconscious goal, be it reproduction, others, that ours is a way of life that suits human psychological
social cohesion, long life, prosperity, or conquest. Wrong is what preferences, both theirs and ours?
obstructs the goal, and evil is interpreted as doing so intention- However, that cohesive set of common instincts breaks down
ally. Values may be incompatible, one negating another with in more problematic cases such as abortion or various versions of
traumatic results. What if the goal is to wield absolute domina- Phillipa Foot’s ‘trolley problem’. For these there may be no
tion over absolute submission, forever? agreement on what is right and we don’t have a method of decid-
DR NICHOLAS B. TAYLOR, LITTLE SANDHURST ing in some formulaic way what the correct action is. Any solution
will cut across someone’s inner instinct, and there is no other way

W hat can we say about the question? First, we must already


to an extent know the answer: we must already have some
idea what ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ mean. If we didn’t, we wouldn’t
of testing the decision-making process. We agonise over these
difficult problems. Perhaps the important question is not Did we
get the morally right solution? – where there may be none – but Did
understand the question. But at the same time, we disagree with we agonise enough? Did we grapple and make sure we looked at
others about ‘right’ and ‘wrong’. But surely, if we know ourselves the problem from all possible sides?
what is right and wrong, all we need to do is explain what those PETER KEEBLE, HARROW, LONDON
words refer to when we use them, others can explain what they
are referring to, and our apparent disagreement will be resolved? The next question is: W hy Is There Something Rather
Yet we cannot do this. We can all look at an action, be in total Than Nothing?
agreement about the facts, about what the action consists of, about Please give and justify your answer in less than 400 words.
what effects it has, yet still disagree about whether or not it is right. The prize is a semi-random book from our book mountain.
If that is the case, then we cannot be arguing about the nature of Subject lines should be marked ‘Question of the Month’, and
that action. Our disagreement – and thus what we each mean by must be received by 12th February 2018. If you want a
‘right’ – must lie elsewhere. This helps explain why we sometimes chance of getting a book, please include your physical
cannot agree about the rightness of an action: its degree of right- address. Submission is permission to reproduce your answer.

How Can I Know Right From Wrong? December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 39
Brief Lives
Henry David Thoreau (1817-62)
In Thoreau’s bicentenary, Martin Jenkins looks at the famous American eccentric.

A
few years ago I went into a bookshop to buy a copy of in on July 4th, and remained there until 1849. He was not a her-
Thoreau’s Walden (1854). I couldn’t find one, but the mit, nor did he set out to be self-sufficient: by his own admission
assistant could: in the fiction section. This may reflect he spent a lot of time with friends, and at his family home, and
the difficulty of classifying Thoreau. Was he a nature often had meals there. Indeed, the most famous incident of his life
writer, a poet, a travel writer, a political thinker, even a philoso- occurred because he went into town to collect a shoe repair from
pher – even all of these? Perhaps; but not, I am certain, a novelist! the cobbler, whereupon he was arrested for non-payment of his
Thoreau’s works do not help to classify him. He wrote widely poll tax and imprisoned for a night, being released after a friend
on a range of subjects. He only published three full-length books, paid it for him. Thoreau refused to pay the tax in protest at the
but wrote numerous essays and lectures, and he kept a journal state’s collusion with slavery in the Southern states.
which ran to two million words. However, two works stand out
philosophically: Walden and the essay Civil Disobedience (1849). Anarchy In The USA
The outcome of this experience was Civil Disobedience, which
Life opens with a statement of his political philosophy:
David Henry Thoreau was born in Concord, Massachusetts, in
1817. (He called himself Henry David from 1837, the year he “I heartily accept the motto, ‘That government is best which governs
started his journal. Both may be seen as expressions of his individ- least;’ and I should like to see it acted up to more rapidly and systemat-
uality.) His father was at first a farmer; but also ran a grocery ically. Carried out, it finally amounts to this, which also I believe – ‘That
store, worked as a teacher in Boston, and then returned to Con- government is best which governs not at all’; and when men are pre-
cord to run the family’s pencil factory. pared for it, that will be the kind of government which they will have.”
Thoreau was sent to Harvard in 1833. He undertook more
than the required curriculum, and graduated in 1837. Returning This is, of course, anarchism; but, as the last phrase shows,
to Concord, he took a job in his old primary school, but resigned Thoreau believed that human beings had to become worthy of it.
rather than flog his pupils. Subsequently he opened a secondary In the meantime, how should those who are worthy of it act
school with his brother John. towards the state as it exists?
About this time Henry was attending meetings of the group Thoreau’s answer is in one sense complex but in another sense
loosely known as ‘The New England Transcendentalists’ at simple: the individual must follow their own conscience, and refuse
Ralph Waldo Emerson’s house in Concord. This group was loyalty and obedience to the state which lacks moral virtue. Slavery,
united more by interests than by ideas: the one thing that they he says, is not maintained by Southern slave-owners, but by North-
agreed on was opposition to slavery. However, they managed to erners who tolerate it in the interests of maintaining the state.
create a magazine, The Dial, in which they expressed their various However, Thoreau is not a rampant individualist. Having
ideas, and to which Thoreau contributed more than thirty essays refused to pay his poll tax, he writes: “I have never declined paying
and other works. the highway tax, because I am as desirous of being a good neigh-
In 1839 both John and Henry Thoreau fell in love with Ellen bour as I am of being a bad subject.” He insists on being a good
Sewell. She rejected both their proposals. This is the only known member of the community – just not of the state. After being
romantic attachment in Thoreau’s life. In 1841, John’s ill health released from prison, he joined a party who were going out to pick
resulted in the closure of the school; and in 1842 John died of huckleberries (“who were impatient to put themselves under my
tetanus after cutting himself shaving. Henry was devastated and conduct”), and two miles outside Concord “the State was
for a while suffered a psychosomatic paralysis. nowhere to be seen.”
As early as 1837, Henry Thoreau had improved the graphite Civil Disobedience is arguably the most influential of Thoreau’s
used in the family firm’s pencils. In 1844 he developed an writings. Reading it convinced Gandhi to develop his theory and
improved drilling machine for the pencils, as well as pioneering practice; and maybe Gandhi, in naming his method satyagraha, or
shades of graphite. In the same year, when Emerson could not get ‘truth-force’, came close to summarising Thoreau’s philosophy.
a single Concord church to offer him space for an anti-slavery
lecture, Thoreau organised the use of the courthouse. In 1850, Into The Woods
when someone was needed to go to recover the body and If Thoreau’s stay in the woods was not an exercise in self-suffi-
manuscripts of Margaret Fuller after she drowned in a shipwreck, ciency, what was it?
it was Thoreau who undertook the job. So Thoreau was an emi- It was an exercise in self-exploration. “Be a Columbus,” Thoreau
nently practical man, and could have been a commercial success. wrote, “to whole new continents and worlds within you, opening
But he chose a different road, and spent most of the rest of his life new channels, not of trade, but of thought.” If Civil Disobedience
relying on odd surveying jobs and work as a handyman. explores the proper relationship of the individual and the state,
In 1845 Thoreau began to construct a cabin in the woods by Walden asks how the individual should properly relate to himself,
Walden Pond, about a mile and a half from Concord. He moved others, and the world in general. How do we perfect ourselves, and

40 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Henry David Thoreau
Portrait by Darren McAndrew 2017

thus become worthy of the ideal state? And to answer that question cate… As if the main object were to talk fast and not to talk sensibly.”
for yourself, you need to know who you are as an individual.
In Walden’s long opening chapter Thoreau mounts a critique Having expressed his dissatisfaction with the contemporary
of modern life and how it generates ‘needs’ (for ‘better’ shelter, world, Thoreau moves on to put forward the alternative he dis-
clothing, food, etc) which are not needs at all. He memorably covered by living at Walden.
describes modern heating as being “cooked, of course à la mode.” Thoreau was not living there to avoid human company. He
He also has no time for the “need for speed” and is unimpressed begins the chapter ‘Visitors’ thus: “I think that I love society as
by the railroad. He writes: much as most, and am ready enough to fasten myself like a blood-
sucker for the time to any full-blooded man that comes in my
“Our inventions… are but improved means to an unimproved end… We way.” He claims to have had up to thirty people in his hut at one
are in great haste to construct a magnetic telegraph from Maine to Texas; time; his circle included thinkers such as Emerson, Nathaniel
but Maine and Texas, it may be, have nothing important to communi- Hawthorne, and Margaret Fuller. But most of the ‘Visitor’ chap-

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 41


Brief Lives
ter is concerned with one man, a Canadian woodcutter. Thoreau Out Of The Woods
clearly enjoyed his company, and “did not know whether he was Thoreau left the woods perhaps because Emerson wanted him to
as wise as Shakespeare or as simply ignorant as a child.” The look after his house while he was on a lecture tour; but his own expla-
woodcutter did not want to change the world but knew how to nation is that “I left the woods for as good a reason as I went there”
live contentedly in it; he had some thoughts, but not great ones: (Walden); or, “I do not know what made me leave the pond. I left it
he was, Thoreau says, humble without knowing what humility as unaccountably as I went to it. To speak sincerely, I went there
was. It is difficult to imagine a greater contrast to the high think- because I had got ready to go; I left it for the same reason” (Journal).
ing of the Transcendentalists; but not hard to understand why This comes close to “It seemed like a good idea at the time.”
Thoreau might have preferred the woodcutter. From this point on Thoreau seems to have distanced himself
This theme of company is continued in the chapter ‘Former somewhat from the Transcendentalists. He was outraged by the
Inhabitants’, in which Thoreau communes with the memory of 1850 Fugitive Slave Act, which required free states to return
people who formerly lived nearby: two slaves, a coloured woman, escaped slaves to their owners in the South. He took an active part
a potter, a ditcher, a tavern-keeper. This is Thoreau’s history of in the underground railroad smuggling slaves out of the South:
Concord: not its great men, nor “the shot heard round the world” on at least one occasion he provided shelter and a route to Canada
but the humble people forgotten except in folk memory. for a fugitive slave. Thoreau continued to think, as his writings
Thoreau had a great deal of solitude at his hut. Perhaps living prove; but he was becoming more of an activist.
there enabled him to ration his human contact, giving him time The most controversial episode of Thoreau’s life occurred in
to explore himself, to encounter nature more directly, to meet 1857, when he met John Brown of Kansas, an abolitionist who
and talk with people outside his usual circles, and most impor- promoted armed insurrection on behalf of that cause, and gave
tantly, to think. “Rather than love, than money, than fame, give him the fullest support, even writing and publishing ‘A Plea for
me truth,” he writes, recognising that truth is what human beings John Brown’ after Brown’s raid on Harper’s Ferry in 1859.
often do not want. On that note he creates a brilliant simile for Thoreau’s father died in 1859, which left Henry head of the
how his book will be received by comparing it with the ice from family and responsible for his mother and sister. In 1860 he
Walden Pond: “Southern customers objected to its blue colour, developed bronchitis and travelled to Minnesota for a cure. Here
which is the evidence of its purity, as if it were muddy, and pre- he met members of the Sioux Nation, and was concerned about
ferred the Cambridge ice, which is white, but tastes of weeds.” their treatment by the federal government – an activist to the last.
For Thoreau, the truth is discovered by looking beyond appear- The cure did not work. Thoreau returned to Concord, made
ance and testing reality. arrangements for the posthumous publication of The Maine
Thoreau is often regarded as a ‘spiritual’ writer. But as has Woods (1864), and died of tuberculosis on May 6th 1862.
been shown, he was a practical man, and towards the end of
Walden he brings together the search for truth and practicality: Assessments
One tendency within Thoreau scholarship has been to divert
“Say what you have to say, not what you ought. Any truth is better than attention from what he says by calling its context into question.
make-believe. Tom Hyde, the tinker, standing on the gallows, was He has been criticised for not being economically self-sufficient
asked if he had anything to say. ‘Tell the tailors,’ said he, ‘to remember (when he did not set out to be); and Carl Bode has put forward a
to make a knot in their thread before they take their first stitch.’ His psychoanalytic explanation which sees Thoreau’s hostility to the
companion’s prayer is forgotten.” state as linked to an Oedipal hatred of his father and John Brown
as a father figure. Anything rather than acknowledge that
(The last sentence reminds us that Thoreau was possessed of Thoreau’s (admittedly threatening) ideas might be worth consid-
a dry humour. For another example, “Some circumstantial evi- ering in their own right!
dence is very strong, as when you find a trout in the milk.”) It seems more likely that what Thoreau saw in John Brown was
a reflection of his own development. He had moved from being
a thinker to being an activist. Emerson and his circle may have
spoken and written against slavery, but they were not recorded as
sheltering runaway slaves, as Thoreau did. Thoreau recognised
in Brown someone who not only believed in a cause, but did
CABIN PIC © RYTHMICQUIETUDE 2010

something about it.


Thoreau can be presented as an outsider, but that does not
appear to be how his Concord neighbours viewed him. Small
communities can be intolerant of difference; but Thoreau was
accepted as a member of his community. He was eccentric, per-
haps: one of that increasingly rare breed, the Yankee individual-
ist. Yet he got on with people; he gave freely of his time and
thoughts to lecture in the Concord Lyceum (and was allowed to
do so); and he kept getting hired. After all, he was a damn good
surveyor, and knew how to make a good pencil.
© MARTIN JENKINS 2017
Replica of Thoreau’s cabin in the woods
Martin Jenkins is a retired community worker and Quaker in London.

42 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Letters
When inspiration strikes, don’t bottle it up!
Write to me at: Philosophy Now
43a Jerningham Road • London • SE14 5NQ, U.K.
or email rick.lewis@philosophynow.org
Keep them short and keep them coming!

Panpsychic Ricochets animals, and indeed many humans. no explanation is given of how this may
DEAR EDITOR: Issue 121 contained four The mysteriousness of all mental work. It’s a ‘just so’ story.
articles on radical theories of conscious- processes generally, and consciousness in Our consciousness however means
ness. The guest editor, Dr Philip Goff, is particular, is reminiscent of the earlier that we are aware of ourselves, and of
one of the four authors. It might have debate between mechanists and vitalists. ourselves in relation to our surroundings.
been better if an editor had been invited Virtually nobody now defends the notion So in what way are the physical proper-
who was more detached from the debate, of the élan vital as a necessity for life. I ties of sub-atomic particles – mass, spin,
as all four contributors, to varying believe that panpsychism will suffer the charge, etc – in their intrinsic nature
degrees, are sympathetic to panpsychism. same fate. I don’t know whether science forms of awareness, as Dr Goff asserts?
To describe panpsychism as counterin- will ever wholly understand conscious- Yes, they interact with other particles in
tuitive is a considerable understatement. ness, but no doubt much will be learnt in precise ways, but that’s not awareness.
The only example of consciousness to the endeavour. It is certainly much too Panpsychists argue that it’s a question
which we have direct access is that of early to give up on the enterprise. of degree. So we don’t ascribe human-
humans, and this we can confidently JOHN RADCLIFFE, WELWYN GDN CITY like awareness to mice or spiders. And so
assert is dependent upon the activity of just as we find it difficult to imagine
our brains. By analogy, on observing the DEAR EDITOR: While agnostic on the having a spider’s form of awareness, we
behaviour of higher animals we accept issue, I would offer a couple of points in find it even more difficult to understand
them as being conscious too. How far support of Phillip Goff’s panpsychism in the awareness enjoyed by a subatomic
down the animal kingdom this goes is Issue 121. I condition this on downplay- particle. And this, they say, leaves open
debatable. Most of us would be comfort- ing the term ‘consciousness’ and turn, the possibility that it has awareness in
able accrediting mice with some level of rather, to a suggestion made by Camilla some way. This is, however, argument by
consciousness, but would draw the line at, Martin in the PN podcast, ‘Free Will and analogy, which has no logical value. And,
say, an amoeba. But panpsychists regard the Brain’ [available at more importantly, if the argument is to
all physical entities as possessing conscious- philosophynow.org/podcasts, Ed]: What have any persuasive power, consciousness
ness. This extraordinary claim is founded we experience as consciousness is a must be recognisably the same at what-
upon our inability to give a detailed composite effect of data. ever level it is said to exist. Unless we
account of how consciousness emerges in First, I would ask the reader to think want to be in Humpty Dumpty land,
objects made up of quarks, electrons etc. about the act of reading this, then think ‘consciousness’ cannot completely change
Presumably if quarks and electrons have about their selves reading this, then meaning as it shrinks. Indeed, if panpsy-
some rudimentary consciousness, then a think about their selves thinking about chism is the best explanation currently
uranium atom, say, which is much more their selves reading this... We could go available, I think I shall get out my self-
complex, has a considerably enhanced on like that forever. But what we’ll never aware Ouija board to see what’s next in
level of consciousness. What about a see is what is looking out: the perceiving line to ‘explain’ consciousness.
pebble on the beach? What kind of inner thing. And how is our basic perception THOMAS JEFFREYS, WARWICKSHIRE
life does it possess? By the time we get to any different to that of, say, a gnat? The
the Rock of Gibraltar it must have a very only difference, as Douglas Hofstadter DEAR EDITOR: As a reason for disbeliev-
substantial conscious mental life indeed! I points out in I Am A Strange Loop, is the ing panpsychism, Raymond Tallis, in
confidently assert that no one has, or ever symbolic filters we use. And why stop with ‘Against Panpsychism’ (PN 121), asks
will have, any evidence that it has. a gnat? Plants, as recent research suggests, how the macroscopic consciousness of
I’m not arguing that consciousness communicate. How far of a jump would organisms can be built up out of elemen-
could only exist in biological entities. In it be to basic elements containing data? tary constituents and why such building
the vastness of the universe who can say D.E. TARKINGTON, BELLEVUE, NE up happens in some things but not others
what might have emerged? I also have an – in brains, for example, and not pebbles.
open mind regarding man-made DEAR EDITOR: The idea of panpsychism The answer is found in the organiza-
conscious systems. That some computer- is that awareness is inherent in every tion of the elementary constituents. If
based systems exhibit at least some aspect of matter, even though normally everything has an inside or subjective
aspects of intelligence is indisputable. we only recognise it in the animal king- aspect as panpsychism suggests, as well as
We must be careful not to set the level dom. The argument seems to be that an outside or objective aspect, then the
of intelligence demanded too high for because particles have consciousness, we organization of the outside should have
consciousness or we will disqualify most are also able to have consciousness. But some bearing on the richness of the

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 43


Letters
inside. There is something unique about higher energy orbital. From the informa- us two legs and two arms. But why? No-
how matter is organized in living beings, tion perspective, the system has one has ever shown in complete detail the
as opposed to non-living things, that can responded to a specific input of datum, biochemical processes by which this
account for the emergence of our which for the panexperientialist is a fleet- happens. Our acceptance of a DNA-based
complex and vivid form of consciousness. ing experience of something outside itself. explanation is just another example of a
Living things are strikingly different Consciousness is a result of the evolution- misplaced reliance on physicalism. And in
from inanimate objects. The matter that ary process when organisms are selected the absence of a complete physical expla-
composes living things is constantly that are able to integrate, attenuate or nation, the origin of our limbs remains
changing through metabolism, the amplify trillions of such data. As a result, unexplained and so should obviously be
process by which matter is ingested, the organism experiences the build-up of referred to as the hard problem of limbs.
transformed and excreted. What persists emotional states. These emotions produce For a philosopher, however, this prob-
is not the matter itself but the form in actions which, as required by evolution, lem is simple to resolve. We need only
which that matter is organized. I follow must be directed towards the organism’s postulate a panlimbist world. Specifically,
Hans Jonas here (pp.64-67 in Mortality survival and reproduction. In this way, the the reason we humans normally have four
and Morality, ed. Lawrence Vogel, 1996), process of evolution ensures that simple limbs is that everything has four limbs,
when he says that the sense of being a experiences become sophisticated presen- down to and including the smallest sub-
whole conscious entity emerges with the tations of the world. atomic particle. Of course we might have
ability of a simple organism to maintain DR STEVE BREWER, ST IVES to modify our definition of limbs a little
its structure through time by exchanging bit, and also the meaning of the number
matter with its environment. Thus a DEAR EDITOR: Philip Goff suggests that 4, in view of the absence of anything
changing material process that has a physicalists might object to panpsychist actually like limbs forming part of moun-
unity of form over time gives rise to a claims by arguing that “We just need a tains or oceans, or indeed electrons and
unity of experience over time which is of ‘Darwin of consciousness’ to come along” protons. We can instead say that they
a higher order than the micro-experi- (p.7). I suggest that physicalists already have an inherent quality much like, say,
ences of the constituent elements. have Darwin[s] of consciousness. One was mass or spin or the electro-weak force,
This higher order depends on the abil- Gerald Edelman (1929-2014), who shared which we could simply name ‘limb’. We
ity of mentality to bleed through, so to a 1972 Nobel Prize with Rodney Robert may then assert that this is fundamental
speak, from one event to another. Anecdo- Porter and wrote Bright Air, Brilliant Fire to enabling us to have what we would
tal evidence of telepathy suggests that (1992). The neurologist Oliver Sacks normally describe as limbs – just like the
mentality does indeed have such an ability. called his ideas “a radically biological assertion by panpsychists that the exis-
Given this account of how the global evolutionary theory of mind”. tence of consciousness in all matter,
mentalities of constituents can combine An interesting example of how Edel- although not in a form that fits the defi-
to form a single richer mentality, man’s major contributions to our under- nition of consciousness, is the source of
panpsychism does indeed make sense. I standing of consciousness have been human consciousness. Problem solved.
discuss the argument for panpsychism in extended is Giulio Tononi’s Integrated PAUL BUCKINGHAM, ANNECY, FRANCE
detail at bmeacham.com/blog/?p=568 Information Theory, as discussed by
BILL MEACHAM, USA Hedda Hassel Mørch in Issue 121. A Solace of Quantum
Tononi was a young member of Edel- DEAR EDITOR: Reading about the funda-
DEAR EDITOR: As a means to understand man’s team of researchers back in the mental laws of quantum mechanics
consciousness, I believe that panexperien- 1990s, and with Edelman co-authored (deterministic and probabilistic) in Issue
tialism (a term coined by the Whitehea- Consciousness: How Matter Becomes Imagi- 121 brought to mind the contrast
dian David Ray Griffin) is to be preferred nation in 2000. Tononi’s AI ‘conscious between when we are experiencing ‘flow’
to panpsychism. It has the advantage of machine’, engineered by “mimicking the and when we are painfully self-aware. In
being entirely consistent with the Inte- natural selection by which the human flow it can feel that we lose consciousness
grated Information Theory of Conscious- brain was created” as Mørch says (p.15), and are merely acting through learned
ness. In panexperientialism, a fleeting is significantly reminiscent of Edelman’s memories, completely absorbed and
experience is generated whenever physical team’s ‘neurally organised mobile adap- confident (deterministic). While self-
systems exchange energy-information, tive device’ (NOMAD). Edelman also conscious, however, our behaviour can
since they’re equivalent. How this might reminds us that “the conscious life [that feel and appear to ourselves and others as
happen can be understood by considering science] describes will always remain erratic, inconsistent, and unlike ourselves.
the simplest stable atomic system, the richer than its description” (Ibid, p.209). When self-consciousness is causing us to
hydrogen atom. In its lowest energy state, COLIN BROOKES, LEICESTERSHIRE ‘measure’ our performance against
it consists of a positively charged proton perceived expectations (that we believe we
orbited by a single negatively charged DEAR EDITOR: The concept of panpsy- cannot meet), it seems that our behaviour
electron. Here we have a system of sub- chism (Issue 121) has made me see that changes compared with presenting to an
atomic particles forming a dynamic yet invoking the existence of a hitherto unde- empty room or when experiencing flow,
self-contained physical system with no tected-as-universal property to explain the therefore the outcome is more uncertain
consciousness. When, however, this unexplained can be extended to other (so probabilistic), with a greater probabil-
system interacts with an externally mysteries. For instance, we are all too ity that we will appear ridiculous.
sourced photon, the electron jumps to a ready to believe that our DNA codes give FELICITY WILLIAMS, MILTON KEYNES

44 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Letters
an obligation to do so.” I think Sally’s 2. The relationship between these symbols
point of view and way forward – that she and reality is contested. They have no
‘intends to embrace [having a designer meaning except by reference to other
baby]’ and that the choice is both her symbols and are ultimately self-referential.
‘right’ and ‘obligation’ (both words orig- 3. The mechanisms by which new patterns
inally italicized) – are unequivocal. of symbols emerge are not understood.
KEITH TIDMAN, MARYLAND 4. There is no convergence between the
patterns that emerge.
Serious Misrepresentations 5. The relationship between these
DEAR EDITOR: I notice that Vincent di processes and the structure of their
Norcia refers to my book Environmental claimed target is not known.
Philosophy: An Introduction (Polity, 2015) Er... that’s it. Should I cancel my
in his review of Patrick Curry’s Ecological subscription? [No. Why resort to merely
Ethics in Issue 122 of Philosophy Now. I am symbolic gestures? – Ed]
grateful to Professor di Norcia for DAVID KERNICK, EXETER, DEVON
mentioning my book; however, I must
point out that he has misrepresented my Poet’s Corner
In Praise of Brain Hats view on the issue of population control. DEAR EDITOR: Interviewed in Issue 120,
DEAR EDITOR: I am writing to tell you He claims that I argue that we must not Raymond Tallis mentioned his disagree-
how much I enjoyed the cover photo on just limit population growth, we must ment with D.H. Mellor’s notion that
#121. The brain hats are so imaginative reduce our numbers to sustainable levels, time is a causal dimension of space-time.
and inventive! I’m seriously considering and, in support of this claim, he refers the This got me to wondering:
how to make one for myself. It might be reader to p.54 and pp.144 ff of my book. were time to cease –
of some help when I am thinking about Yet I argue no such thing. On p.54, I would strings cease their singing?
philosophical problems. Sometimes all maintain that it would be appalling to spheres cease their song?
you need is a little extra confidence. suggest we should welcome such events K.O. SMITH, ASHEVILLE, NC
D. N. DIMMITT, LAWRENCE, KANSAS as droughts and famines, which reduce
the global population of human beings. DEAR EDITOR: A haiku response to 118’s
Serious Baby Talk On pp.144 ff, I do not argue that we must ‘Hens, Ducks & Human Rights in China’:
DEAR EDITOR: I would argue that Quinn reduce the global population of human China/West memo:
Rivet, in commenting in Letters, Issue beings; I suggest that rates of population ‘We’ is not a plural ‘I’.
121 on my dialog ‘Are Designer Babies growth in some of the world’s poorer Hens and ducks talking.
Our Future?’ in Issue 119, is actually in countries could be reduced by such ALASDAIR MACDONALD, GLASGOW
the same camp as I. In the case of the measures as alleviating poverty and
exchange between my two acquain- enacting social reforms to give women Wittgenstein
tances, Pat simply served as my dialog’s more control over their lives. Numbers are better than words he said,
convenient foil in alluding to the puta- SIMON JAMES, DURHAM UNIVERSITY For numbers exist outside our heads.
tive downsides of genetic manipulation, But words are made up by you and me,
especially of so-called ‘designer babies’. DEAR EDITOR: Issue 122 of PN has just And do not exist in reality.
My position on genetic engineering and arrived, excellent as ever. I question, JEFFREY WALD, FALCON HEIGHTS, MN
designer babies should have been clear however, whether the portrait purport-
from the arguments presented by Sally edly of Michael Oakeshott (whom I DEAR EDITOR: From Russell’s quote in
in order to push back against Pat – argu- knew) is really of Oakeshott and not of 120, “To be happy, one must first not be
ments that I made stronger than Pat’s. his colleague, Maurice Cranston, whom unhappy” I was inspired by a Rodgers
For instance, the dialog opens with Sally I also knew. A quick check on the Inter- and Hart standard, and by Lord Byron:
saying, “I want to decide my baby’s net shows the resemblance of the
traits. Genetic engineering is making portrait to Cranston. [Ed.: You’re right, it Glad To Be Unhappy
that possible” and ends with her saying, is Cranston. Very sorry about that!] Fools rush in, so here I am
even more forcefully, “I believe it’s just a DR GEOFFREY THOMAS, FORMERLY Very glad to be unhappy
matter of time. Eventually people will RESEARCH FELLOW, BIRKBECK COLLEGE, I can’t win, but here I am
iron out the scientific, ethical, and social UNIVERSITY OF LONDON More than glad to be unhappy
wrinkles, and be selecting their babies’ Unrequited love’s a bore
preferred traits. What’s seen as accept- Philosophy as Pattern Recognition And I’ve got it pretty bad
able will change dramatically over the DEAR EDITOR: Knowing nothing about But for someone you adore
next twenty or thirty years, and gene philosophy, I was introduced to your It’s a pleasure to be sad
editing can’t be uninvented! Personally, I journal some eighteen months ago and I Like a straying baby lamb
intend to embrace it as far as the means now feel in a position to offer an obser- With no mammy and no pappy
are available. I think not only do I have a vation on the nature of the discipline: I’m so unhappy
right to give birth to a healthy, smart, 1. Philosophy studies how patterns of But oh so glad!
capable, competitive child if I can, I have symbols interact to form new patterns. RAY SHERMAN, USA

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 45


Grant Sterling asks some immediate questions about

Books Ultimate Questions, and John Greenbank asks if science


can ultimately tell us anything about artistic experience.

Ultimate Questions So this is the great theme of Ultimate Ques-


by Bryan Magee tions: our ignorance is astoundingly vast.

BRYAN MAGEE’S ULTIMATE Unknowable Unknowables


Questions (2016) is a Having spent a great deal of time trying to
thought-provoking and show how reality spills over the boundaries
interesting book with some strong passages, of the natural world as studied by scientists,
but in the end we still have many questions, Magee turns to a discussion of those philoso-
and fewer answers. phers who attempt to solve the problem of
Magee apparently wishes to be known as the vast unknowability of it all. Ignorance,
the great agnostic philosopher. The flavor especially inescapable ignorance, is distress-
of his agnosticism can be seen in this passage, ing, so it is no surprise that many people look
which provides a good summary of this book: for doctrines which avoid the possibility.
One way to do this, which Magee primar-
“The unknowable and unconceptualizable ily associates with Hegel’s idealism, would be
spill over into our empirical world. We live to narrow the concept of ‘truth’ by holding
amongst them all the time. We are mysteries that it is grounded in our consciousness. In
to ourselves, and to one another. In our sex- this way, all the alleged unknowables would
ual relationships the miraculous happens, be swept away: ‘truths unknowable by
and happens again in the creation of new humans’ would be, by definition, impossible
life. We do not understand life or death. – a self-contradiction. Magee rejects this
Nor do we understand time. . . ‘What is it position: no matter how comforting the idea
about our empirical world that convinces that truth is what is knowable by humanity
you that there must be something else?’ I am proper organs. Moreover, it is overwhelm- might be, there are simply no arguments that
tempted to say, ‘Everything.’” (pp.56-7). ingly likely that there are countless aspects of can prove that it’s true, and it is unacceptable
reality that no living being can possibly expe- to believe in such a doctrine without proof.
Magee repeatedly emphasizes this idea rience, because the necessary organs cannot A popular way to escape the limits of our
that reality is, or is likely to be, far greater and exist. This means that not only are there ignorance is to hold that we can have knowl-
deeper than the physical world we perceive. countless truths that we do not know, there edge about a supernatural realm. If we
For example, we know some moral truths; are entire realms of truth that we cannot even cannot eliminate the unknowables by
and morality, he thinks, cannot be reduced
to a social convention. We perceive the phys-


ical world; and yet our own consciousness
cannot be understood by what we know An interesting read, and a good antidote to
about the physical world. Music cannot be
explained in words, and yet it offers insights
the widespread modern tendency of people
into reality that words could never convey. to naïvely assume that modern science
knows all and sees all.


We see other people, but what we know
about them, how we understand them, and
how we relate to them, is so much more than
with the perception of other physical objects.
When we have sex, especially, we can
encounter something that is so much more begin to conceptualize. Combine this with reducing them to the physical or by restrict-
than the physical interaction of two objects. the fact that even what we do experience is ing truth to what can be in our conscious-
Magee rejects all attempts at reduction- only the tiniest fraction of what exists in the ness, then why not simply accept that the
ism, and all attempts to confine reality to the world right now; and that the world right now supernatural exists, and find a way to know
boundaries of the empirical realm. After all, represents only an instant in the history of a it? And if our senses and consciousnesses are
he argues, we happen to have five major species that has existed for hundreds of thou- inadequate to know it, why not just accept
senses, but we know that some other animals sands of years and that Magee confidently that there is a being greater than us who can
have fewer, and some have senses that we assumes is likely to continue to exist for impart some knowledge of it to us – the most
don’t have, such as echolocation in bats. So hundreds of thousands or even millions of important parts, no doubt? In short, why
we know that there are aspects of reality that years, and the sheer volume of the unknown not turn to religion? But Magee has the
we cannot sense, because we don’t have the and unknowable should give us pause. same view of religion that he has of Hegelian

46 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018 Book Reviews


Books
idealism: of course there could be a deity, just ture and paintings, or be uplifted by the psychology, which for Baumgarten was a
as “it could also be true that my living room sound of words and music? Beauty was a discipline that investigates the depths of the
is full of silent, invisible, intangible primary theme among ancient Hellenistic soul, that is, the source of our representa-
monkeys” (p. 22); but there is no proof avail- and Medieval philosophers, and was central tions or experience. Baumgarten seems
able for such a belief, and so this strategy to Eighteenth and Nineteenth Century thence to adopt the traditional idea of beauty
must also be rejected. thought, as represented in treatments by as ‘unity in variety’. Kant, who greatly
This, however, is the part of the book that such diverse thinkers as Shaftesbury, Hutch- respected Baumgarten, failed to disentangle
most needs our attention. Magee repeatedly eson, Hume and Burke in Britain, and by these aspects.
treats religious beliefs as if they’re all trans- Baumgarten, Kant, Hegel and Schopen- Our sense of a breathtaking encounter is
parently nothing more than wish-fulfill- hauer in Germany. not like a process of rational thought, but is
ment, so that there is no need to respond to Alexander Baumgarten (1714-1762) one of a significant disclosure, a sudden
them with arguments. He writes, “Religious thought that the senses had their own rules breaking-in to our awareness. We are
discourse has this general characteristic. It is and their own perfection, differing from inspired variously by feelings of devotion,
a form of unjustified evasion, a failure to face logical rules and the knowledge generated gratitude, identification, admiration, joy,
up to the reality of ignorance as our natural by logical thought-processing. The rules of even of love. All such experience exemplifies
and inevitable starting point.” (p.31). This perception were to be studied by a science Kant’s idea of imaginative ‘play’, perhaps to
conclusion might be justified if it were of perception, which Baumgarten called be interpreted as the human creative drive
supported with arguments; but here it is aesthetics, from the Greek for ‘to or creative response to the world. Even the
Magee who offers none. Certainly, though, sense/perceive’. In 1739 he claimed in §533 more mundane aspects of our experience –
this vision of religious thought does little of his Metaphysica that, “The science of this form and balance, symmetry and complete-
justice to thoughtful writers such as Aquinas sensible knowledge and speaking is ness – are also component parts of aestheti-
or Augustine. AESTHETICS (the logic of the lower cism. And yet as a species we seem to take
Ultimate Questions is an interesting read, cognitive faculty, the philosophy of the all this experience for granted; all as normal
and a good antidote to the widespread graces and the muses, a lower doctrine of as breathing and sleeping.
modern tendency of people to naïvely knowledge, the art of thinking beautifully,
assume that modern science knows all and the art of analogy to reason)” (my transla- Art Under Science
sees all – the sort of people who, like Horatio tion). This formulation leaves us with a mix But now our aesthetic sensibilities are being
in Hamlet, refuse to allow that there may be of unassociated references: to science, logic, brought under close ‘scientific’ scrutiny.
more things in Heaven and Earth than are a ‘lower cognitive faculty’, philosophy, and Psychoanalysts, particularly Freud and Jung,
dreamt of in their empirical philosophies. to the ‘art of thinking beautifully’. ‘Logic’, delved into our deepest desires, and in doing
But the book seems to merely assert the in the tradition to which Baumgarten (and so exposed unexpected psychological mech-
truth of inescapable agnosticism, rather than Kant) belonged, does not refer to a formal anisms and motives. However, these findings
supporting the assertion. In any case the discipline, but to how a given mental faculty are being extended and transformed by
book is aptly titled: it does raise some of the is to be exercised in the most efficient way – cognitive science and neurology. Can its
ultimate questions, whatever the reader may thus there can be a logic of sensibility. Such empirical findings be meaningfully related to
think about the answers that are offered. a logic must incorporate the findings of aesthetic awareness? When science gets so
© DR GRANT STERLING 2017
Grant Sterling is a professor of Philosophy at
Eastern Illinois University. St Georges Major At Dusk
by Claude Monet, 1908
• Ultimate Questions, Bryan Magee, Princeton,
2016, 144 pages, £14.95, ISBN: 0691170657

Aesthetics & The


Sciences of Mind
Editors Currie, Kieran,
Meskin, & Robson

THE NATURE OF BEAUTY


is one of the most endur-
ing and controversial themes in Western
philosophy, and along with the nature of art,
is one of the two fundamental issues in
aesthetics. Along with goodness, truth, and
justice, beauty has traditionally been
counted among the ultimate values. What
would life be like if we could not respond to
the beauty of sea and landscape, enjoy mind-
transporting novels, admire great architec-

Book Reviews December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 47


Books
involved, have aestheticians reason to feel discourse. In philosophy, reason or reflection successfully rationalise their own experience
uneasy? Philosophical thinking about alone is used for deriving the truth or falsity of artistic works. If aesthetic appreciation is
aesthetics has been tied to the idea that of propositions. Whilst language, letters, at least partly a matter of sufficient correct
philosophy’s business is primarily to analyse words, truths, numbers, logic, and mathe- perception, then a psychologist must deter-
concepts. This approach contrasts with the matics, all exist only in the mind, the primary mine both when correct perception has
methods of psychologists, sociologists, and source of scientific evidence is the senses. occurred, and that it is in fact sufficient to
comprehend the piece. Few great works of
art necessarily make their effect on first
encounter, but over a period of exposure and
reflection. Conversation between two view-
ers of, say, the same painting, can result in a
deeper perception of aspects of the work for
both, without there being any resort to ratio-
nalising explanation. This is despite Lopes’
assertion that appreciation of a Monet paint-
ing involves ‘being aware’ of the features that
‘make it beautiful’. This is almost to replace,
say, a feeling of (aesthetic) happiness with an
assessment of the reasons for being happy.
In ‘Is Aesthetic Experience Possible?’,
Sherri Irvin asks “what if it turns out that we
don’t have introspective access to the
processes by which our aesthetic responses
even evolutionary theorists. How far should Music is perhaps the most universal art are produced?” (p.37). Here again commen-
philosophers be responsive to the results of form. We can appreciate melody, rhythm, tary on aesthetics is seen only at the level of
these studies? Should philosophers’ views on harmonic texture and dynamic contrast as post hoc rationalisation, as a scientific evalu-
aesthetic values, interpretation, imagination, separate but correlated attributes of a single ation of artistic experience. But experiments
and the emotions of art, change in the light experience. Together they function as a on how consumers evaluate the quality of,
of scientific understanding? Aesthetics & The complex language – the foundational ‘song say, soft drinks, hardly compare with exper-
Sciences of Mind (2014) asks, “Are the tradi- without words’. From both a performer’s imentally analysing exposure to works of
tional methods of philosophical aesthetics and a listener’s perspective, understanding human creative achievement in painting,
adequate, or should we supplement – even of that language can certainly be deepened architecture or music. And one aspect of
replace – them with some of the methods by increasing familiarity. After attending a aesthetic analysis that is not evaluated in
employed by the natural and social sciences?” concert we can discuss our experience with experiments is the transformative nature of
Aesthetics and science have progressed as other listeners, sharing with them quite the experience. How does it change us? A
separate fields of study for at least three specific aspects of the performance, down distinction is made between aesthetic expe-
centuries, but there is an apparent danger even to the effect of individual passages. For rience and aesthetic appreciation, and a
that academic ambition (hubris?) is this to be possible each person’s understand- further distinction between mere apprecia-
currently inspired to bring everything into ing must be first hand, at the level of tion and deep appreciation, involving, in the
conformity with scientific methods. Neuro- personal disclosure; a direct, intimate expe- latter case, non-aesthetic components:
science might be able to help to answer rience, for which there can be no substitute. “Deep aesthetic appreciation involves
whether music and ballet are to be under- So is it even conceivable that we could understanding of how the artwork achieves
stood as providing essentially different types account for – and so ‘explain’ – the arts in its effects.” This is a fundamental misunder-
of aesthetic responses from, say, painting terms of measurable responses, and standing of the nature of aesthetic experi-
and sculpture, or whether the senses of hear- outcomes that can be summarised in charts ence, for which no rational explanatory
ing, seeing and touch provide aesthetically and graphs? And can the impact of a work components are directly contributory. It
equivalent experiences. But does a scientifi- of art be reducible to its components? also undermines Irvin’s strong appeal to
cally experimentable entity such as a mirror mindfulness as relevant to responding to
neurone, or its activity, meaningfully match The Authors’ Artistic Experiences “aesthetically relevant features” (p49).
to anything described as ‘aesthetic’? The contributors to this wide-ranging book David Davies’ ‘“This is Your Brain on
For there to be any meaningful relation- bring various points of view to the central Art”: What Can Philosophy of Art Learn
ship between aesthetics and the sciences of issues. from Neuroscience?’ repeats the old ques-
mind, all terms and categories used in Dominic McIver Lopes sees social tion of whether there is an aesthetic differ-
comparing ideas between them must be at psychology as supporting the idea that ence between a work of art and a forgery,
least congruent – they must mean the same reason plays no part in aesthetic judgement, and queries our responses to literary fiction,
thing in both domains. Congruency also and further, that post hoc rationalisations and the aesthetic significance of hearing old
requires that any new knowledge found must cause ‘distortion’ in that judgement. He music performed on contemporary instru-
be consistent with whatever old knowledge implies (correctly) that it is not reasoning ments. And can the intentions of an artist, a
we want to retain. Scientific enquiry that provides aesthetic satisfaction, but he writer or a composer be frustrated by the
contrasts with that of philosophical seems muddled as to whether critics can unprepared reception of a work? Prepara-

48 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018 Book Reviews


Books
tion, by for example, reading up about a balance; and what he calls default principles, the cart before the horse in demoting
painting or a piece of music before experi- such as elegance always being beautiful. But ‘aesthetic features’ of a work below a consid-
encing it, only facilitates the essential such aspects of beauty are not ‘components’ eration of its production.
aesthetic process or event: it does not of art. Aesthetics is not atomistic. He’s mostly Perhaps the most stimulating contribu-
contribute to the aesthetic experience itself. right that “empirical evidence cannot provide tion is ‘Seeing with Feeling’, where Jesse
Prinz approvingly quotes C.I. Lewis’s idea
that “the beauty of the rose is its form and
colour.” This is a phenomenological viewpoint
on beauty: beauty is not conceptual, but it
can be seen. He considers such objections as
the ‘Puzzle of Manifest Beauty’, whereby we
do not (can not) register complexity
phenomenologically. His conclusion is that
“Beauty is not there to be seen, but there in
the seeing” (p.156).
Other contributors to this book address
relatively peripheral issues. So I would say
that although there is no doubting the
commitment and intellectual engagement
exhibited throughout this book, the lack of
secure critical foundations leads rather
quickly to confusion and a deepening
uncertainty, where explanations become
too reductive, and what is important about
the aesthetic experience gets explained
away.

The Way Forward?


We can say that philosophy is concerned
with ideas about ideas; science with ideas
about things in the world and their relations;
and aesthetics (along with ethics) with expe-
rienced emergent values.
We need a procedure to record, classify
Rembrandt self-portrait, 1660
and associate agreement in matters
aesthetic: the ‘greatness’ of art, the ‘beauty’
So far as aesthetic response occurs or devel- any non-inferential justification for aesthetic of a landscape, the ‘power’ of a musical
ops over time, rather than immediately and judgements”, but wrong about there being a composition. These may be given quantifi-
completely on initial exposure, any means of parallel between an aesthetic response and, able values through established procedures
focusing attention on the artistic experience say, estimating the size of a crowd. of opinion polling and sampling. I propose
will be helpful; but this supplementary assis- In ‘Portrait of the Artist as an Aesthetic that we refer to any consensus achieved in
tance is not ‘of one substance with’ the Expert’, Christy Mag Uidhir and Cameron this process as ‘collective subjectivity’.
aesthetic experience itself. Buckner try to reframe the aesthetic theory Though more extreme forms of art must
A fundamental difference between the of art (which refers to aesthetic features of an remain closed off to more people, I suggest,
aesthetic and the scientific is that aesthetic artwork) by claiming that instead of the piece nevertheless, that a collective subjective
phenomena should only be seen holistically – of art holding any aesthetic quality in itself, evaluation can be used (with various degrees
we cannot reductively analyse a work of art – it attains the status of art by virtue of its of confidence) to make quantifiable value
whereas science breaks phenomena up into creation by an artist, who holds in mind an judgements that are more than simply
elements that have significance in themselves. ‘aesthetic concept’. So we have a new pairing, ephemeral matters of taste.
This means that what science is looking for is not between “artworks and their aesthetic Might we now begin to answer Baum-
quite different from what the art appreciator features but instead between artists and their garten’s concerns?
is looking for. So, whilst Davies explores the aesthetic concepts” (p.125). They also argue © JOHN GREENBANK 2017
role of mirror neurons in response to fiction, that artists with training are more likely to John Greenbank graduated in Natural Sciences
he moderates his enthusiasm for experimen- attain the status of ‘aesthetic experts’ and and English from Clare College, Cambridge, and
tal data by stating that “most of the significant have a better grasp of aesthetic concepts. The in Mathematics from the Open University, and
philosophical issues cannot be resolved by outlook is naïve: “What kinds of training or is a trained concert singer.
appeal to this” (p.74). practice have expert artists received, and
In ‘The Limits of Aesthetic Empiricism’, what role do aesthetic concepts play in their • Aesthetics & The Sciences of Mind, Eds Greg
Fabian Dorsch refers to two kinds of aesthetic distinctive perceptual, motor, and concep- Currie, Matthew Kieran, Aaron Meskin, Jon Robson,
principle: conceptual principles, such as tual abilities?” (p.130). Their conclusion puts OUP, 2014, 272 pages, £48 hb, ISBN: 0199669635

Book Reviews December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 49


THE BIG
LEBOWSKI
Film Matt Qvortrup contemplates Dude philosophy.

M
aybe, just maybe, the mean- The Big Lebowski might have lent itself to ideals of the Enlightenment. But for direc-
ing of life is to live it: to leave a lazy rehash of the postmodern theories of tors Joel and Ethan Coen, The Big Lebowski
the worries to one side and, Jean Baudrillard, who wrote about “the end was their first foray into Greco-Roman
as in The Big Lebowski, say, of meta-narratives,” or what he saw as the philosophy. They would later direct a
“F**k it… let’s go bowling” – or whatever extinction in the late 20th century of any remake of Homer’s Odysseus in the Deep
pointless activity takes your fancy. grand overarching ideas about plans or South in Brother, Where Art Thou? (2000),
To assent to this idea, it must be said, is purposes for human life. To be sure there and recently Hail Caesar (2016). Coen
not to assert that the philosophy of The Big are elements of this in the movie, as is Brothers movies often contain philosophi-
Lebowski (1998) can be reduced to a single perhaps natural given that it was made at cal references. In Hail Caesar, there is even
insight. Indeed, it is in the nature of the true the time when America was confronting a cameo appearance by Herbert Marcuse,
work of art that it contains many, often Saddam Hussein (who is irreverently the German émigré Marxist Professor, who
contradictory, stands. This film is no excep- referred to as “that camel f**ker in Iraq” by talks about “Ze dialectic” to George
tion. Still, it is above all a funny film, with a Walter Sobchak, a cantankerous Vietnam Clooney’s hapless and very impressionable
perfectly cast Jeff Bridges as the antihero vet played by John Goodman). But overall, character. But The Big Lebowski is (perhaps
Jeffrey Lebowski, who answers to ‘the for those who watch this movie with a unwittingly) their most complete rehearsal
Dude’, or “his Dudeness, Duder, or El philosophical eye, it is almost breath-taking of philosophical themes.
Duderino if you’re not into the whole how many references there are to non-post-
brevity thing.” The film is not a treatise on modern thought; how the characters almost The Big Stoic
practical philosophy, but an exuberant go out of their way to insist on meta-narra- Is it just coincidental that Ethan Coen, who
display of cinematographic playfulness, tives, on purposes. For example, reflecting earned a BA in Philosophy at Princeton,
showcasing the directors’ effortless comic on nihilism (a concept not much discussed endowed the Dude with such a strong dose
genius. Nor is this just a chronicle of the in other Hollywood blockbusters), Walter of Socratic irony? If Socrates had lived in
unemployed Lebowski’s descent into the – a convert to Judaism – dismisses this anti- L.A. in the early 1990s, would he not have
underworld of early 1990s Los Angeles due creed with characteristic bluntness: been a dude? A bearded, slightly overweight
to a case of mistaken identity. It is also (and “Nihilists? F**k me! National Socialism… character, well-liked by his friends, a medi-
perhaps even more so) a cacophony of small at least it’s an ethos.” And the self-same tating ten-pin bowler with a resigned and
and seemingly unrelated events woven into Walter notes that “this is not Nam, there irreverent attitude to life, he shares many of
a tapestry of the sublime and the ridiculous. are rules.” The Big Lebowski is not a movie the characteristics of the Athenian sage
How many movies begin with the main based on the stringent logic of a René portrayed in Plato’s earlier dialogues. And
character writing a cheque for 69 cents? Descartes, still less one that portrays the yet the Dude is not always a convincing
Socrates. His philosophy is not that the
unexamined life is not worth living, as
Socrates famously asserted in Plato’s Apol-
ogy. Rather, if this movie is anything philo-
sophical, it is Stoic.
Stoicism can be summed up as a philos-
ophy of how to face adversity with equanim-
ity. Founded in Athens by Zeno of Citium
in the Third Century BC, Stoicism taught
that to live the good life one has to under-
stand the natural order of things; that what
happens to you is often beyond your
control, but you can control how you
respond to it emotionally. Not merely a
practical philosophy, the Stoics were also
pioneers of a propositional logic which
some commentators consider to be close to
the logic of Gottlob Frege (1848-1925). But
these considerations, as well as their dualist
metaphysics, were but means to an end – to
The Dude samples the good life develop a philosophy of the good and
contented life. Having been established in

50 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


The Dude’s
No.9 dream

Film
BIG LEBOWSKI IMAGES © WORKING TITLE PRODUCTIONS 1998

“ If Socrates had lived


in L.A. in the early
1990s, would he not
have been a dude?

Greece, where Epictetus further developed


it in the Second Century BC, Stoicism was
given a more popular form by Roman
philosophers including Seneca (4BC-65
AD) and Rome’s philosophising Emperor,
Marcus Aurelius (121-180 AD).
Like a good Stoic, the Dude is above all
Stoic). And what constitutes contentment
for the Dude is summed up in the words
“bowl, drive around, and the occasional acid
flashback” – in other words to live in the
present and to be content with his lot. In
this, the Dude is the very personification of
Seneca’s definition of ‘the wise man’, some-
the humanities and the arts insist on the
interplay of multiple perspectives, which can
only be experienced through artistic expres-
sion. The cinematic arts are no exception.
The Dude’s Stoicism is not of an abstract
nature, nor is it adhered to with unfailing
consistency. Greatness means to be so large

calm in the face of adversity. When two one who “is content with his lot, whatever it that there is room for contradictions. The
angry mobsters push his head into a toilet may be, without wishing for what he has Dude is – if pressed – capable of anger,
bowl and demand “Where’s the money, not” (Letters). This is a man whose life though often in a resigned fashion: “You’re
Lebowski?” he stoically responds, “It’s uh… centres around bowling; although he does not wrong Walter, you’re just an a**hole!”
it’s down there somewhere, let me take care a little about replacing a rug that “tied And like Christ in the desert, the Dude is
another look.” After the Dude has suffered the room together.” tempted to depart from his true inner beliefs.
no end of misfortune, the narrator of the Egged on by Walter, he is lured by the
movie, ‘the Stranger’ – a Texan with a Niet- Core Dudeism promise of easy money; but in its pursuit he
zschian moustache – observes that life goes To claim that the Dude is a Stoic is clearly only finds himself at the mercy of nihilists
on, and that we can still look to him for open to criticism (as all philosophy should and the occasional pornographer.
guidance: “Up and down, the Dude is out be!). Philosophical analogies are never According to the early Stoic Epictetus,
there taking it easy for all us sinners.” ‘Us entirely accurate in works of art, and char-
sinners’ are caught up in a debilitating rat- acters in movies are by definition larger and “Philosophy does not promise to secure
race and would do better to emulate a lazy more multifaceted than the abstractions of anything external for man, otherwise it would
man – “and the Dude certainly was that.” philosophy. It should also be noted that the be admitting something that lies beyond its
“True happiness”, as Seneca observed, “is to film has given rise to a semi-religious philos- proper subject-matter. For as the material of
enjoy the present, without anxious depen- ophy of a Daoist nature, often referred to as the carpenter is wood and that of the statuary
dence upon the future” (Letters From A Dudeism. Jeff Bridges even co-authored a bronze, so the subject matter of the art of
book about the philosophy of the film living is each person’s own life”
The Stranger with the moustache (Bernie Glassman and Jeff Bridges, The (Discourses 1.15).
Dude and the Zen Master, 2014). But it is not
the prerogative of the artist to interpret his To be inspired by and follow the Dude’s
work. It is for the spectator, not the actor, to philosophy of life also does not promise to
draw lessons, find similarities, and take the secure anything external. Finally bereft of
longer view. both his friend Danny (played by Coen
All analysis can become uninspiring if Bros. regular Steve Buscemi) and his
pushed too far. The beauty of art as a means beloved rug, the Dude returns to enjoying
of representing philosophical truths is that the quiet life of drinking White Russians in
there are insights that can only be repre- suburban L.A. and living in accordance with
sented and understood in an artistic form; Walter’s final philosophical insight: “F**k it
perceptions that somehow go beyond ratio- Dude, let’s go bowling.”
nal comprehension and scientific reduction- © DR MATT QVORTRUP 2017
ism. While the sciences generally seek to Matt Qvortrup is a dude, and Professor of
break things down into their simplest parts, Politics at Coventry University.

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 51


Subscribe to Philosophy Now
philosophynow.org
6 IDEA-PACKED ISSUES FOR £15.50/$32*

With a subscription to Philosophy Now you can save up to


30% off the newsstand price, have your copies delivered
to your door and enjoy unrestricted access to our online
content. Subscribe today at philosophynow.org or fill
out and return one of the coupons below.

Subscription inquiries: email subscriptions@philosophynow.org or phone 01959 534171


To tell us about a change of address, please email addresschange@philosophynow.org
*price is in US Dollars

UK / Rest of World United States


Name Name _____________________________________________
Address Address ___________________________________________
___________________________________________________
Email Email ______________________________________________
Subscribe to Philosophy Now for 6 issues (1 year)
Subscribe to Philosophy Now for 12 issues (2 years) Subscribe to Philosophy Now for 6 issues ($32)
UK 15.50/28 (GBP)
Canada 37/69 (CAD) Subscribe to Philosophy Now for 12 issues ($59)
New Zealand 49/93 (NZD)
Australia 40/75 (AUD) Starting with Issue #123/Issue #124 (delete as appropriate)
Europe 23/42 (EUR)
Rest of World 21/37 (GBP)

Starting with Issue 123/Issue 124 (delete as appropriate)


Buy back issues on CD (please circle)
Buy back issues on CD (please circle) Vol.1/Vol.2/Vol.3/Vol.4
Vol.1/Vol.2/Vol.3/Vol.4
Buy back issues in PRINT (please specify issue no.s)
Buy back issues in PRINT (please specify issue no.s) ______________________________________
______________________________________
Buy _____ binders to hold back issues (insert quantity)
Buy _____ binders to hold back issues (insert quantity)
TOTAL AMOUNT PAYABLE: $_________
TOTAL AMOUNT PAYABLE: _________
Please make your cheque payable to ‘Philosophy Documentation
Please make your cheque payable to ‘Philosophy Now’ or fill in your Center’ or fill in your details below:
Mastercard /Visa /Maestro card details below:
Card no.
Card no. Expiry_________________ Security Code__________
Expiry__________________ Security Code___________ Name on card ________________________________________________
Name on card ________________________________________________ and send it to: Philosophy Documentation Center,
and send it to: Philosophy Now Subscriptions P.O. Box 7147
Kelvin House, Grays Road, Charlottesville, VA, 22906-7147
Westerham, Kent TN16 2JB, U.S.A
United Kingdom

52 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Digital Editions and Back Issues
Digital Editions (see philosophynow.org/digital)
Website Subscriptions
Print subscriptions to Philosophy Now don’t include Kindle, Nook, app content etc but do include access to our website which has
2,500+ articles from past issues. Password is available on request or is sent automatically if you subscribe online. We also sell
website subscriptions separately, from our store at philosophynow.org/shop

IP-based online access is available for schools and colleges – visit philosophynow.org/institutions

App Philoso
phy Now
Available in the Apple App Store and Google Play store. Free sample issue included.

Kindle
Buy a single issue or an ongoing subscription. (30 day free trial)

Nook
Available on Barnes & Noble’s Nook reader and the Nook app. (14 day free trial)

Zinio
There is also an edition for the Zinio app on iPad and Android. Single issue or ongoing subscription.
Back Issues in Print T-shirts
Issue 120 Russell: Philosophy, Passion, Life, Reason, Logic / Essentialism /
End of Individualism / Morality of Divorce / Westworld review We now sell Philosophy Now T-shirts on Amazon. They
Issue 121 Radical Consciousness: Panpsychism; Neutral Monism; IIT; make great birthday presents. The shirts are made, sold and
Quantum Collapse / Trump’s Language / Rawls Brief Life / Foucault dispatched by Amazon.com. Available only in the USA, com-
Issue 122 Socrates & Plato, on vision, love, memory, politics & Facebook /
Zizek interview / Cubism / Experience machines / Pirsig’s Quality ing to the rest of the world soon.

We also still have copies of these earlier back issues: The shirts cost $18.00 each.
Issues 2, 4, 39-47, 55-80, 82, 84, 85, 87-89, 91-119
There are four designs so far,
For full details and tables of contents of all back issues, please
visit our online shop at philosophynow.org/shop with more following soon.
Each is available in a variety
Back issues cost £3.75 each if you live in the UK (inc p&p) or of colors and sizes. To visit
US$10/C$10/A$10/NZ$12/£6.50 elsewhere via airmail. For the Philosophy Now T-shirt
every three back issues you buy, we’ll give you a fourth for free shop on Amazon.com, please
(please tell us which you would like). type this shortened address
exactly:
Binders: Our smart green Philosophy Now binders each hold
12 magazines. UK£8.75, US$25, A$27,C$27, NZ$34, or Rest http://amzn.to/2fKrwPF
of World £15.

PDFs: Available for purchase from our online shop

Back Issues on CD
Philosophy Now has been published since 1991, so it is hardly surprising that we’re often asked for back
issues which have long since sold out. Therefore we’ve put our first eighty issues onto four CDs in
PDF format.

Vol. 1: Issues 01-20; Vol. 2: Issues 21-40; Vol. 3: Issues 41-60; Vol. 4: Issues 61-80
Single vol. (1, 2, 3 or 4) UK£15 US$23 Can$35 Aus$35 NZ$40 RoW£17
Two volumes: UK£25 US$40 Can$55 Aus$55 NZ$65 RoW£30
Three volumes: UK£35 US$55 Can$75 Aus$75 NZ$90 RoW£40
Four volumes: UK£45 US$69 Can$95 Aus$95 NZ$115 RoW£51

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 53


Death &
T allis The Philosopher
in
Wonderland Raymond Tallis on philosophical attitudes to non-being.

I
have recently been rereading Thomas model we form we usually forget about of our non-existence may sometimes be
Nagel’s The View from Nowhere (1986). them” (p.163). In other words, if objective curiously exhilarating. The darkness of
In the more than thirty years since its reality, and the world seen through the glass death’s dateless (and dataless) night, the
publication, the standing of this rela- eye of mathematical physics, were really the undifferentiated Nothing that awaits us – or
tively slim volume has grown steadily. To full story, there would be no physics. There rather, doesn’t even bother to await us –
borrow a metaphor that George Santayana would be no world pictures, no ‘view from highlights, by contrast, the multi-layered
applied to Spinoza, “like a mountain nowhere’, or indeed, from anywhere. richness of our ‘ordinary’ days. A glimpse of
obscured at first by its foothills, he rises as he our objective insignificance enhances our
recedes.” Yet it is dispiriting how many The View From Now Not Here awareness of the spaces, times, places, lights,
contemporary intellectual trends – material- Even if we admit the irreducible reality of and shades, the joys and sorrows, the n-
ist theories of the mind and evolutionary our subjective experiences of ourselves and dimensional complexity, of the life and
epistemology to name only the most fatuous of what is beyond ourselves, the tension world we are living. And the very knowledge
– have continued to flourish despite Nagel’s between those experiences and the objective that reveals itself as minute and short-lived
demonstration of their inadequacy. view remains. It becomes a source of is itself deeply mysterious, being sustained
At the heart of The View from Nowhere is anguish when we look at our lives from the by unfathomable networks of concepts.
one of the key issues in philosophy, and, Archimedean point of our own death. It is How did we wake out of ourselves suffi-
indeed, in our lives. It is that of reconciling this to which Nagel devotes the final section ciently to see what (objectively) we are?
our necessarily local, even parochial, subjec- of his masterpiece. He writes:
tive viewpoints with the objective standpoint The Deaths of Philosophers
whose most developed expression is science. “The ultimate subject-object gap is death. The Looking back from death towards life can,
How do we square – or even connect – the objective standpoint simply cannot accommo- alas, do little to ease the pain of bereavement.
view from within, according to which we are date at its full subjective value the fact that every- The richness of a remembered shared life only
of overwhelming importance, with the view one, oneself included, inevitably dies” (p.230). exacerbates our sense of actual or impending
from without, which sees us as insignificant loss. As for the miserable process of dying,
in a vast universe? Nagel pursues his Nothing could matter to us more than philosophy seems to have little to offer.
response to this existential challenge, that our death, which brings all possibilities to an Of course, some philosophers have had
“reality is not just objective reality” (p.87), end; and yet nothing, so far as the universe exemplary deaths. Socrates’ courage as the
with consummate skill, imagination, and is concerned, could be less important. As hemlock worked its way through his body
much self-questioning. Nagel puts it, “the vanishing of this individ- has left a 2,500 year contrail of inspiration.
That great physicist and subtle philoso- ual [for example, your columnist] from this His final words “Crito, I owe a cock to
pher Erwin Schrödinger anticipated some of world is no more remarkable or important Asclepius; will you remember to pay the
Nagel’s preoccupations. In What is Life? than his highly accidental appearance in it” debt?” expressed his wish that Asclepius, the
(1944), Schrödinger pointed out that a (p.229). Indeed, according to Anaximander, god of medicine, should be thanked for
“moderately satisfying picture of the world in the first preserved written fragment of curing him of the disease of life.
has only been reached at the high price of Western philosophy, “Where things have David Hume’s serene passing, beautifully
taking ourselves out of the picture, stepping their origin, they must also pass away recorded in a long letter from his friend
back into the role of the non-concerned according to necessity; for they must pay the Adam Smith, is even more impressive, given
observer”, adding that “While the stuff from penalty and be judged for their injustice, that his last days were troubled by “an habit-
which our world picture is built is yielded according to the ordinance of time.” It is our ual diarrhoea of a year’s standing.” While his
exclusively from the sense organs as organs lingering not our transience that is a scan- life drained away in this most unbecoming
of the mind… yet the conscious mind itself dal. This scandal is expressed in the modern fashion, and the very special ‘I am’ of David
remains a stranger within that construct, it acknowledgement that life, particularly the Hume was squeezed to extinction by the
has no living space in it” (p.119, in the 1967 complex life of human beings, exists in defi- dysfunctioning ‘it is’ of his body, he received
edition). This gives rise to a paradox that ance of the second law of thermodynamics. his friends, discussed philosophy, worried
although “all scientific knowledge is based Philosophers have often been preoccu- over the welfare of his family, and impressed
on sense perception… the scientific views of pied with death. Acknowledging our fini- all who met him with his dignity and courage.
natural processes formed in this way lack all tude is the mark of Heidegger’s authentic Even so, cultivating awareness of mortal-
sensual qualities and therefore cannot consciousness, as being-towards-death. To ity and the habit of ‘living each day as if it
account for the latter. In the picture, or look at ourselves from the ultimate outside were thy last’, as the hymn exhorts us, tries to

54 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


overlook the actual process of dying – that plays or dinosaurs were walking the earth.
time when, more than any other, “our flesh/ Unfortunately, this mirror image anal-
Surrounds us with its own decisions,” as ogy does not hold up. In my pre-natal exis-
Philip Larkin put it in his wonderful poem tence, I am not in a state of privation,
‘Ignorance’. To retain the metaphysical because there is not yet anything or anyone
purity of the idea of death, we naturally prefer
to think of the process of our extinction as a
to house my lack of being. Before I am born,
I am only a general possibility, not an indi-
T allis
simple, if total, cancellation; a painless, even vidual to whom any subtraction – never
in
featureless, passage from RT to not-RT.
Some secular philosophers claim to find
reassurance rather than a validation of our
sense of tragedy in the thought that there
mind the comprehensive subtraction of
death – can be applied. My pre-natal, unlike
like my post mortem, non-existence, is not
the result of loss.
Wonderland
will be no afterlife. Images of eternity may Besides, if death does not matter, then whelming grief after the death of his
more often bring terror than consolation. nor do our lives. And among those things mother, to pay for her funeral. Rasselas is
Why fear being dead, the Stoic philosopher that do not matter must be included our impressed by a philosopher preaching Stoic
Lucretius famously argued, since there is relationships with each other, most impor- values. Imlac his mentor warns him that
no-one to experience the state?: tantly, love and friendship. Lucretius, it “they discourse like angels but they live like
seems, forgets that death breaks off all our men.” Rasselas soon discovers how true this
“Since death forestalls [grief and pain] and connections with those who mean most to is when he finds the Stoic philosopher weep-
prevents any existence into which such mis- us, and also that the world does not come to ing in a darkened room, poleaxed by the
fortunes might otherwise crowd, we may be an end as our participation in it does. While death of his daughter.
sure that we have nothing to fear in death, each of us may adopt a non-tragic attitude A world in which none of us cared about
and that he who is no more cannot be to our own death, and to the general fact of death would be one in which none of us
wretched, and that there is not a scrap of mortality, tragedy is still alive in those we cared about each other. That would seem to
difference to him if had never at any time have left behind. While I will not miss be a victory for death, not a victory over
been born, when once immortal death has myself after I have died, there will (I hope) death. And to fix our gaze on what a small
stolen away mortal life.” be others who will miss me. figure we cut in the world as a way of blunt-
(On the Nature of Things, translated by Cyril ing our tragic sense is a kind of betrayal of
Bailey, 1910) After Death those to whom we matter. The sense of our
If philosophers have sometimes guided us in own objective insignificance, and that, in the
Our non-existence after death, Lucretius the art of living, and have occasionally long run, nothing matters very much, even
further asserts in an argument discussed by provided us with exemplars to inspire us in if it conquered horror of death, can bring
Nagel, is a mirror image of our non-existence the art of dying, they have little to offer us only a Pyrrhic victory.
before we were born, and the latter is hardly on the art of outliving – on how to cope with Lucretius offers another way of minimis-
something we regret. I am not concerned, the loss of others. Dr Johnson reflects on ing death even for one whose life has been
even less upset, by the fact that I was not this in Rasselas (1759), the allegorical novel favoured by fortune:
around when Shakespeare was writing his he wrote at high speed in a state of over-
“Why groan and weep at death? For if the life
that is past and gone has been pleasant to you,
HEIDEGGERIAN FISH © STEVE DELMONTE 2017 PLEASE VISIT WWW.STEVEDELMONTESTUDIO.COM

and all its blessings have not drained away


and not been enjoyed… why don’t you retire
like a guest sated with the banquet of life?”

In short, why not accept that all good


things must come to an end? Precisely
because one is not “sated with the banquet of
life”. Life is not a meal, and we who live are
not mere vessels to be filled. Yes, there are
some who are tired of life, and everyone may
feel this sometimes. But which of us, facing
the real and present prospect of extinction,
will not suddenly become aware of its
preciousness?
Living the truth about ourselves is not
easy. Or as Nagel put it with characteristic
lucidity and concision, “The objective
standpoint cannot be domesticated.”
© PROF. RAYMOND TALLIS 2017
Raymond Tallis’ latest book, Of Time and
Lamentation: Reflections on Transience is
out now.

“I’m trying to live each day as if it’s my last” December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 55
Philosophy Then

IMAGE BY CAROL BELANGER GRAFTON


When Your Favorite
Philosopher is a Bigot
Peter Adamson considers possible ways forward.

W
e seem to be living in a time inducing bits weren’t there at all. everything men can do, but not so well, he
when people are willing to But is their bigotry so easy to contain? was being unusually ‘feminist’ for his time
overlook bigotry. Donald Let’s have a closer look at that idea of natu- – while simultaneously being sexist by
Trump looks at a crowd of ral slavery. Aristotle actually doesn’t invoke modern standards.
white supremacists and sees the ‘very fine the notion of ‘race’ at all. Instead he justifies This seems a reasonable solution, but it
people’ among them. Trump’s own sexist his idea that there are people who are natu- will not be enough for those philosophers
remarks provoke nothing worse than exas- rally slaves in part with reference to the who do not see themselves as ‘mere’ histo-
perated sighs among his supporters. Across impact of environment on people’s bodies. rians, but seek truth in historical works.
Europe, the frank racism of far-right parties If you live in an imbalanced climate, this will Most notorious in this regard is the case of
doesn’t stop people from voting for them as have an effect on your intelligence and Heidegger. There is an ongoing debate as
an expression of unhappiness with the gov- other traits, which is why the Greeks, who to whether his Nazism effectively poisons
ernment. No doubt genuine racism and live in an ideally balanced zone, are his thought as a whole, making it off limits
sexism play a role here, but it also seems that uniquely capable of self-mastery. Climate is as a source of philosophical inspiration.
people who would be horrified to be meanwhile influenced by the movement of Analogous threats also need to be taken
accused of prejudice themselves are willing the heavenly bodies. This conjunction of seriously by exegetes of other thinkers, and
to ignore or forgive prejudice in others. The ideas appears in later authors, as when the have been, to some extent: good work has
intelligentsia tends to be outraged by this, Muslim thinker al-Kindi draws on the been done on Kant and race, for example.
but I wonder, are we really so much better? ancient astronomer Ptolemy to explain that Some contributions in this direction
Or rather, I wonder, am I myself so much people who live in a very hot climate – he have used the ideas of historical thinkers
better? As a historian of philosophy, I explicitly mentions people with black skin to challenge those thinkers’ prejudices.
devote much of my life to the careful and and kinky hair – are characteristically dom- Kant is an obvious example. The ethical
sympathetic exegesis of thinkers who were, inated by wrath and desire, whereas people demand of his ‘categorical imperative’ to
almost to a man (and they were mostly from further north are ‘strong thinkers’ and treat other humans as having an irre-
men), outrageous bigots by today’s stan- ethically moderate. Thus were the full ducible dignity, has been an important
dards. Nearly everything Aristotle says resources of Aristotelian cosmology pressed source for ideas about equality and human
about women consists of unfavorable com- into the service of something resembling rights; and Kant himself was critical of
parisons to men. His ‘natural slave’ theory modern racism. Can that really be irrele- European imperialism. Likewise, one
has been a historical bulwark of racism; and vant to our evaluation of that cosmology could note the poor fit between Aristotle’s
it was echoed two millenia later by and the motives underlying its invention? commitment to the rationality of humans
Immanuel Kant, who was adamantly The historian may protest that to be as a species, his assumption that nature
opposed to interracial marriage, and who interested in Aristotle, al-Kindi, or Kant, is broadly achieves its purposive aims, and
claimed that “negroes cannot govern them- unlike voting for a politician: it need involve his elitist, racist and sexist claims that the
selves, and can serve only as slaves.” no approval of the author’s worldview. I’ve vast majority of humans are incapable of
The usual way philosophers have of deal- met many experts in Aristotelian cosmol- the highest level of reasoning. The pur-
ing with this is akin to many Trump sup- ogy, and not one of them has thought that pose of this ‘immanent critique’ by
porters’ attitude towards his misogyny: they the Sun orbits the Earth, as Aristotle did. So modern philosophers of their historical
don’t really approve of it, but also don’t we might treat the bigotry of the past the counterparts is not to catch out famous
think it matters so much. Similarily, the way we treat the scientific mistakes of the philosophers in self-contradiction.
argument goes, Aristotle’s views on women past. That is, rather than detaching hateful Rather, it is to acknowledge the ugly, even
or Kant’s ideas on race can be detached from remarks from the rest of the theory, we evil, aspects of historical writings while
the rest of their teachings, treated as a few detach ourselves, offering an objective anal- finding in those very writings the
unfortunate sentences in the midst of an ysis of these thinkers’ ideas without ever resources to challenge the bigotry of the
otherwise valuable body of work. As histori- adopting those ideas as our own. This will past, and, more urgently, the present.
ans, we usually take great pains to read var- often involve situating the thinkers in their © PROF. PETER ADAMSON 2017
ious passages in light of one another; but historical context. We might for example Peter Adamson is the author of A History of
here we do the reverse, engaging in a kind of note – as a historical observation, not as a Philosophy Without Any Gaps, Vols 1, 2
interpretive quarantine by reading the rest matter of praise or blame – that when Plato & 3, available from OUP. They’re based on
of the book as if the (mercifully brief) wince- argued in the Republic that women can do his popular History of Philosophy podcast.

56 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


The Truth
Kaya York tries to comprehend Everything.
“In time, those Unconscionable Maps no longer satisfied, and the Interpret ‘How to Interpret “The Truth”’.)
Cartographers Guilds struck a Map of the Empire whose size was The Truth was found, drawn and quartered, subjected to the
that of the Empire, and which coincided point for point with it.” proper book-keeping, and available in the ‘T’ section of all major
Jorge Luis Borges, ‘On Rigor in Science’ bookstores (the ‘ค’ section in Thailand, of course, and so on:
translation into other languages was less difficult than expected).
he night that Boonsri Amudee discovered The Truth The critical responses took years to emerge, and are

T she felt rather empty. After fervently writing down


her basic insight until the early hours, she brewed a
cup of sweet tea and watched the sun rise with no
thoughts in her head. “I finished my tea,” she said in a later
interview, “walked home, made normal love with my spouse,
exemplified by William Jacobson’s brief review: “Yes, I think
that about sums it up.”
Once people could be persuaded to read the books, it was
clear that the game was up. Philosophy departments shut down.
The sciences were revised. Historians kept records that sounded
and dreamed about a featureless sphere.” increasingly like dream-journals. Postmodernists continued as
Her findings were published five years later in the ten-thou- before, unfettered by The Truth – not necessarily to their
sand-plus page tome The Truth. The first draft had been incom- discredit. Theocrats banned the book. Televangelists protested
prehensible, as alien to any reader as the landscape of the Moon. the book’s existence despite (or because of) not having read it.
Amudee responded to this problem by releasing another book, Trappists remained silent. Buddhists laughed. A few people
How to Interpret ‘The Truth’, alongside an additional sequel, How created a church dedicated to the book. After telling them that
to Interpret ‘How to Interpret “The Truth”’ just for good measure. such a church was unnecessary, Amudee herself was asked by
She left it at that, feeling that two levels of recursion were quite the congregation to kindly sod off. When she appeared on talk
enough. (Although later, gradually, debates grew, even outside shows, people asked her questions like, “Yes, but when writing
the usual literary circles, about how exactly to interpret How to this incredible book, did you get a sense of beauty?” She would

December 2017/January 2018  Philosophy Now 57


frown back and say things like, “I got a sense of neutrality.” The Truth in all its completeness and totality as a matter of
Most politicians paid lip service to The Truth and showed “happening to be the right blip in the structured radio static of
how their various positions were vindicated by it. A coalition statistical aberration, the right words coming together, the right
of right-wing parties avoided the whole mess by publishing their neurons happening to fire at the right time, to be a crest on
own fifty-page book, titled The Alternative Truth. Fortuna’s rigorous waves.” No one quite knew what she meant,
After the first assassination attempt on Amudee, she moved but we nodded and scribbled it down.
to an undisclosed rural location, unheard from again except for
an occasional poem. ive hundred years later, when the Earth was much wetter,
The most understandable chapters of The Truth were
compiled into various abridgements. Those who read these
F aliens visited.
The visit was pleasant, if awkward. The aliens were presented
books did seem to change over time in subtle, almost non- with The Truth as a gift. They presented us with the same gift
documentable ways. Some developed a habit of looking at the – their own civilization’s version of The Truth. A superintelligent
ground as they walked so as to avoid stepping on insects. supercomputer was taken out of a basement (where it had been
Others found themselves unsatisfied with The Truth. People kept so as to cause no further trouble) to translate the alien
complained online. One online poster wrote that reading The version of The Truth into human. It could not. A brief fight
Truth seemed not to provide “any sort of deep, existential (sic) ensued, followed by tense silence. Then, before it was shut off
satisfaction.” “If this is the best Truth can give me,” another by a much less intelligent computer, the superintelligent
commentator wrote, “then screw it.” computer announced that it had found a way to translate the
High school students were forced to read An Introduction To works into a common meta-language, but that this meta-
The Truth, and most found it tedious. The suicide rate didn’t language required the invention of 84.217 intermediary
go up; but it didn’t go down, either. In truth, most people just languages. The processing power necessary to produce these
didn’t care to read it. other languages would require employing the total energy
Apocryphal stories arose that Amudee had withheld certain capacities of human civilization plus those of the alien
devastating or beatific material from The Truth. In these myths, civilization. The matter hardly seemed worth it. Both
commonly, the True, sexier version of The Truth would draw civilizations decided that their own Truth was satisfying enough.
the reader inevitably to suicide, or enlightenment, or catatonia.
These confident speculations about what Amundee had left out wo thousand years after this, a demon appeared on Earth.
of her book evolved into entire books of their own, eventually
together selling more copies than The Truth itself. Indeed, far,
T It was Japanese for some not very clear reason. The demon
offered to grant a wish to Earthlings.
far fewer read the original, unabridged book, as it was very Having already solved the problems of scarcity and mortality,
abstract. The book’s final thousand pages, which were dedicated the humans, ravens, and octopuses talked, and soon decided to
to issues arising from the book’s capacity to represent and ask the demon for a translation of the human, alien, and now
account for itself, were, like much self-referential writing, barely raven and octopus, versions of The Truth into a universal
readable. However, some chapters, particularly ‘Modera As language, understandable to all. The demon made a face that
Quipt In NAWIA’, ‘Ormahian Reactions In An Ideal Context’, was the demon equivalent of a smile, and disappeared. There
and ‘The Real Reason That People Smile So Much When appeared in the sky a large book. It grew. It grew until the planets
They’re Around Each Other’, were surprisingly humane, and were pressed between its pages like dried leaves. Earth would
prone to set the careful reader into fits of cathartic laughter: a have been the size of a period on the end of one of its sentences,
laughter of simultaneous discovery and recognition. except that the sentences remained normal font sized. To read
The Truth had some practical effects. Technology improved one page would have taken centuries.
– causing new problems, which technology then solved – causing The book grew some more. Stars burned small holes in its
new problems. Wars and bombings continued, with greater pages in final attacks of self-defense as it subsumed them. The
efficiency. Fashions changed. Art continued. James Bond book stretched to the size of the observable universe, possibly
movies were still produced, although people familiar enough larger, before collapsing under its own weight.
with The Truth found themselves inexplicably embarrassed At first it turned into a giant star, the heat tearing its atoms
while watching them. Social inequality continued. apart. Its collapse continued until the book that was the universe
Amundee was speculated to be anything from a Celestial became a single point, infinitesimally small and infinitely dense.
Being to the Antichrist – but only among those who had not Some say that for 10-43 seconds there was silence. Some say time
read her books. did not exist at all. In either case, there was the silence, the point,
Boonsri Amudee had been somewhat eccentric, but not the mysterious source of order in existence, and the ground of
particularly remarkable. She wasn’t a former spelling bee being itself. And then, another Big Bang! The universe again:
champion, a Macarthur Fellow, the recipient of any grant or another Earth, another sentient human life, another Boonsri
prize. The daughter of Thai rubber tree farmers, she worked Amudee, another Truth, another contact, another demon. And
quietly as a statistical researcher at Kasetsart University, on and on it went, ad infinitum.
publishing the odd Philosophy of Mathematics paper in her © KAYA YORK 2017
free time. None of this seems to account for the book she is Kaya York is a graduate student in Philosophy and has taught English
best known for. Mathematics only amounts to a fragment of and Western Culture in China. You can follow Kaya’s fiction at
The Truth. Amudee herself considered her sudden insight about kayayork.wordpress.com

58 Philosophy Now  December 2017/January 2018


Professor Daniel Dennett
Visiting Professor of Philosophy at
New College of the Humanities

MA Philosophy
NCH London

Distinguished postgraduate study led by


extraordinary faculty.

Why study Philosophy anywhere else?

nchlondon.ac.uk

You might also like