You are on page 1of 10

INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PSYCHOLOGY, 2000, 35 (2), 126± 135

Justice and Social Con¯ ict

Gerold Mikula Michael Wenzel


University of Graz, Austria University of Jena, Germany

This article analyzes possible effects of ideas of justice, perceptions of injustice, and the use of justice arguments on the
emergence, course, and resolution of social con¯ icts. Four functions of justice are identi® ed: (1) ideas of justice and
perceptions of injustice can elicit or evoke social con¯ icts; (2) justice arguments and rhetorics can be used to support one’s
own position in a dispute; (3) the basic value and the principles and rules of justice can restrict social con¯ icts and help to
generate ways of con¯ ict resolution; (4) the labelling of con¯ ict resolutions as just can increase the acceptance of the
resolution. The analysis is illustrated by making reference to a recent case of international con¯ ict and diplomatic
controversy.
Cet article analyse les effets possibles des ideÂes de justice, les prceptions d’injustice et l’utilisation d’arguments juridiques
sur l’e mergence, le deÂveloppement et la reÂsolution de con¯ its sociaux. Quatre fonctions de la justice sont identi® eÂes: (1) les
ideÂes de justice et les perceptions d’injustice peuvent deÂclencher ou raviver des con¯ its sociaux; (2) les arguments juridiques
et la rheÂtorique peuvent eÃtre utiliseÂs pour appuyer sa propre position dans une dispute; (3) la valeur fondamentale de justice
ainsi que ses principes et reÁgles peuvent limiter les con¯ its sociaux et servir aÁ geÂneÂrer des solutions au con¯ it; (4) eÂtiqueter la
solution d’un con¯ it comme juste peut augmenter l’acceptation de cette solution. Cette analyse est illustreÂe par un cas
reÂcent de con¯ it international et de controverse diplomatique.

Social con¯ icts are ubiquitou s in human life. This holds In December 1997, at the summit in Luxembourg, the
true for the most intimate personal relationship s as much European Union (EU) reached a landmark decision on
as for large-scale relations between national states and its extension. The candidate countries for joining the EU
between supra-national associations. Certainly, con¯ icts in the near future were decided on, namely the Czech
in these various contexts do have their peculiarities and Republic, Cyprus, Estonia, Hungary, Poland, and
unique aspects. However, there are also important in- Slovenia, with whom negotiations would shortly be
variances and, on some level of abstraction, general initiated. Turkey was not considered as a candidate,
processes that all con¯ icts share. In this article, we will although it has been associated with the EU since 1964,
analyze social con¯ icts from the point of view of social has repeatedly applied for membership, and has a long
justice research. More speci® cally, we will analyz e the tradition of economic relations with the EU; most
possible effects of ideas of justice, perceptions of injustice, recently it agreed on a tariff union with the EU in
and the use of justice arguments on the emergence, course, 1996. The vast majority of the Turkish people wanted
and resolution of social con¯ icts. We regard distributive and hoped for a membership in the EU. These hopes
and procedural justice as equally relevant for this analysis were additionally fuelled when Germany’s previous
and will not distinguish between these two forms of justice Chancellor, Kohl, in September 1997 said that Turkey
in the following discussion because most of the arguments would, in the long run, belong to the EU. The EU
hold for both of them. The analysis is meant to hold decision thus led to huge disappointment for the Turkish
equally well for interpersonal con¯ icts and intergroup public and to harsh criticisms from high-ranking Turkish
con¯ icts of the largest scale. Yet, throughou t this paper politicians. In particular Germany, considered the most
we will refer to a recent case of internationa l con¯ ict and important partner in the EU, and Chancellor Kohl were
diplomatic controversy, and we will try to illustrate crucial held responsible for the decision. They were strongly
points of our discussion by referring to some actual details criticized and accused of pursuing an expansionis t policy
and some hypothetica l possibilitie s of that con¯ ict. not unlike Nazi Germany’s ``Lebensraum-Strategie’’

Requests for reprints should be addressed to Gerold Mikula, Department of Psychology, University of Graz, A-8010 Graz, Austria (Tel:
+43 316 380 5113; Fax: +43 316 3809 807; E-mail: Gerold.Mikula@kfunigraz.ac.at).
We would like to thank Julie Peard for her help with the manuscript preparation.

q 2000 International Union of Psychological Science


JUSTICE AND SOCIAL CONFLICT 127

(Turkey accuses Kohl on EU policy, 1998).1 Hence, the the resolution of con¯ icts. This proposition is already
EU decision led to considerable diplomatic con¯ ict and, re¯ ected in the different functions we have just intro-
at least temporarily, a decline in the quality of relations duced, and it will be repeatedly highlighted when we
between Germany and Turkey. Turkey felt the decision to discuss these functions in detail in the remainder of this
be unjust. Meanwhile, the whole con¯ ict has cooled article.
down, without actually having been solved. The con¯ ict Before going into details, it seems important to
was loaded with justice arguments, and thus may be a emphasize that we are dealing here with a genuinely
proper illustration for our discussion of the relation psychological analysis of justice, conceptualizing justice
between justice and con¯ ict. as a subjective perception. We will not propose any
Despite the intuitive relevance of justice and con¯ ict notions of justice to be more or less right, nor even to
for each other, there has been surprisingly little research be more or less conducive to con¯ icts or their resolution.
and theorizing on the relationship of the two concepts Rather, we are interested in the way that perceptions, and
(Hegtvedt & Cook, 1987). Some con¯ ict researchers have arguments, of justice shape the occurrence and course of
discussed justice as a means to avoid, limit, or negotiate con¯ icts. Our emphasis of the subjectivity of justice
con¯ icts (Fisher, Ury, & Patton, 1991; Pruitt & Carnevale, judgements may appear trivial. However, justice is often
1993). Pruitt and Carnevale, for instance, point out that referred to as if it were an objectively de® nable quality.
norms of distributive justice can prevent con¯ icts by Politician s and social activists try to convince people
making opponents’ claims compatible (e.g. the owner- again and again that there is something like objective
ship rule). Rules of procedural justice can regulate the justice, and they, of course, know what it is. Justice,
con¯ ict behaviour, for instance, by referring to principles however, can be unambiguously and objectively de® ned
of fair ® ght or competition. Finally, distributive and only at an abstract level. Let us consider two examples of
procedural rules can also provide options for solving such abstract de® nitions. The philosopher Perelman
given con¯ icts. However, Pruitt and Carnevale stress (1963, p. 16) de® ned formal, or abstract, justice as ``a
that norms of justice may also fuel con¯ icts, and lead principle of action in accordance with which beings of
to escalations, when they prescribe harsh reactions or one and the same essential category must be treated in
when the parties disagree about which norms are applic- the same way.’ ’ According to a de® nition that is common
able to their situation. In addition , because norms are among social psychologists, justice means that people get
perceived as morally right, they may lead to rigid percep- what they are entitled to through who they are or what they
tions of one’s own entitlements, and to hostile reactions have done (cf. Cohen, 1986a; Lerner, 1991). It is immedi-
when entitlements are perceived to be violated. ately apparent that these abstract de® nitions allow a
In this article, we will argue that issues of justice can diversity of different translations into concrete terms.
in¯ uence social con¯ icts in different ways and in different Thus, judgements of justice and injustice are always
phases of the course of con¯ icts. These different ways subjective judgements. The judgements may be socially
may be understood as different functions of justice for shared, that is, there may be a consensus among the
the emergence, development, and resolution of social members of given social systems. But such a consensus
con¯ icts. We will discuss four different functions of does not change the basic subjective nature of ideas and
justice for social con¯ icts. First, the trigger function judgements of justice and injustice.
means that ideas of justice and perceptions of injustice
can elicit or evoke social con¯ icts. Second, the argument
function describes how justice arguments and rhetorics
can be used to support one’s own position in a dispute. PERCEPTIONS OF INJUSTICE AND THE
Third, according to the resolution function, the basic OCCURRENCE OF SOCIAL CONFLICTS
value as well as the principles and rules of justice can
restrict social con¯ icts and help to generate ways and According to one of the standard de® nitions of con¯ ict,
means of con¯ ict resolution. Fourth, the acceptance func- ``con¯ ict means perceived divergence of interest, or a
tion means that the labelling of con¯ ict resolutions as just belief that the parties’ current aspirations cannot be
can help to increase the acceptance of the resolution. In achieved simultaneously’ ’ (Rubin, Pruitt, & Kim, 1994,
agreement with Pruitt and Carnevale (1993), we propose p. 5). The perception of injustice is thus no necessary
that considerations of, and references to, justice are both condition, because social con¯ icts can emerge without
helpful and potentially detrimental to the limitation and any perceptions of injustice when the divergence of inter-
ests results from incompatible desires or wishes without
any legitimate entitlement. However, social con¯ icts
1
It was felt to be an additional affront against Turkey that the frequently follow from perceptions of injustice, and per-
EU considered Cyprus as a potential member. Cyprus is divided tinent divergent views of the existence of an injustice.
into the Republic of Cyprus inhabited by Greeks, and a northern According to the de® nition of justice provided earlier,
part that is occupied by Turkey. The fact that the EU offered
the perception of injustice presupposes the existence of
negotiations to the government of the Republic of Cyprus can be
considered as an affront against Turkey because this act acknow- certain ideas of entitlement or deserving, and the obser-
ledged internationally the government of the Republic of Cyprus as vation that someone’s entitlements have been violated.
the only legitimate government of Cyprus. We will brie¯ y discuss a theoretical conceptualization of

127
128 MIKULA AND WENZEL

perceptions of injustice that may be considered helpful subject of controversy between observers who differ in
for the further analysis. their perspectives and social identities (Wenzel, 1998).

Entitlement Beliefs Perceptions of Injustice

People have ideas about what they and others deserve, or The observation that somebody’s entitlement has been
are entitled to, according to who they are or what they violated is clearly the basic element of perceptions of
have done. These ideas derive from various sources; from injustice (Lerner, 1991; Major, 1994). However, the
principles of justice, from laws or contracts, from perception of violations of entitlement is not the only
customs, and from abstract social values (Furby, 1986; element. Not every violation of entitlements is necessar-
Wenzel et al., 1996). Some of these sources of entitlement ily perceived as unjust. Two further important elements
beliefs (e.g. principles of distributive justice) directly are the identi® cation of an agent who is responsible
imply comparison processes; for instance, people deserve for the violation, and perceived lack of justi® cation
to be treated the same as others who are like them in a for the violation of entitlements (Crosby, Muehrer, &
certain respect. Other notions seem to contain rather Loewenstein, 1986; Folger, 1986, 1987; Mikula, 1993;
absolute standards. For instance, ``Everybody has the Montada, 1991). If no agent is identi® ed who is respon-
right to life, liberty and security of person’ ’ (Article 3, sible for a given violation of somebody’s entitlements
Universal Declaration of Human Rights), independent and/or the violation is suf® ciently justi® ed, the state of
of whether or not other people are treated in that way. affairs will not be regarded as unjust. Perceptions of
At a more abstract level, entitlement beliefs involve injustice are thus based on the perception of entitlements
categorizations of people according to who they are or being violated (as a results of an action or omission of
what they have done, that is, categorization s that are some agent), the attribution of responsibilit y to an agent,
based upon ascribed and achieved characteristics (Folger, and the perceived lack of justi® cation for the violation of
1994; Furby, 1986; Lerner, 1991; Major, 1994; Mikula, entitlement (Mikula, 1993)2.
1993; Steil, 1994). These categorization s de® ne the kinds
of people to whom the respective entitlements apply.
Examples of such categories are all human beings, The Trigger Function: Divergent
citizens (vs. foreigners), unemployed people, high- Perceptions of Injustice Can Elicit
performance workers (vs. low-performance workers) Social Con¯ icts
etc. Thus, it is possible to conceptualiz e entitlement
judgements in terms of categorization processes (Wenzel, Social con¯ icts and disputes frequently result from the
1997, 1998, in press). Indeed, categorizations at different perception that a distribution, procedure, or treatment is
levels of abstraction may be involved. A ® rst categoriza- unjust. The critical factor that leads from the perception
tion refers to the recipient unit, which indicates the level of injustice to a dispute and open con¯ ict is the lack of
of aggregation of the social entities that are regarded as consensus between different parties in their assessment
potential recipients (Eckhoff, 1974). For example, var- of a given situation. The subjective nature of judgements
ious countries may be considered for membership in the of justice and injustice makes it very likely that different
EU, but not individua l persons. A second categorization people will evaluate one and the same situation differ-
refers to the range of social entities that are considered as ently. Divergent assessments and evaluations, and con-
potential recipients, as opposed to those that are per- sequent disputes, are even more likely as people do not
ceived as nonrecipients (Cohen, 1991; Walzer, 1983). simply differ in their views, but they differ in a systematic
For example, only European countries are potential way, depending on their respective identities, roles, and
members of the EU, but not non-European countries. perspectives.
This so-called primary categorization de® nes the bound- Three different perspectives can be distinguishe d with
aries of the justice problem. (This type of categorization respect to the perception of injustice: the perspective of
has some resemblance to the concepts of moral commu- the victim, that is, the individua l who suffers from the
nity and moral exclusion, which refer to the perception injustice; the perspective of the causal agent, actor, or
of who belongs to and who is excluded from the social
category within which moral values and rules of justice
and fairness apply; cf. Opotow, 1990.) A third categor- 2
From this perspective, judgements of injustice can be con-
ization refers to the differentiation and subcategorization ceived of as a particular instance of blaming, that is, blaming an
of potential recipients on relevant dimensions that are agent for violating the entitlement of a person or a group (Mikula,
regarded as prototypical, or de® ning, features of the 1993). The attribution of blame implies the attribution of responsi-
primary category. For example, candidates for member- bility for a negative incident and lack of suf® cient justi® cation. The
attribution of responsiblit y implies that the violation of entitlement is
ship in the EU may be differentiated with regard to their
perceived to be caused by an action or omission by an agent who
respecting of human rights, market-economy orientation, was able to foresee the consequences of his conduct, had control
and other dimensions which may be perceived to de® ne over his or her behaviour (i.e. he or she could have acted otherwise),
``Europeanness.’ ’ All these categorizations should be the and behaved intentionally.
JUSTICE AND SOCIAL CONFLICT 129

perpetrator, that is, the individua l who caused the situa- identi® cation as Germans. It was found that Germany
tion in question; and the perspective of an observer who was perceived to be more, and Turkey less, relatively
perceives the critical situation without being personally prototypical of Europe, the stronger the respondents
affected. (A fourth possible perspective is that of the identi® ed with Germany. In turn, the EU decision was
possible pro® teer, which may coincide with the perspec- regarded as more just, and Turkey’s entitlement to
tive of the causal agent or be independent of it.) membership as lower, the more Germany, rather than
There is much empirical evidence showing that people Turkey, was regarded as prototypical of Europe. Hence,
holding different roles or perspectives in relation to social the entitlement judgement depended on the understand-
transgressions, such as aggression and injustice, differ in ing or de® nition of the primary category, Europe, and on
their views and evaluations of that incident. Actors typic- the perceived prototypicalit y of potential recipients for
ally regard their own conduct as appropriate and justi® ed, the primary category thus de® ned. By extrapolation, it
and refer to external mitigating circumstances of their can be assumed that Turks who identify strongly with
own negative behaviour. Victims of social transgressions Turkey would de® ne Europe (being the primary
regard the incidents as more serious and unjust than category) differently and consider different dimensions
actors do themselves, and attribute more responsibility as important; they would regard Turkey as more
and blame to the actors (Baumeister, Stillwell, & relatively prototypica l for Europe and thus as more
Wotman, 1990; Stillwell & Baumeister, 1997; Mikula, deserving. Hence, con¯ icts may easily evolve from these
1994; Mikula, Athenstaedt, Heschgl, & Heimgartner, different perceptions that imply divergent views on
1998; Mummendey, Linneweber, & LoÈschper, 1984; entitlements.
Mummendey & Otten, 1989; Otten, Mummendey, & Referring to our discussion of perceptions of injustice,
Wenzel, 1995). Much of this research has been done entitlements are not the only aspect on which parties may
with interpersonal relationships, but it is likely that have divergent views. Turkish politicians, for instance,
similar evidence can be obtained in intergroup contexts accused the German government of being mainly respon-
(cf. Otten et al., 1995). Con¯ icting groups generally sible for the EU decision. Germany might have repu-
regard their own actions as more appropriate and legit- diated blame by pointing out that it was an EU
imate than the actions of the respective other group decision in which its own vote was only 1 next to 14
(Blumenthal, Kahn, Andrew, & Head, 1972; Reicher, others; Germany would not be any more responsible
1996). than the other 14 members. Again, the divergence could
Mikula et al. (1998), who studied perspective differ- have resulted from different identities and corresponding
ences in the evaluation of injustice in close personal perceptions of the situation. Germany might have felt
relationships, found that the perspective differences itself solely to be a member of the EU and did not feel
between the evaluations by victims and actors were any other obligation s than to act as a member of that
moderated by the quality of the relationship between category. Turkey, however, might have felt itself to be
the partners. The described differences were less likely Germany’s partner as it traditionally had good relations
to occur among partners with high-qualit y relation- to Germany. Accordingly, it expected Germany to make
ships. High relationship quality seems to promote every effort to convince other EU members to grant
people’s willingness to refrain from self-serving inter- Turkey membership. Interestingly, judgements of
pretations and to cope with potentially destructive responsibility may thus, in some contexts, be related
relationship problems in ways conducive to a good to other secondary judgements of entitlement and
climate between the partners. Putting it in less instru- obligation.
mental terms, high relationship quality may imply a It was previously stated that perceptions of injus-
stronger common identity of the partners and, thus, tice are not necessary preconditions for social con-
the sharing of values and perspectives, so that there ¯ icts. It should be added now that they are also not
would be less divergence in their appraisals of the suf® cient for the elicitation of social con¯ icts. No
situation. social con¯ ict will arise out of the perception of
In our discussion of the entitlement concept, we injustice as long as the perception of injustice is not
argued that the perceivers’ identities and perspectives overtly expressed in some way. There are a number of
have an impact on their social categorizations and different ways in which people can react behaviourally
corresponding perceptions of entitlement. Concerning to the perception of injustice (Mikula, 1987; Tedeschi
the Turkish-German con¯ ict introduced at the begin- & Nesler, 1993; Tyler, Boeckmann, Smith, & Huo,
ning, Wenzel (1998, Study 3) asked German participants 1997). People may do nothing, claim or demand
whether they regarded the EU decision not to grant action by the agent, punish the agent, or leave the
Turkey membership in the EU as just. Beforehand, relationship or group. An open social con¯ ict will
respondents were asked to rate Turkey, Germany, and only emerge in two of these cases, namely when per-
Europe on a series of dimensions potentially relevant to sons perceiving an injustice make a claim for restora-
that question. On the basis of these pro® les, Germany’s, tion or compensation, or when they punish the actor
relative to Turkey’s, prototypicality for Europe was cal- in some way. In these cases, perceptions of injustice
culated. Respondents also indicated the extent of their trigger a social con¯ ict.
130 MIKULA AND WENZEL

JUSTICE EVALUATIONS AND JUSTICE initial action as inappropriat e and accept their punish-
ARGUMENTS IN THE COURSE OF ment as being deserved.
SOCIAL CONFLICTS The course of events following a claim for restoration
or compensation also depends on what the former actors
On the Course of Injustice-based Social do in response to the claim. Basically, they have four
Con¯ icts different options to react (cf. McLaughlin , Cody, &
O’Hair, 1983; SchoÈnbach, 1990; Scott & Lyman, 1968).
When persons who perceive an injustice claim restoration First, they can make concessions , that is, admit to have
or compensation, or when they punish the actors, the violated some norm and accept responsibility for the
further course of the con¯ ict will depend on the reactions transgression (and perhaps apologize). Second, they
of the former actor. Figure 1 depicts possible courses of can provide justi® cations, that is, accounts that accept
social con¯ icts that result from perceptions of injustice. responsibility for the act in question but provide reasons
Let us consider punishment ® rst. Punishment may be why the action was legitimate and the correct, or at least
used by victims or observers of injustice in order to necessary, thing to do in that situation. Third, they can
restore justice by retaliation or as a means of deterring provide excuses, that is, accounts that concede the viola-
further offences (Tyler et al., 1997). When the former tion of a norm but deny responsibility for the negative
actors perceive their actions as appropriate, and it is event due to lack of foreseeability, control, or intention.
very likely that they will do so, they will perceive any Finally, they can react through various forms of refusals,
punishment as unjusti® ed and feel unjustly treated. for instance, by denying that any injustice has occurred,
Hence, the punishment leads to perceived injustice and or denying their involvement in the event and thus their
the same process starts again but, from the actors’ view- blameworthiness.
point, with reversed roles. That is, the former actors are If actors acquiesce to the claim and concede their
now the victims and have the same range of options; not transgression, and perhaps additionally apologiz e for it,
improbably, they may punish the punisher, thus retaliat- the victims or observers of injustice may very likely for-
ing in some form. Since the former victims or observers give them, and the con¯ ict will be settled. The con¯ ict
of injustice regarded their punishment as justi® ed, they may also be resolved if actors provide an account that
will regard the former actors’ retaliation as unjusti® ed excuses the actor or justi® es the event and the victims or
and retaliate themselves. Obviously, such a sequence of observers accept the accounts and absolve the actor from
reactions, elicited by the use of punishment, leads to an blame. If the actors’ accounts are not accepted by the
escalation of the con¯ ict. Punishment may terminate the victims or observers, they may either insist on their
con¯ ict only if the former actors perceive their own claim, or punish the actor, and the con¯ ict will continue.

FIG. 1. A process model of possible consequences of perceived injustice.


JUSTICE AND SOCIAL CONFLICT 131

Similarly, if the harmdoer rejects the claims of the per- Turkey’s entitlement, but Turkey would feel this entitle-
ceiver of injustice, the con¯ ict will go on. ment was violated, whereas Germany would not. With
regard to the third point (divergent views on responsi-
Differences in Justice Evaluations bility), we indicated earlier that Turkey regards Germany
as mainly responsible, whereas Germany may reject this
According to our conceptualization of perceptions of by pointing out that the decision was made by all 15 EU
injustice described earlier, disputes between con¯ icting members. As an illustration of the fourth point
parties about justice and injustice can refer to different (divergent views on justi® cations), an interesting, but
aspects, namely, the nature of the entitlements of certain seldom overtly discussed, reason for the EU decision is
persons, the violatio n of existing entitlements, the that inclusion of Turkey, and thus an extension of the EU
responsibilities of various agents, and the availabilit y of towards the borders of Syria, Iraq and Iran, would seem
suf® cient justi® cations (Mikula, 1994). First, disputes to exceed the EU’s current capabilities of integration and
may focus on the perception of entitlements. The parties thus jeopardiz e the whole European project (Buhbe,
may disagree whether or not a person, or a group, actu- 1998). Whereas Germany and the EU might want to
ally deserves a certain kind of treatment or outcome. justify their decision with the argument that the success
Second, even if the parties agree on the nature of the and survival of the EU has priority over Turkey’s
entitlements, they may disagree whether any entitlements entitlements, Turkey would certainly be less prone to
have been violated or not. Third, even if both parties accept it.
accept that certain entitlements have been violated,
they may disagree on who is responsible for the negative
event. As discussed earlier, research shows that actors The Argument Function: The Use of
who committed a social transgression frequently deny Justice Appeals in Order to Support
personal responsibility for what happened while victims One’s Position
(and unaffected observers) of the transgression attribute
personal responsibility to the actor. Finally, the parties Independent of whether or not social con¯ icts have been
can disagree on the availabilit y of suf® cient justi® cations elicited by perceptions of injustice, con¯ icting parties
for the action in question. Actors may provide reasons frequently use justice arguments in their dispute to
why the action was the correct, or at least necessary, strengthen and support their case. Justice is used as an
thing to do in that situation, while victims and observers argument to legitimize one’s own actions and claims
may reject any justi® cations for what happened. (Mikula, 1984; Reis, 1984), and portrayals of injustice
To illustrate these points, we may refer again to the are used to discredit the opponent’s position. Reference
example of Turkey being denied membership in the EU. to justice when justifying actions and decisions stresses
Turkey regards itself as a victim of injustice and perceives the actors’ impartiality and transfers the responsibility
Germany to be the main agent of that injustice. It was for the action from the actor to the impersonal authority
stated earlier that the two parties probably have different of norms of justice. Using appeals to justice when
views on whether or not Turkey is entitled to member- making a claim imbues the claim with greater legitimacy
shipÐ in particular, from the perspective of members than referring to personal wants; saying that one
who strongly identify with their respective group. In deserves, or is entitled to, something is more than saying
another respect, however, both Turkey and Germany that one wants it. Finally, labelling an action or decision
may actually agree on Turkey’s entitlement, namely that as ``unjust’ ’ simultaneously stresses the objectionabl e
Turkey, being (at least partly) a European country, has character of what happened, and strengthens requests
the right to apply for membership in the EU and is for a change or a compensation.
entitled to serious consideration of whether or not it In our example of Turkey and the EU, both parties
meets the criteria for membership. Turkey belongs to may have referred to justice, although for different pur-
the primary category Europe and should thus be treated poses, after the EU decided not to consider Turkey as a
like any other member and applicant for membership candidate. The representatives of the EU may have used
(that is, it has in this sense an entitlement to consistency, justice as an argument to legitimize the decision to deny
a principle of procedural justice; Leventhal, 1980). How- Turkey membership in the EU. The representatives of
ever, whereas Germany may acknowledge this entitle- Turkey may have referred to injustice to emphasize the
ment but consider Turkey not to meet the relevant objectionable character of the decision.
criteria (respecting human rights, respecting the In the case of con¯ icts between opponents with
sovereignty of other states, etc.), Turkey’ s (former) Prime unequal power, the question arises of whether those in
Minister Yilmaz claims that Turkey was denied equal power or the powerless would use appeals to justice more
treatment (equal to the treatment of those other Middle frequently and be more successful with these appeals.
and Eastern European countries that were granted Since normative arguments represent the only means of
candidature). According to him, Turkey was simply the powerless to support their position, they are likely to
kept out of Europe and thus, we could add, morally resort to this means more frequently. However, the more
excluded (``Bittere EnttaÈuschung’ ’ [Bitter disappoint- powerful may be more successful in using appeals to
ment], 1998). Hence, both parties would agree on justice (Cohen, 1986b; Walster & Walster, 1975).
132 MIKULA AND WENZEL

Justice arguments can help to support one’s position differences between the parties (see also Stephenson,
in disputes because justice is a generally accepted social 1984). Hence, justice and con¯ ict resolution presuppose
value. However, their effects are limited in several an inclusion in a superordinate category which, then,
respects. They are only useful as long as the opponent needs to be consensually de® ned.
does not come to believe that the appeal to justice is On a more pragmatic level of analysis, rules of justice
only made for tactical purposes. The effects are further provide a variety of possible solutions that the parties
limited to social con¯ icts between opponents who may consider and discuss in their search for a resolution
regard each other as belonging to the moral community of the con¯ ict. For instance, as Messick and co-workers
within which moral values and rules of justice apply. have shown (Allison & Messick, 1990; Messick, 1993;
Moral exclusion abolishe s the argument function of Samuelson & Allison, 1994), the equality rule serves as
justice. a prominent decision heuristic in many complex decision-
making situations and, thus, can also facilitate con¯ ict
resolution. If no agreed-upon distributive principle could
JUSTICE AND THE RESOLUTION be found, agreement might be possible on procedures
OF CONFLICTS regarded as fair by the con¯ icting parties, such as, for
instance, giving the parties a chance to present their
The Resolution Function: How Notions views. Tyler et al. (1997, p. 250) suggest that notions of
and Rules of Justice Can Promote procedural justice, which seem in general to be shared
Con¯ ict Resolution and less in¯ uenced by cultural and ethnic backgrounds,
should be crucial for ``bridging across con¯ icts in
Justice can help to resolve social con¯ ict only if there is a normative belief systems.’ ’
minimum level of readiness to cooperate between the Research and practice of con¯ ict resolution and nego-
con¯ icting parties (Deutsch, 1975). The opponents tiation informs us that talks between con¯ icting parties
must perceive each other as being members of the same can contribute, in multiple ways, to de-escalating and
moral community, each of whom is entitled to be treated resolving con¯ icts. Making reference to justice may
justly. Justice plays no role in the resolution of con¯ icts also be useful here. First, if the search for a solution is
when the opposing party is not perceived to belong to guided by concerns about justice on both sides, the
one’s moral community. In this case, appeals to justice observation that the opponents subscribe to similar
will be made only, if at all, as a tactical means to justify social values can promote mutual trust 4. Second, the
one’s own actions and claims3. explicit discussion of the individua l parties’ ideas of
When both parties are perceived to belong to a shared justice can help to de® ne the range of negotiation by
moral community or (with a slight change in meaning) to excluding solutions that are unacceptable to one or
a common primary category (Wenzel, 1997), justice has both sides, and by identifying acceptable solutions.
the potential to promote con¯ ict resolution due to its Third, and possibly most important, in explicitly discuss-
status as an accepted social value. Justice does not ing their justice notions, the parties have a chance to
provide one particular just solution but, in principle, it recognize the subjectivity and perspective dependency
sets limits to self-interests. Justice implies shared criteria of ideas of justice and entitlement. If they do so, they
for people’s actions and claims and, due to the shared- may become more ¯ exible in their own views and take the
ness of these criteria, the reference to justice commits the entitlement claims of other parties as being as equally
con¯ ict parties to work out a shared understanding of the legitimate and relevant as their own ones. Simultan-
situation and the primary category. This implicit com- eously, they may experience that their own entitlement
mitment de® nes the limits on one’s conduct. Thus, claims are recognized by their opponents. Both processes
although justice presupposes some common moral should help to reach a shared understanding of the situa-
community and identity, it is achieved only by further tion and come to an agreement about a shared view of
specifying, and agreeing on, the meaning of that justice. Alternatively, and perhaps more probably, the
common identity. In a similar vein, Eggins (1997) argues, parties, having recognized the partiality of their views
on the basis of self-categorization theory (Turner, Hogg, of justice and entitlements, would perceive them to be
Oakes, Reicher, & Wetherell, 1987), that con¯ ict resolu- equally valid from their respective perspectives and try to
tion requires a rede® nition of the common superordinat e work out a compromise. Such a compromise need not be
category, which has meaning for the de® nition of the understood as a betrayal of essential values and prin-
con¯ icting subgroups and their relationship to each ciples, but rather as a commitment to one’s own values
other, so that it reconciles (but does not conceal) the and the simultaneous acknowledgment of others having
3
Here, the con¯ ict will only be resolved when the proposed
4
resolution is to the advantage of both parties (i.e. leads to better However, if the parties realize during these discussions that
outcomes for both parties), as compared to a nonresolution. This they actually do not share the most basic social values, appeals
is because material interests and the maximization of outcomes to justice may be detrimental as they may turn a con¯ ict of
should be the only criteria for one’s con¯ ict behaviour when the interests into a dispute on world views, lead to rigidity, and deepen
parties do not share a moral community and thus justice does not the divide between the parties (Pruitt & Carnevale, 1993; see
matter. above).
JUSTICE AND SOCIAL CONFLICT 133

different values. Although such a compromise would not CONCLUSION


be fully satisfactory, because each party would have
thought of a solution more favourable to themselves, The present discussion has shown that justice has
the justice discussion would have helped to make the multiple functions for the emergence and resolution of
compromise solution acceptable. social con¯ icts. Perceptions of injustice and divergent
views about what is just and unjust can evoke social
The Acceptance Function: Labelling a con¯ icts. Disputes about individua l entitlements and
Resolution as Just Can Promote its their violation, about the responsibilitie s of various
Acceptance agents, and about the availabilit y of justi® cations, are
the subjects of discussion and negotiation between
As mentioned before, the reference to justice to justify opposing parties and shape the course of social con¯ icts.
actions and make claims can be used to stress one’s Appeals to justice that are made by the con¯ icting parties
impartiality and transfer part of the responsibility to to support their respective positions can be conducive or
the impersonal authority of the justice norm (Mikula, detrimental to the achievement of jointly agreed-upon
1980, 1984). Due to the status of justice as a social resolutions. The subscription to justice as a social value,
value, calling a decision just can imbue it with greater and the rules of distributive justice and fair procedures,
signi® cance and legitimacy and, consequently, promote can help con¯ icting parties to come to an agreement that
its acceptance. We refer to this as the acceptance is acceptable to all participants. Finally, the conviction of
function of justice. Consensually labelling a con¯ ict former con¯ icting parties that an eventually achieved
resolution that has been jointly achieved by the con- resolution is just may ensure adherence to the agreement
¯ icting parties as just can increase the level of com- over time.
mitment to the solution, advance its strict translation Thus, the notion of justice can be helpful for, but also
into action, decrease the likelihood of sabotaging the detrimental to, the limitation and resolution of social
resolution, and thus promote a de® nite termination of con¯ icts. To be helpful, it presupposes that the con¯ ict-
the con¯ ict. ing parties share the basic value of justice and regard
For the latter two functions of justice for con¯ icts, the each other as belonging to the moral community within
resolution and the acceptance function, the Turkish-German which moral values and rules of justice and fairness
con¯ ict following the denial of the EU membership to apply. In addition, the parties have to reach a shared
Turkey seems a rather weak example. One has the understanding of the situation and a shared view of their
impression that no constructive talks to settle the con¯ ict entitlements. Alternatively, they at least have to recognize
actually occurred. Political authorities were instead the existence of differing but equally legitimate and valid
rather preoccupied with expressing indignation and views of justice. Common views are more likely to emerge
counter-indignatio n and issuing defamations. Only one among con¯ icting parties who share a common identity.
unilateral action of the EU may be interpreted as an Many internationa l con¯ icts, however, seem to exist
(unsuccessful) attempt to limit the con¯ ict that was between groups or parties who do not share a common
anticipated to follow the decision on the circle of candi- identity and do not regard each other as belonging to a
date countries. At the same Luxembourg summit, the EU common moral community. If this was the case, justice
also decided to establish a ``European Conference’ ’ that would lose any worth for con¯ ict resolution. The parties’
would include all EU members and all European coun- rigid ideas of justice, and their ® rm convictions that their
tries considered as potential candidates for membership. own view is the only objective and true one, would rather
Turkey was also invited to this conference, but refused to hinder con¯ ict resolution. Con¯ ict may only be resolved
take part and did not want to accept this ``consolation in this case if there is a resolution that leads to better
prize.’ ’ Inviting Turkey may have been a means of outcomes for both parties as compared to a non-
demonstrating that the EU did not want to (morally) resolution. In other cases, the parties may actually
exclude Turkey and that the EU acknowledged Turkey’s belong to, or commonly refer to, some (multinational )
entitlement to apply for membership and to serious inclusive body (e.g. the United Nations, EU). However,
consideration of its application. Turkey, however, felt quite often this inclusive category is ill-de® ned and the
this invitation to be an empty placatory gesture. Perhaps parties disagree on its essence. Such divergent concep-
the justice implications of the EU action were not clear tions of the common inclusive category instead breed
enough to successfully avoid Turkey’s impression of con¯ ict between the parties and form the basis for
being (morally) excluded. A more explicit re¯ ection of perceptions of social discrimination (Mummendey &
each parties’ justice notions might have contributed to a Wenzel, 1999). Con¯ ict resolution would require the
less emotional, and more constructive, debate. The parties to ® rst come to terms with each other with respect
con¯ ict cooled down meanwhile; but with respect to to a shared understanding of a common superordinate
the acceptance function we pointed out earlier, it may category.
be feared that, due to the insuf® cient discussion of justice The present discussion illustrated the main points of
notions, a residual con¯ ict could easily lead to new our analysis by making reference to a recent example of
tensions in future. international con¯ ict and diplomatic controversy. In
134 MIKULA AND WENZEL

spite of this focus on international con¯ icts, the argu- (pp. 183± 215). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates
ments of the analysis are meant to hold likewise for Inc.
Folger, R. (1994). Workplace justice and employee worth.
intergroup con¯ icts on a smaller scale and interpersonal Social Justice Research, 7, 225± 240.
con¯ icts. Social justice research clearly contributes to our Furby, L. (1986). Psychology and justice. In R.L. Cohen (Ed.),
understanding of the basis, the dynamics, and the possi- Justice: Views from the social sciences (pp. 153± 203). New
ble resolutions of social con¯ icts. It also helps us to York: Plenum Press.
Hegtvedt, K.A., & Cook, K.S. (1987). The role of justice in
understand why con¯ ict resolutions are often so dif® cult
con¯ ict situations. In E.J. Lawler & B. Markowsky (Eds.),
to achieve. Advances in group processes, Vol. 4 (pp. 109± 136).
Greenwich, CT: JAI Press.
REFERENCES Lerner, M.J. (1987). Integrating societal and psychological
rules of entitlement: The basic task of each social actor
and fundamental problem for the social sciences. Social
Allison, S.T., & Messick, D.M. (1990). Social decision heuris- Justice Research, 1, 107± 125.
tics in the use of shared resources. Journal of Behavioral Lerner, M.J. (1991). Integrating societal and psychological
Decisions Making, 3, 195± 204. rules of entitlement. In R. Vermunt & H. Steensma (Eds.),
Baumeister, R.F., Stillwell, A., & Wotman, S.R. (1990). Victim Social justice in human relations, Vol. 1 (pp. 13± 32). New
and perpetrator accounts of interpersonal con¯ ict: Auto- York: Plenum Press.
biographical narratives about anger. Journal of Personality Leventhal, G.S. (1980). What should be done with equity
and Social Psychology, 59, 994± 1005. theory? New approaches to the study of fairness in social
``Bittere EnttaÈuschung’ ’ Ð ein Stimmungsbild [``Bitter dis- relationships. In K.J. Gergen, M.S. Greenberg, & R.H.
appointment’’ Ð a picture of the general atmosphere] (1998, Willis (Eds.), Social exchange: Advances in theory and
April 16). Die Zeit, p. 13. research (pp. 27± 55). New York: Plenum Press.
Blumenthal, M.D., Kahn, R.L., Andrew, F.M., & Head, K.B. Major, B. (1994). From social inequality to personal entitle-
(1972). Justifying violence: Attitudes of American men. Ann ment: The role of social comparisons, legitimacy appraisals,
Arbor, MI: Institute of Social Research, University of and group membership. In M. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in
Michigan. experimental social psychology, Vol. 26 (pp. 293± 355). New
Buhbe, M. (1998). Die TuÈrkei und die Grenzen der euro- York: Academic Press.
paÈischen Integration [Turkey and the limits of European McLaughlin, M.L., Cody, M.J., & O’ Hair, H.D. (1983) . The
integration]. Internationale Politik und Gesellschaft, 2, management of failure events: Some contextual deter-
157± 172. minants of accounting behaviour. Human Communication
Cohen, R.L. (1986a). Introduction. In R.L. Cohen (Ed.), Jus- Research, 9, 208± 224.
tice: Views from the social sciences (pp. 1± 9). New York: Messick, D.M. (1993). Equality as a decision heuristic. In B.A.
Plenum Press. Mellers & J. Baron (Eds.), Psychological perspectives on
Cohen, R.L. (1986b). Power and justice in intergroup rela- justice: Theory and applications (pp. 11± 31). New York:
tions. In H.W. Bierhoff, R.L. Cohen, & J. Greenberg Cambridge University Press.
(Eds.), Justice in social relations (pp. 65± 84). New York: Mikula, G. (1980). On the role of justice in allocation deci-
Plenum Press. sions. In G. Mikula (Ed.), Justice and social interaction
Cohen, R.L. (1987). Distributive justice: Theory and research. (pp. 204± 227). New York: Springer.
Social Justice Research, 1, 19± 40. Mikula, G. (1984). Justice and fairness in interpersonal rela-
Cohen, R.L. (1991) . Membership, intergroup relations, and tions: Thoughts and suggestions. In H. Tajfel (Ed.), The
justice. In R. Vermunt & H. Steensma (Eds.), Social justice social dimension, Vol. 1 (pp. 204± 227), Cambridge:
in human relations. Vol. 1: Societal and psychological origins Cambridge University Press.
of justice (pp. 239± 257). New York: Plenum Press. Mikula, G. (1987). Exploring the experience of injustice. In
Crosby, F., Muehrer, P., & Loewenstein, G. (1986). Relative G.R. Semin & B. Krahe (Eds.) Issues in contemporary
deprivation and explanation: Models and concepts. In J.M. German social psychology (pp. 74± 96). London: Sage.
Olson, C.P. Herman, & M.P. Zanna (Eds.), Relative depriva- Mikula, G. (1993). On the experience of injustice. In W. Stroebe
tion and social comparison: The Ontario symposium, Vol. 4 & M. Hewstone (Eds.), European review of social psychology
(pp. 17± 32). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Vol. 4 (pp. 232± 244). Chichester, UK: Wiley.
Inc. Mikula, G. (1994). Perspective-related differences in inter-
Deutsch, M. (1975) . Equity, equality, and need: What deter- pretations of injustice by victims and victimizers: A test with
mines which values will be used as the basis of distributive close relationships. In M.J. Lerner & G. Mikula (Eds.),
justice? Journal of Social Issues, 31, 137± 149. Entitlement and the affectional bond: Justice in close relation-
Eckhoff, T. (1974). Justice: Its determinants in social inter- ships (pp. 175± 203). New York: Plenum Press.
action. Rotterdam, The Netherlands: Rotterdam University Mikula, G., Athenstaedt, U., Heschgl, S., & Heimgartner, A.
Press. (1998). Does it only depend on the point of view? Perspec-
Eggins, R. (1997). Social identity processes in intergroup tive-related differences in justice evaluations of negative in-
con¯ ict: Negotiating the path to resolution. Unpublished cidents in personal relationships. European Journal of Social
manuscript. Psychology, 28, 932± 962.
Fisher, R., Ury, W., & Patton, B. (1991). Getting to yes: Nego- Montada, L. (1991). Coping with life stress: Injustice and the
tiating agreement without giving in (2nd ed.). New York: question ``who is responsible?’ ’ In H. Steensma & R. Vermunt
Penguin. (Eds.), Social justice in human relations, Vol. 2 (pp. 9± 30).
Folger, R. (1986). Rethinking equity theory: A referent cogni- New York: Plenum Press.
tions model. In H.W. Bierhoff, R.L. Cohen, & J. Greenberg Mummendey, A., Linneweber, V., & LoÈschper, G. (1984).
(Eds.), Justice in social relations (pp. 145± 162). New York: Actor or victim of aggression: Divergent perspectivesÐ
Plenum Press. divergent evaluation. European Journal of Social Psychology,
Folger, R. (1987). Reformulating the preconditions of resent- 14, 297± 311.
ment: A referent cognitions model. In J.C. Masters & W.P. Mummendey, A., & Otten, S. (1989). Perspective-speci® c dif-
Smith (Eds.), Social comparisons, social justice, and relative ferences in the segmentation and evaluation of aggressive
deprivation: Theoretical, empirical, and policy perspectives
JUSTICE AND SOCIAL CONFLICT 135

interaction sequences. European Journal of Social Psy- dimensions of bargaining and negotiation. In H. Tajfel
chology, 19, 23± 40. (Ed.), The social dimension, Vol. 2 (pp. 646± 667).
Mummendey, A., & Wenzel, M. (1999). Social discrimination Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
and tolerance in intergroup relations: Reactions to inter- Stillwell, A.M., & Baumeister, R.F. (1997). The construction
group difference. Personality and Social Psychology Review, of victim and perpetrator memories: Accuracy and distor-
3, 158± 174. tion in role-based accounts. Personality and Social Psy-
Opotow, S. (Ed.). (1990) . Special issue: Moral exclusion and chology Bulletin, 23, 1157± 1172.
injustice. Journal of Social Issues, 46, 1. Tedeschi, J.T., & Nesler, M. (1993). Grievances: Development
Otten, S., Mummendey, A., & Wenzel, M. (1995). The evalua- and reactions. In R. Felson & J.T. Tedeschi (Eds.), Aggres-
tion of aggressive interpretations in interpersonal and inter- sion and violence: A social interactionist approach (pp. 13±
group contexts. Aggressive Behavior, 21, 205± 224. 45). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Perelman, C. (1963). The idea of justice and the problem of Turkey accuses Kohl on EU policy. (1998, March 6). The
argument. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Financial Times, p. 1.
Pruitt, D.G., & Carnevale, P.J. (1993). Negotiation in social Turner, J.C., Hogg, M.A., Oakes, P.J., Reicher, S.D., &
con¯ ict. Paci® c Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole. Wetherell, M.S. (1987). Rediscovering the social group: A
Reicher, S. (1996). ``The battle of Westminster:’ ’ Developing self-categorization theory. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
the social identity model of crowd behaviour in order to Tyler, T.R., Boeckmann, R.J., Smith, H.J., & Huo, Y.J. (1997).
explain the initiation and development of collective con¯ ict. Social justice in a diverse society. Boulder, CO: Westview
European Journal of Social Psychology, 26, 115± 134. Press.
Reis, H.T. (1984). The multidimensionality of justice. In Walster, E., & Walster, G.W. (1975). Equity and social justice.
R. Folger (Ed.), The sense of injustice: Social psychological Journal of Social Issues, 31, 21± 43.
perspectives (pp. 25± 61). New York: Plenum Press. Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of justice: A defense of pluralism
Rubin, J.Z., Pruitt, D.G., & Kim, S.H. (1994). Social con¯ ict: and equality. New York: Basic Books.
Escalation, stalemate, and settlement (2nd ed.). New York: Wenzel, M. (1997). Soziale Kategorisierungen im Bereich dis-
McGraw-Hill. tributiver Gerechtigkeit [Social categorizations in the realm
Samuelson, C.D., & Allison, S.T. (1994). Cognitive factors of distributive justice]. MuÈnster, Germany: Waxman.
affecting the use of social decision heuristics in resource- Wenzel, M. (1998). A social categorisation approach to dis-
sharing tasks. Organizational Behavior and Human Perfor- tributive justice: Social identity as the link between relevance
mance, 58, 1± 27. of inputs and need for justice. Unpublished manuscript.
SchoÈnbach, P. (1990). Account episodes: The management of Wenzel, M. (in press). Justice and identity: The signi® cance of
escalation of con¯ ict. New York: Cambridge University inclusion for perceptions of entitlement and the justice
Press. motive. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin.
Scott, M.B., & Lyman, S.M. (1968). Accounts. American Wenzel, M., Mikula, G., Faber, G., Avci, M., Enge, W.,
Sociological Review, 23, 46-62. Liekefedt, H., Mummendey, A., & Schulz, P. (1996).
Steil, J.M. (1994). Equality and entitlement in marriage: Funktionen von Gerechtigkeitsauffassungen und Gerechtig-
Bene® ts and barriers. In M.J. Lerner & G. Mikula (Eds.), keitsrhetoriken fuÈr Genese, Verlauf und Management von
Entitlement and the affectional bond: Justice in close relation- Kon¯ ikten [Functions of justice notions and justice rhetorics
ships (pp. 229± 258). New York: Plenum Press. with respect to development, course, and management of
Stephenson, G.M. (1984). Intergroup and interpersonal con¯ icts]. Zeitschrift fuÈr Sozialpsychologie, 27, 137± 147.

You might also like