You are on page 1of 34

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/326126971

A Pragmatic Approach of Distributive Justice

Thesis · July 2018

CITATIONS READS

0 22

1 author:

Vincent van Grondelle


University Pompeu Fabra
10 PUBLICATIONS   0 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

A Pragmatic Approach of Distributive Justice (Master's Thesis) View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Vincent van Grondelle on 02 July 2018.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


A P RAGMATIC A PPROACH
OF D ISTRIBUTIVE J USTICE

By

Vincent van Grondelle

How combining principles of Distributive Justice with social-


scientific evidence can challenge global wealth inequality

Presented to the faculty of Political and


Social Sciences at the University Pompeu Fabra

In fulfilment of the requirement s for the degree


of Master of Arts in Political Philosophy

Under supervision of
professor Santiago Zabala

Master’s Thesis

Barcelona, June 2018


As long as poverty, injustice and gross inequality
persist in our world, none of us can truly rest.

Nelson Mandela
TABLE OF CONTENTS

INTRODUCTION 4

PART I: THE HARMFUL SIDE OF INEQUALITY 7

PSYCHOLOGICAL IMPLICATIONS 7

POLITICAL IMPLICATIONS 8

HUMANITARIAN IMPLICATIONS 10

PART II: PRINCIPLES OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE 12

EGALITARIANISM 12

SUFFICIENTARIANISM 13

LIMITARIANISM 14

PART III: REALISTIC EGALITARIANISM 17

A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE 17

THE FEASIBLITY AND DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTIONS 22

CONCLUSION 26

BIBLIOGRAPHY 29

ABSTRACT
In this paper I argue for a pragmatic model of Distributive Justice called ‘Realistic Egalitarianism’. By
examining the severe psychological, political and humanitarian implications of extreme inequality, I will
develop arguments why two of the existing principles of Distributive Justice - Limitarianism and
Sufficientarianism - should be combined and used to create both a minimum and a maximum threshold
for wealth possession. These arguments will be further developed by arguing against the possible
‘feasibility’ and ‘demandingness’ objections, and by stating that the implementation of Realistic
Egalitarianism not only needs two thresholds, but also requires specific forms of educational and
governmental interventions. Then, and only then, can Realistic Egalitarianism be the key to tackling
extreme global inequalities.
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

INTRODUCTION

A
ccording to the World Inequality Report 2018, recent decades have shown a large rise in
global income inequality in nearly all countries in the world. For example, in the United
States, the people with the top 10% income shared 34% of the American national income in 1980,
while they currently possess 48% of the national income. This increase was lower in Europe
(from 32% to 37%), but income inequality in China, India and Russia has increased at an even
higher pace. In Russia for instance, statistics show a rise from 21% to 56%, which exposes how
the abandoning of communism has affected inequality. The few exceptions that have a relatively
stable income inequality, such as the Middle East, sub-Saharan Africa and Brazil, show constant
huge income differences over time, as 10% of the top-earners in these countries received
between 55% and 77% of the national income. Analysing the complete picture since 1980, the
top 1% richest individuals in the world have benefitted from twice as much growth as the
bottom 50% of people (1).
Not only these income differences indicate how unbalanced our current world is; differences
in capital distribution are equally substantial. In 2017, the 500 richest people on earth have seen
their ownership of capital rise with almost a 1,000 billion dollar, leading to a total capital
ownership of 5,300 billion dollar. This is a rise of 23% in just one year (2). At the same time,
human development organisation Oxfam has estimated that the poorest half of the world
population possesses 400 billion dollars (3), which is half of the one-year total rise of capital
ownership by the richest in 2017. Oxfam claimed that this year, for the first time in human
history, the richest 1% of the world population own more than half of the world’s wealth
(50.1%). More specifically, their report pointed out that the richest 42 people in the world
possessed the same amount of money as the poorest 3.7 billion people, more than half of the
world population. This is a significant difference with 2009, when 380 billionaires owned the
same amount of wealth as these 42 do now. In total, from the 9,000 billion dollar rise of global
wealth, 82% of that rise ended up in the hands of the richest 1% of the world, while the poorest
half did not gain any advantage from this growth (4). This relates to the claim of UN coordinator
Jan Vandemoortele, who argued that macro-economic stability and growth do not automatically
benefit the poor (5), which means that numeric averages of economic growth are poor indicators
of a reduction of poverty or inequality.
While the trend towards growing inequality may not be similar in every country, the overall
curve is steadily increasing every year. It is claimed that this will soon lead to the emergence of
the first ‘trillionaire’, which illustrates how vast extreme wealth is developing. A trillion dollar
is a one with twelve zeroes, a thousand billion dollars, or, as The Independent reporter James
Vincent pointed out, enough to offer every person on earth 140 dollars each or buy all real estate
of central London (6). Amazon founder Jeff Bezos is rapidly coming closer to reaching this almost

4
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

unimaginable amount of wealth with a current ownership of 116.8 billion dollars (7). Even
though he ‘only’ possesses roughly 10% of the magic number of a trillion dollars, the rapid
growth of income and ownership by the richest 1% since 1980 made Oxfam speculate that the
arrival of the first trillionaire might happen within the next 25 years (8). In consideration of this
and the data of the previous paragraphs, it can be concluded that the group of richest people in
the world is not only becoming wealthier, but individually also reach new levels of wealth that
are creating even wider gaps with the remainder of the world population. An important note
here is that the numbers about ‘the richest 1%’ are not only about the billionaires and the
upcoming trillionaires, but embrace all people with a yearly income of 30.250 euros or more1 (9).
While the wealth levels of the richest people are steadily increasing, 10.7% of the world’s
population live below the extreme poverty line, meaning that 767 million people live off 1.90
dollars or less a day. Especially in Sub-Saharan Africa, many people need to survive on this bare
minimum. However, at the same time, it is claimed by The World Bank that the number of people
living below the poverty line is steadily declining, with an average pace of 1.1 percentage points
a year since 1990 (10). Yet, while looking at more of Vandemoortele’s assertions, it cannot only
be questioned whether existing poverty norms are valid minimum levels, but it can also be
argued that considering economic growth as the best way to reduce poverty might be a wrong
assumption. According to Vandemoortele, “Much will depend on how [economic] stability is
achieved” and “more nuanced positions and conclusions are warranted, given the many
complexities that govern the relationship between growth and poverty” (5). A good example of
this can be found in Africa, where recent reports show that the number of people living in
extreme poverty has grown substantially, even though general poverty numbers may be lower
than previous estimates (11).
So, where there soon might be people having so much wealth that they could buy Apple, help
approximately 8 million Americans through all four years of college or order 26,000 1963 Ferrari
250 GTO's (12); a huge part of the world’s population will live in deprivation and will not be
able to provide their families with basic health care, enough food or a roof over their head. This
contradiction, combined with the data mentioned thus far, leads to the content and the purpose
of this paper2.

1 When considering wealth level instead of income numbers, the threshold is higher. To be part
of the richest 1% based on wealth, you will need to possess a minimum of 720.000 euros in net
worth (9).
2 This paper has been commissioned by the University Pompeu Fabra in Barcelona, Spain. The

word count is – without footnotes – 10,282 and the paper consists of a total of 33 pages. The
paper has been supervised by professor Santiago Zabala and is written in fulfilment of the
requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Political Philosophy. The paper has been
submitted in June 2018.

5
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

I strongly believe in Nelson Mandela’s claim that “As long as poverty, injustice and gross
inequality persist in our world, none of us can truly rest” (13). Or, in slightly different words, if
there is a group of people who have sufficient resources to live a humane, healthy and peaceful
life, they cannot turn their eyes away from a group of people who lack the means to also live
such a life. In Part I of this paper, by analysing the various consequences of huge global
inequalities, I will offer reasons why the validity of this reasoning can be strengthened, as
inequality has many negative and even dangerous implications. To do so, I will adopt an
interdisciplinary approach where I will combine various sources from political and social
sciences. Next, in Part II, I will assert different theories within the discipline of Political Philosophy
that can be used to combat inequality. These principles of ‘Distributive Justice’ offer concepts
on how the benefits and burdens of society should be distributed and how for example income,
wealth, opportunities, jobs and welfare should be allocated. Finally, in Part III, I aim to offer a
framework for a pragmatic approach of Distributive Justice by combining existing theories of
Distributive Justice with current data on global inequality. By doing so, I intend to make the
abstract ideas of Distributive Justice applicable to one of the most urgent and difficult challenges
of contemporary times: reducing the extent of global inequality.

6
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

PART I: THE HARMFUL SIDE OF INEQUALITY

“We may have democracy, or we may have wealth concentrated in

the hands of a few, but we cannot have both.” – Louis Brandeis

T he introduction of this paper has shown that global inequality is not only persistent
throughout recent decades, but is also increasing at a steady pace. However, so far,
nothing has been said about the consequences of inequality itself. How does inequality affect
people’s behaviour? How does it influence political relations and stability? How can it cause
obstacles related to health care or food and water access? To address these types of questions, I
will now examine the psychological, political and humanitarian implications of extensive
inequality.

PSYCHOLOGICAL IMPLICATIONS
Various studies show that inequality has two sorts of psychological implications. On the one
hand, it has been established that being at the bottom of the wealth distribution has severe,
negative consequences for one’s psychological well-being. For instance, a 2012 study on the
relationship between inequality and happiness showed that (income) inequality directly affects
people’s happiness for two different reasons. The first and most obvious reason, self-interest,
affects people’s well-being as people tend to have negative attitudes towards inequality when
they themselves are on the ‘wrong’ side of it. The second reason, regard for others, affects people’s
well-being as research shows that humans often have truly egalitarian preferences and strong
beliefs on fairness. If these preferences or beliefs are not met, it will have an impact on their
happiness level (14). After all, when you think of yourself watching a commercial of starving
children in Africa, it is quite likely that you will experience the negative feeling that the world
is rather unjust than fair.
A different study, performed in the United States, argued that there is a strong relationship
between income inequality and poor health, as the study pointed out that more unequal states
showed higher incidences of depressions (15). Other research on inequality has shown similar
results, but also demonstrated that places with high inequality rates are associated with
increased anxiety and mistrust about social status. This does not only lead to lower happiness,
but also to lower social cohesion, weaker morality, higher mortality and worse health (16).
Furthermore, there is evidence found that more egalitarian societies consistently do better than
unequal ones, and even that psychiatric problems such as schizophrenia, narcissism and
psychotic symptoms are more common in less equal societies (17).

7
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

On the other hand, research has shown that being at the top of the inequality scale can lead
to negative attitudes towards people who are less fortunate. Princeton University has conducted
a study in which the brain activity of university students was monitored while they were
looking at images of different sorts of people. The MRI scans specifically focussed on the part of
the brain that normally is activated when someone thinks of other people. However, when
images were shown of homeless people, drug addicts or other less-fortunate people, this part
stayed inactive. On the contrary, the (mostly affluent) students responded to these images as if
they “had tumbled on a pile of trash”. The research concluded that being extremely wealthy
could lead to seeing the less rich as “subhuman” (18). Similar results were found in a study from
the Universities of Amsterdam and California, in which couples that never met before were
asked to share personal issues with each other. It was demonstrated that the wealthier
individuals tended to show fewer compassion towards the difficulties of the less-rich and less-
powerful (19).
By analysing the consistency of the above explained study outcomes, it can be determined
that a large social gap between people (i.e. large inequality) often leads to a high prevalence of
mental illnesses, lower happiness levels and poorer health. At the same time, it is also shown
that it can cause severe implications for the way people behave towards each other, which leads
me to the next section of this chapter: the political implications of inequality.

POLITICAL IMPLICATIONS
Concluding from the previous paragraph, inequality has a significant impact on the empathy
levels of wealthier people. It has been argued that as a consequence, this may well influence
political decisions and policies (18). For example, when there is a large social distance between
a (wealthy) politician and a (poorer) working-class individual, and therefore a lack of empathy
from the political side, social policies will find it harder to come into existence. After all, if you
would consider the poor person to be less human or when you lack the empathy to understand
her or his situation, it is less likely that you will think of policies that can help this person out of
deprivation.
This is in line with the findings of philosophy and law professor Thomas Christiano. In his
paper Money in Politics he explains how money can be turned into political power, and how this
has strong influence on laws and policies. According to Christiano, this can occur via four
mechanisms. Firstly, as rich people can easily use money to fund political parties and
individuals, it will not only create significant influence by the donor on the political program,
but may also lead to a situation in which the implemented policies protect the donor's own
interest. An extreme example is currently occurring in American politics, where a new tax bill
by president Donald Trump proposes a drop of 2.6% for the individual tax rate (from 39.6% to
37) and a drop of 14% for the corporate tax rate (from 35% to 21%). It is claimed that this will

8
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

only benefit the richest classes and large companies, and will simultaneously deprive the
American middle class, thus leading to higher levels of inequality (20). However, the bill does
not only benefit the well-off, but will also benefit Trump’s own companies, as calculations show
that he will save approximately 11 million dollars a year if the new tax system would be
implemented (21).
Secondly, when the ability to raise funds becomes an important aspect of political campaigns,
and the upper-middle-class and rich people have more possibilities to fund these campaigns (as
they simply have more money), the political candidates who represent these groups are more
likely to end up as final candidates. Resulting from this, candidates who represent the poor and
middle-class people are therefore less likely to be elected, and the political influence by these
groups consequently decreases. A recent example can be found in the US Democratic elections
of 2016, won by Hilary Clinton, went on to almost win the US elections of 2017. With a joint
income of 10.5 million dollars, a political campaign largely funded by large banks and with a
campaign budget of 623.1 million dollars (22), it is claimed that she only represented the rich
and successful people of American society. Characterizing for this was her statement regarding
Trump voters, whom she called “the basket of deplorables” (23), reinforcing her distance from
the working-class people. However, at the same time, the other democratic candidate, Bernie
Sanders, had to campaign without support from large companies and ‘only’ had 234.3 million
dollars to spend3 (25), while he placed a much stronger emphasis on combatting wealth
inequality, establishing free education and creating higher salaries in favour of working-class
people (24).
Thirdly, as the media can be highly susceptible to money as well, they can easily be used by
most well-off to spread their political ideas and create positive attitudes towards their political
goals. A good example can be found in Italy, where for decades (extremely-wealthy) ex-
president Silvio Berlusconi has wielded immense political influence, even though he was part
of several scandals. It is often argued that his ownership of several Italian media sources allowed
him to decrease the impact of his own controversies. Furthermore, there are claims that his
influence in the media was also used to spread his own political ideas (26; 27).
Lastly, as the most well-off people often have portions of their wealth concentrated in large
firms, they have the capability to use the economic power of these firms to change political
discourse (28). To give an example, imagine a labour union that comes to an agreement with the
government about higher salaries for low-skilled workers. The companies that employs these

3 Sanders did not received funding from billionaires and large corporations but raised his
funding budget with small contributions from people all over America. In total, there were 7
million individual contributions paid to support his campaign, making it one of the most
successful insurgent campaigns in the history of the democratic party (79). Still, he lost the
democratic elections.

9
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

workers could respond by threatening to move to another (cheaper) country, thereby causing
unemployment and economic instability. The government might then reconsider the agreement
and continue to allow the low salaries, and thereby continue to reinforce inequality.
Concluding from all this, it can be said that inequality can both arise from politics as well as
influence politics, and that it directly endangers democracy and political equality. The
consequence of the most well-off having high political influence could be that public spending
is not directed – as normally – to the common good, but rather to benefit the rich by tax cuts and
regulations. This can then result in under-investment in public services such as health, social
benefits and education, and in extreme cases, may lead to a society that is solely ruled by the
wealthy, i.e. a plutocracy (29).

HUMANITARIAN IMPLICATIONS
Apart from severe psychological and political implications, there are also humanitarian
consequences to extensive inequality that directly harm people. These are often strongly related
to environmental issues caused by human behaviour. An unfortunate but coherent example of
this can currently be found in South Africa, where the major city of Cape Town is coming closer
to ‘Day Zero’; the day that the city runs out of water. A researcher at the Global Change Institute
at the University of Witwatersrand, David Olivier, claims that the main causes of the shortage
are the general attitude towards water usage and the way people live. According to Olivier, “It's
'we pay our taxes' and therefore we should be as comfortable as possible” (30). However, a claim
like this can only be used by the people who can actually pay for high water usage. A large part
of Cape Town’s residents lives in townships such as Khayelitsha, where people have no
bathrooms, much less a dishwasher or a washing machine. While the richer people complain
about the current water restriction of 25 litres a day 4, people in the townships are used to a
maximum of 50 litres a day for years (31). They do not have the swimming pools, gardens and
other water-intensive means that play a big part in the water shortage issues (32). However,
even though the problem is largely caused by the water usage of people who can afford such
large water consumption, they are at the same time the people who are least affected by the
problems. The affluent can use expensive water delivery and in-built tanks to meet their demand
for water, while the poor people are seeing their already low water consumption being reduced
even further (33). A water crisis like this is not only endangering stability in Cape Town, but

4 To compare, in 2014, average daily water usage per person in the US went over 500 litres. In
Europe, per person water usage in countries such as Italy and Spain was between 300 and 400
litres a day. In countries such as Mozambique, Uganda and Rwanda, average water usage per
person was between 5 and 20 litres a day (81).

10
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

also threatens cities such as São Paulo, Bangalore and Beijing; cities that also endure high
inequality levels (34; 35; 36; 37).
There are many other examples of humanitarian implications of inequality. Think of
construction workers in Dubai, who are living in extreme poverty while working for the extreme
rich in dangerous conditions. Because the poor work for starvation wages5, the rich are capable
to expand their wealth and property to a great extent (38). A different example can be found in
the clothing business, an industry that clearly demonstrates the global humanitarian
consequences of large inequalities. According to a report by the International Labour Organisation,
most of the 170 million children that are globally engaged in child labour are working in this
controversial industry. Clothing companies can only keep up with the large demand of
(wealthier) consumers in Europe, the US and beyond by using these forms of cheap labour from
for instance Egypt, Pakistan, China, India and Bangladesh (39; 40). Another example are fuel
consumption patterns, as many people continue to use relatively cheap gas from companies that
have consistently participated in human rights violations that expanded inequality, such as gas
company Shell (41). It seems that extensive, global inequality only leads to greater inequality,
and even causes humanitarian threats that can result in severe harm for large numbers of people.

5The average per capita income in the United Arabic Emirates is 2,106 dollars per month, while
the average migrant worker earns only 175 dollars a month (78).

11
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

PART II: PRINCIPLES OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

“The worst form of inequality is to try to make unequal things equal” - Aristotle

B
ased on the previous part, we can conclude that inequality has harmful implications for
large groups of people. Does this make inequality morally unjustified? This question leads
us to political philosophy, a field of study in which principles of ‘Distributive Justice’ try to
determine what a justified distribution of goods should be. These principles can be considered
as the framework or the moral guidance for political policies and structures (42). In this second
part, I will briefly address three principles of Distributive Justice that are all very much related
to the social-scientific data discussed thus far. I will start with examining the principle of
Egalitarianism.

EGALITARIANISM
The principle of Egalitarianism claims that people should be treated the same, be treated as
equals and/or receive the same. The moral idea behind this theory, historically emerged from
the Christian belief that God loves all human souls equally, is that all human beings are
fundamentally equal in what they are worth. Someone who supports this principle will uphold
the idea that all people ought to be treated as equals and all are intitled to the same fundamental
level of dignity. Within this principle, no one can and should be born into a caste or a favoured
race. This preference for full equality can have an instrumental value, where equality is deemed
important due to its advancement of solidarity and community among people, or it can have a
non-instrumental value, whereby equality has moral importance and is understood as a
component of justice.
Within Egalitarianism, the concept of Equality of Opportunity is often considered as an ideal
situation. This idea states that every single human should have the same opportunities in life,
and if not, should be given the resources to have these opportunities. This means that in an ideal
society, everyone would have the same starting position, and jobs and positions would be open
to all applicants. As all people would have the same starting position, no one is able to use pre-
owned wealth to prepare oneself better for life opportunities. A strong egalitarian will therefore
aim to eliminate any advantages created by family wealth or social status (43). At the same time,
Equality of Opportunity is not necessarily incompatible with inequality. While in a caste society
inequality can result from simply being born; in a society of Equality of Opportunity, inequality
can arise from forms of competitive processes to which everyone is eligible to on equal terms.
After all, if everyone is given the same starting point, they can then compete for the positions
and jobs they would prefer, which could still lead to some people having more than others (44).

12
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

Thus, Equality of Opportunity allows distributive differences, as long as they are not fixed in
advance and result from processes in which all people are treated equally (45). Famous
philosopher John Rawls (1921-2002) summarizes this reasoning in A Theory of Justice (46):

“Those who are at the same level of talent and ability, and have the same willingness to use them,
should have the same prospects of success regardless of their initial place in the social system”.
(Rawls, p. 73, 1971)

However, it is often claimed that this ideal might lead to unequal rewards, which are then
incompatible with the egalitarian principles. How should these rewards be limited and justified?
Harvard philosopher Thomas Scanlon (1940) has proposed a three-level justification for
inequality emerging from the Equality of Opportunity, which consists of Institution Justification,
Procedural Fairness and Substantive Opportunity. The first justification claims that having an
institution that generates certain inequalities is fair, which means that inequalities can be
justified “simply by the fact that they arise from interactions between individuals exercising
their property and contract rights”. This Institutional Justification relates to Rawls’s Difference
Principle, as this principle would allow institutions to create inequalities, as long as they benefit
those who are worse-off (46). The second justification says that inequality is justified when the
process that led to inequality was procedurally fair, meaning that for example “no fraud or theft
was involved”. The last justification says that it is not unjust to withhold people from an
opportunity if they do not have the necessary qualifications (47). Following these justifications,
inequality can be legitimated, even within Egalitarianism.

SUFFICIENTARIANISM
Philosopher Harry Frankfurt (1929) has argued that not everyone should have the same, as has
been claimed by Egalitarians, but rather should have enough. He further examined this idea in
his principle of Sufficientarianism. From a moral point of view, Frankfurt claimed that the very
idea of equality cannot be neutral and rather creates “envy”, and at the same time causes “moral
shallowness” because of its lack of interest in determining what is enough. According to
Frankfurt, “it is whether people have good lives, and not how their lives compare with the lives
of others” (48). Thus, the importance is not to compare wealth differences between certain
groups of people, but rather to make sure that people have sufficient means to reach a threshold
that allows them to have a decent life prospect. The doctrine of Sufficientarianism therefore
holds that it should be prevented that people fall below a sufficiency threshold that would
prevent them from having such a life (43). According to philosophy professor Paula Casal, a
good reason to support Sufficientarianism can be based on the ideas of philosopher Karl Popper
(1902-1994), who stated the following (49):

13
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

“[There is] no symmetry between suffering and happiness, or between pain and pleasure. Human
suffering makes a direct moral appeal, namely, the appeal for help, while there is no similar call
to increase the happiness of a man who is doing well anyway.” (Popper, p. 570-71, 1943)

Following Poppers reasoning, it is not the pursuit of happiness that should have the highest
priority, but rather the avoidance of situations that could harm people, which would therefore
make Sufficientarianism the strongest principle of Distributive Justice.
The principle of Sufficientarianism is based on a positive and a negative thesis. This means
that when one individual finds her- or himself below the threshold of sufficiency, while
someone else is above the threshold, the priority should be given to the first individual in order
to put her or him above the threshold. This is the positive thesis. However, when both
individuals are above the threshold, the position of the less well-off does not matter; this being
the negative thesis. The goal of Sufficientarianism is to use all available resources to give as
many people as possible enough (50). This also means that when people pass the minimum
threshold to live a decent life, there is no need to offer further forms of aid (51).
The idea that everyone should have enough brings forth two questions: enough of what and
how much is enough? Economics philosopher Amartya Sen (1933) tried to answer this question
by creating a framework to measure poverty and use this to determine a minimum threshold
(52). Elizabeth Anderson has rather claimed for ‘democratic equality’, meaning that everyone
should have the ability to fully participate in a democratic society, which closely relates to the
concept of Equality of Opportunity (53). Frankfurt himself proposed that a threshold is reached
when someone does not have “an active interest in getting more”, as “a contented person
regards having more money as inessential to his being satisfied with his life”. Even though
someone might enjoy additional benefits by receiving more money, he is not “particularly eager
or restless” in receiving it (54).
Sufficientarianism has been criticised and several scholars tried to improve it. Nonetheless,
the underlying idea of Sufficientarianism can be used as valid argument to support those in
need and was of great influence in the emergence of welfare states (55), After all, the providence
of some minimum living standard is widely accepted in several countries around the world,
including the Netherlands, Denmark, Belgium, Norway and Sweden (56).

LIMITARIANISM
A quite new principal within Distributive Justice is what philosophy professor Ingrid Robeyns
(1972) calls Limitarianism. She advocates that it is not morally permissible to be rich, where
being rich is defined as “having more resources than are needed to fully flourish in life”. The
underlying reasons for holding this view are closely related to the implications of inequality that

14
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

have been mentioned earlier in this paper. For example, Robeyns also points to Christiano’s
paper Money in Politics to demonstrate how extreme wealth has severe implications for
democracy. Simultaneously, she uses an argument that strongly relates to the humanitarian
implications of inequality discussed in part I, which she calls the argument from unmet needs. This
argument is considered legitimate when at a certain moment in the world there are [1] extreme
global poverties, [2] local or global disadvantages for people, [3] urgent challenges in collective-
action and when these three conditions can be changed by active government-action and the
appropriate financial resources. Robeyns uses data comparable to those that have been
discussed in part I of this paper to show that our current world fulfils all these conditions. For
example, she claims that much of the current global poverty can be reduced by interventions
that require financial resources, including the institutional changes to make such interventions
possible. Also, she claims that people who are not extremely poor in a material way can still be
“deprived or disadvantaged in many other ways”. Think of children who need special
education that they are not receiving or people with mental health problems who cannot get
adequate support. Robeyns also argues that there are indeed “numerous collective-action
problems that require the attention of governments or other actors of change”, as many of the
major problems in the world “could be effectively addressed if only the government were to
devote sufficient attention and resources to these issues”.
Robeyns uses the Rescue Principle of Scanlon (57) to support her doctrine, which states the
following:

“If you are presented with a situation in which you can prevent something very bad from
happening, or alleviate someone’s dire plight, by making only a slight (or even moderate)
sacrifice, then it would be wrong not to do so”. (Scanlon, p. 244, 1998)

Following this reasoning, the well-off would have a direct duty to support those in need. After
all, using surplus money to prevent suffering does not demand a big sacrifice. However,
according to Robeyns, her limitarian principle is less demanding, as she does not defend an
intrinsic version of Limitarianism. In such an interpretation, being rich would be morally
objectionable in itself. Robeyns rather stands for a non-intrinsic version, which holds that “riches
are morally objectionable to a world where certain intrinsically important values are not secured
and where Limitarianism is instrumentally valuable to securing those ultimate ends”. Therefore,
she focusses her doctrine only on moral duties related to surplus money. This means that someone
will not be prevented from buying a new piano or taking a holiday abroad, as this can be
beneficial to further flourish in life and is therefore not considered to be wrong.
Related to the distinction between Limitarianism as an intrinsic or non-intrinsic doctrine is
the question how the principle should be realized. If Limitarianism is merely considered as a

15
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

moral doctrine, there would only be a moral duty not to be rich. This means that if one would
become rich, no one would prevent her or him from doing so, and it would solely violate a norm
that is set on the possession of wealth. However, Limitarianism can also be used as a political
doctrine, in which the government actively taxes surplus money, or in a more radical version,
reforms social and economic institutions so no one would even be allowed to gain surplus
money. As Robeyns applied political justifications to her principle and used Rawls’s vision of
justice, which holds that “Each person possesses an inviolability founded on justice that even
the welfare of society as a whole cannot override”, and that “for this reason, justice denies that
the loss of freedom for some is made right by a greater good shared by others” (46), she argues
for Limitarianism as political doctrine. After all, only when Limitarianism is accepted as part of
Rawls’s view on justice, coercive measures to achieve a just society would be made possible (58).

16
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

PART III: REALISTIC EGALITARIANISM

“Poverty is not an accident. Like slavery and apartheid, it is man-made and

can be removed by the actions of human beings” – Nelson Mandela

F
rom what has been demonstrated in the first two parts of this paper, it can be deduced that
the examined principles of Distributive Justice are not successfully applied to the current
global distribution of goods, as on the one hand, the most well-off are getting richer,
characterized by the possible emergence of the first ‘trillionaire’, and, on the other hand, the
least well-off are living below thresholds that prevent them from fully flourishing in life. This
leads to a still-growing inequality gap, as there is no wealth-limit for the first group of people
and no sufficiency-minimum for the latter. Because of this, one might claim that Egalitarianism,
Sufficientarianism and Limitarianism are merely ideal theories, rather than theories that are of
actual practical value.

A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE


Even though the current global situation seems far removed from the discussed principles of
Distributive Justice, this does not automatically mean that they could not work. For example,
despite large global obstacles, we have seen how the basic idea of Sufficientarianism has been
successfully applied in some welfare states. Still, on a larger scale, the global (political) system
of distribution seems too powerful to be affected by the ideas of Distributive Justice. This is
characterized by individual consumption behaviour and the unwillingness of governments to
change policies in favour of these principles. Think for example of Trump’s tax plan in favour
of the rich6 or the consumption patterns that can cause large problems such as the water shortage
in Cape Town.
Does this make these principles meaningless? After all, as philosophy professors Julian
Lamont and Christi Favor have pointed out, “Distributive Justice is not an area where we can
say an idea is good in theory but not in practice”, because “if it is not good in practice, then it is
not good in theory either” (42). I agree with their statement, as I think an important goal of
philosophers should be to reflect on how their ideas can work in practice. Nonetheless, I do not
consider the principles discussed fruitless because of this. I rather think that they should not be

6 One could argue that such tax changes can attract large companies to come (back) to the US
and therefore decrease unemployment levels. However, at the same time of the tax changes,
various federal social aid programs on which many poor people depend, such as Medicaid or
anti-poverty efforts, are also being reduced (82). As the least well-off will be mostly affected by
this, it shows that the general policy of the current US government is also not in favour of the
least well-off, whether there is less unemployment or not.

17
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

seen as separate principles, but used as supplementary to one another. Robeyns already advised
this regarding her own principle by stating that “The principle of Limitarianism can be
combined with additional recipient-oriented principles of justice or with distributive rules about
those parts of the distribution below the wealth line” (58).
Therefore, in this last part, I will argue for a hybrid model of Distributive Justice which I will
call Realistic Egalitarianism. Within this new principle, Sufficientarianism will be made possible
by the concept of Limitarianism, which can lead to a more equal, global society. The principle
will be grounded by the existing principles of Distributive Justice, but also by the implications
of extreme inequality that are described earlier in this paper. This makes the principle both
morally and theoretically justified, and simultaneously practically achievable.
To show how Realistic Egalitarianism works in practice, consider the following figure:

As made visible, Limitarianism pushes the extreme wealthy – the ones above the maximum
threshold (I) - downwards (II) by redistributing their surplus money (III) to the people below
the minimum threshold (IV), making the goal of Sufficientarianism – providing resources to the
worst-off to reach the minimum threshold – possible (V). The space between the thresholds will
be called Just Competition (VI), in which a free market economy can exist and where inequality

18
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

can occur as long as it is a result after complete Equality of Opportunity. This is not only a strong
moral improvement of current global distribution, but also makes the model feasible, as it does
not require the abolishment of a free market economy, i.e. capitalism. I will now explain the
various arguments that justify the model in more detail.

The argument for limited inequality


Realistic Egalitarianism does not oppose inequality per se, but aims to allow it under certain
circumstances, as I do not believe that wealth inequality in itself, or being richer than others, is
intrinsically bad. While everyone should be entitled to the same opportunities and have the
freedom to choose what to do with them, it needs to be taken into account that humans vary,
and that some are more content with having less, just as others can be happier with having more
and are therefore prepared to work more to gain more wealth. Having ambitions is relative, just
as being content with less is relative. Therefore, within Just Competition, Equality of
Opportunity is what matters, not full equality. Yet, it is important that within Just Competition,
Scanlon’s three level justification (Institution Justification, Procedural Fairness and Substantive
Opportunity) needs to be adhered, as only with those criteria the potential inequality can be
legitimated.
Allowing inequality also has a practical reason, as I consider it unrealistic to think about an
(almost) completely equal world where everyone has the same. Although I consider such
Marxist thoughts to be morally relevant, I follow Richard Rorty (1931-2007) that we do not have
to undo economic impoverishment by (solely) focussing on the wrongs of private ownership of
the means of production. Still, we need to take these concerns into account, as I consider Scanlon
to be correct when he stated that “workers, as participants in a scheme of cooperation that
produces national income, have a claim to a fair share of what they have helped to produce”
(59). However, even if it would be desired, I believe it is simply not possible to overthrew
capitalism in our current global system in its current state. Like Rorty, I rather belief that we
need a highly socialized democracy for a morally and socially desirable distribution of wealth
(60). Therefore, I argue that the goal should be to limit the harm that capitalism has done and is
doing, by aiming at a version of Realistic Egalitarianism in which capitalism and free market
economy can still exist (and thus inequality), as long as it takes place between the two thresholds
– within the space of Just Competition -, so everyone receives the fair share that Scanlon has
argued for.

The argument for limiting wealth


While Realistic Egalitarianism allows inequality and therefore allows that some people are
wealthier than others, it aims to prevent extreme inequalities by using Limitarianism to limit
wealth possession. Or, to put it differently: it prevents capitalism to result in an unfair

19
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

distribution of capital. This is because I do believe that extreme inequality is intrinsically bad due
to its implications that directly harm human well-being, as shown in earlier in this paper.
However, there is another reason why limiting wealth is not only justified, but is also a necessary
measure that can be grounded in the relationship between environmental evidence and
inequality; a relation that has already been discussed before. This connection can be further
explained by the claim that humanity has already passed many boundaries that keep our planet
hospitable to modern life, which has a strong impact on environmental issues such as climate
change (61). It can be claimed that the most well-off people will have the highest influence on
such issues, as they use the earth’s resources more intensively simply because they can effort to
do so. Think for example about the water shortage in Cape Town or consider that only the well-
off people can use many fuel-consuming transportation methods that affect climate change. This
can be proven by considering the model of the Global Footprint. This footprint is calculated in
global hectares, a metric that assesses the global per-person biological productive space, which
can be used to measure how much of the earth’s resources one person uses. It is claimed that
the current global average was 2.2 global hectares per person, which, according to the World
Wildlife Fund (WWF), is 20% to 25% over the number that our earth is able to handle (an estimate
of 1.8 hectares for every person) (62). However, if we consider specific countries, there are huge
differences. For example, with an average of 9.5 global hectares, the United States uses six times
more than the global average. And while the average in the Netherlands is 4.7 hectares,
individuals in India, Tanzania and Afghanistan use less than 1 global hectare per person. The
overall global trend shows familiar results, where richer countries indeed often play a more
significant role (63), as is visible in the following map (where darker means a higher global
hectare average):

At the same time, the environmental issues are not only mainly caused by the richer countries;
research has also shown how this depletion of the earth will exacerbate inequality, as poor
people will most likely pay the highest price for the economic consequences of for instance

20
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

climate change (64). Thus, when considering the negative snowball-effect of the richer countries’
high usage of earth resources, a limitation to wealth is a necessary and justified measure, as this
will force the well-off to reduce their usage of the earth’s resources7.

The argument for redistributing surplus wealth


As explained, Realistic Egalitarianism not only limits wealth, but also aims to redistribute the
remainder surplus wealth. There are two reasons to support this choice. The first reason is that
the redistribution of surplus wealth is merely a methodological choice for the operation of the
principle, as it is feasible to use surplus wealth – which is not needed for survival – for the
providence of sufficiency for the least well-off. For example, we could follow the idea of
economist and philosopher Philippe Van Parijs, who argued that we can use the profits of
capitalism to provide sufficiency via certain arrangements, such as a universal grant (i.e. basic
income) (65). Thus, within Realistic Egalitarianism, surplus wealth will be used to provide
sufficiency for the people below the minimum threshold, simply because of its pragmatic
strength of preventing poverty - hence harm -, therewith adhering to the Rescue Principle of
Scanlon.
The second reason for redistributing wealth is grounded by the writings of ethics professor
Thomas Pogge (1953). According to Pogge, there is a direct relationship between the deprivation
of the least well-off and the wealth of the richest, as “the worse-off are not merely poor and often
starving, but are being impoverished and starved under our shared institutional arrangements,
which inescapably shape their lives”. Pogge has listed certain conditions that prove that this is
currently happening, for instance when the well-off “enjoy significant advantages in the use of
a single natural resource base from whose benefits the worse-off are largely, and without
compensation, excluded”. This condition relates with what this paper has already shown, as
many of the extreme rich can only be so rich because of the economic deprivation of the least
well-off. For example, think back of the humanitarian implications of inequality, where the rich
benefit from low wages in poor countries, or think about how climate change is largely caused
by the well-off. Pogge argues that this negative contribution can invoke both the positive duty
to “help persons in acute distress” and the negative duty “not to contribute to or profit from the
unjust impoverishment of others” (66). Concluding from this, when accepting Pogge’s
reasoning and thus accepting the duties that the well-off have, we have a valid legitimation for
the redistribution of surplus wealth, as by doing so the well-off fulfil their (moral) duties
towards the least well-off.

7 If interested, one can calculate her or his own global footprint via this website:
http://www.footprintcalculator.org/. This website also contains more useful information related
to humankind’s usage of the earth’s resources.

21
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

THE FEASIBLITY AND DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTIONS


Concluding from the previous paragraph, Realistic Egalitarianism can be defended by three
arguments. Firstly, while extreme inequality is bad, inequality itself is not, which justifies a
limited version of a free market economy. Secondly, due to the severe implications of extreme
wealth inequality, limiting wealth is justified. And thirdly, as the deprivation of the least well-
off is directly related to the wealth of the richest, redistribution of surplus wealth is justified.
However, one might say that even though the model can be morally justified, the practical
feasibility of redistributing wealth in form of money might be low, considering the results of
existing global aid programs. Let me call this the Feasibility Objection. For example, an important
paper on the effects of aid showed that there is no correlation between “aid inflows into a
country and its economic growth”. The researchers also found “no evidence that aid works
better in better policy or geographical environments, or that certain forms of aid work better
than others”. They concluded their paper by stating that “the findings suggest that for aid to be
effective in the future, the aid apparatus will have to be rethought” (67). Another study showed
more positive results, but also pointed out that if aid has a positive effect, the effect is modest
(68). Thus, one might indeed doubt if solely redistributing the surplus wealth to the poor is an
effective way of implementing Realistic Egalitarianism.
My response to this objection is that I partly agree, as we should indeed be very critical of the
effectivity of aid. However, within Realistic Egalitarianism, the redistribution of wealth should
not only be limited to just giving money to the people below the minimum threshold. It should
as well, as there is strong proof that aid will always improve and save at least some lives (69),
but at the same time, the process of redistributing is not that single-sided. Instead, a less inequal
world rather would require large reforms of global and systematic structures, just as philosophy
professor Allan Buchanan (1948) argued: “because the distributional effects of a basic structure
are profound and enduring, [global] justice requires systematic principles that are applied to the
basic structure, not merely principles of aid to be applied by individuals, whether the
individuals be persons or particular societies” (70). Therefore, to create a fair and realistic
redistribution, we could consider existing models that aim to be an improvement or replacement
of aid, such as Pogge’s Global Resources Dividend model (GRD). In his model, Pogge proposed
that nations would need to pay a dividend, or a tax, on any of the resources that they use or sell.
He calculated that a dividend of just 1% could raise 300 billion dollars each year, an amount that
could be used to offer each individual in the poorest regions on earth a subsistence minimum of
250 dollars (66). Another more moderate proposal is to require large companies to pay their
(low-skilled) workers a higher salary, as research has shown that this can decrease poverty and

22
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

therefore could create sufficiency8 (71). This might make end-products more expensive, but
considering the wealth of the buyers in for instance Europe or the US, this should not
compromise the sufficiency level of those consumers.
Just as aid, changes like raising minimum wages in poorer countries or more ambitious
proposals such as the GRD model are instruments for redistributing wealth, but can be much
more effective than just giving money. As Pogge stated about his GRD proposal, measures that
change the way the system works “require only one — albeit [a] rather more far-reaching —
political decision”, instead of the “national measures of development aid and environmental
protection” that require to be constantly “politically fought for or defended year after year” (66).
One might object that such changes are infeasible as well, as there are no global governance
institutions capable of implementing such changes. However, by using Buchanan’s reasoning
again, this can also be counterargued 9. According to Buchanan, it is wrong to assume that
“principles of justice have no useful role to play prior to the point at which they can be
successfully implemented”. They do, as before fully implementing them, they can “play a role in
helping us to determine what sorts of institutions we need to build in order to be able to achieve
justice”. Additionally, Buchanan claimed that “one should not assume that the ‘successful
implementation’ of principles of justice requires that they be perfectly satisfied” (70). Thus, even
though Realistic Egalitarianism (probably) might not be implemented from one day to the next,
its mere existence and acknowledgement can in itself help us reach a more just world with less
inequality.
Another objection that one might raise is that Realistic Egalitarianism is too demanding for
the well-off in the world. After all, to belong to the richest 1% of the world, one would need to
earn a yearly income of 30.250 euros or more, which would for example include many people
in Western Europe. How politically achievable is asking an average European citizen to limit
her or his wealth? Let me call this the Demandingness Objection.
It is indeed true that it will be very difficult to literally start taking money from the average
European citizen. Also, even though it might be a small percentage, one can claim that they
already participate in improving other people’s lives by paying taxes, as a part of that money is
also spent on the least well-off. However, when considering Pogge’s reasoning once more, the

8 Caution has to be taken when raising minimum wages, as it has been shown that the success
of decreasing poverty by doing so depends on several conditions. Therefore, when considering
such a proposal, these conditions should be taken into account. For more details about these
conditions, one can review the report by IZA (71).
9 The objection is derived from an objection to Buchanan’s own reasoning in his article Rawls's

Law of Peoples: Rules for a Vanished Westphalian World (70), in which he argues against Rawls’s
Law of Peoples. However, the objection is also applicable to Realistic Egalitarianism, ergo the
counterargument.

23
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

well-off would not only have a positive duty of helping, but also a negative duty of non-
participation in the processes that can cause suffering (66). Therefore, Realistic Egalitarianism
requires two important commitments if the model wants to be successful.
The first commitment, education, consists of two main points. Firstly, there should be more
education focussed on the relation between individual behaviour, such as buying a 5 euro
Primark T-shirt, and the potential effects of doing so. Without knowledge of the exploitative
aspect of the operations by Primark10, one would have no reason to think about changing her or
his behaviour. Secondly, if we want the acquired knowledge of consumption effects to actually
change people’s behaviour, there should be a high focus on empathy development. This is
grounded in the thinking of social philosopher Roman Krznaric, who stated that “empathy is
about stepping outside yourself”, which can bring “an interest in human rights and social
justice”. According to Krznaric, people with high levels of cognitive empathy – perspective-taking
empathy – are more likely to act on injustice (72). Thus, if people want to change their behaviour
that might harm other people, a greater level of empathy can make such change possible.
To see how empathy development can work in practice, we might consider the concept of
Sentimental Education by Rorty, which can, according to Rorty, increase the visibility of
similarities between different people. The main question within Sentimental Education is how
empathy and compassion can encourage people to show affection towards strangers who are
not kin to oneself, or even whose habits one might find disgusting. Rorty argues that the answer
lies not in the (traditional) response that we should care because we belong to the same species,
but rather because we should imagine how it would be to be in her or his situation, or, more
specifically, envision a situation in which “she might become your daughter in law” or because
“her mother would grieve for her”. Rorty suggests that the best way of doing so is not to focus
on the presence of ‘a special added ingredient’ or ‘a sense of moral obligation’ that all humans
possess (as Plato and Kant did), but rather by for instance reading novels that put oneself in the
shoes of the other, such as Uncle Tom’s Cabin. According to Rorty, “such stories, repeated and
varied over the centuries, have induced us, the rich, safe powerful people, to tolerate and even
to cherish powerless people” (73).
I do believe in such forms of moral (or sentimental) development, which is aptly manifested
by Mandela, a person who used empathy and compassion to institute great changes. He
described the following in his autobiography A Long walk to Freedom (74):

“Whereas my father once told stories of historic battles and heroic Xhosa warriors, my mother
would enchant us with Xhosa legends and fables that had come down from numberless

10Among several other scandals, Primark has been shown to use child labouring in Indian
refugee camps to produce its cheap clothes (80).

24
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

generations. These tales stimulated my childish imagination, and usually contained some moral
lesson. I recall one story my mother told us about a traveller who was approached by an old
woman with terrible cataracts on her eyes. The woman asked the traveller for help, and the man
averted his eyes. Then another man came along and was approached by the old woman. She asked
him to clean her eyes, and even though he found the task unpleasant, he did as she asked. Then,
miraculously, the scales fell from the old woman’s eyes and she became young and beautiful. The
man married her and became wealthy and prosperous. It is a simple tale, but its message is an
enduring one: virtue and generosity will be rewarded in ways that one cannot know”. (Mandela,
p42, 1994)

This simple but accurate example shows how literature and other mechanisms can indeed help
develop empathy, and can thus create compassion for people who are very different from
ourselves.
Concluding from all this, a person who is educated in the effects of certain forms of
consumption and is likewise encouraged to develop empathy, is less likely to participate in
harmful consumption behaviour. After all, if you would not only learn about the effects of
buying that T-shirt from Primark, but also embolden your capacity to think of yourself working
in such bad working conditions, you are more likely to change your consumption behaviour.
The same goes for eating a McDonalds burger from which you know that many of the employees
who helped to produce that burger are extremely poorly paid (75), or fuelling your car at Shell
while being aware of Shell’s participation in human rights violations (41), or buying that Huawei
phone from which you are aware that the Chinese workers who developed that phone got sick
from toxic gasses in the production facilities (76).
However, even if empathy and consumption knowledge would be increased, it is still quite
demanding to require people to buy a 50 euro fair-trade T-shirt instead of a normal 5 euro T-
shirt. As a result of this, the second commitment within Realistic Egalitarianism is aimed at the
governmental level, which relates to the counterarguments of the Feasibility Objection. On the
one hand, governments should be much stricter on following guidelines about safe-working
conditions. They could, for example, oblige companies to participate in fair-trade labels, instead
of leaving it as a voluntary choice. On the other hand, governments should be more committed
to support fair-trade and ecological companies that develop clothes, food and other products in
humanitarian conditions. Both measures would reduce prices of products that did not enlarge
inequality, and raise prices of products that did. Combined with the first commitment of
Realistic Egalitarianism, this can actually realise the negative duty of Pogge, and would
therefore make the redistribution of wealth more realistic, as it does not only redistribute
surplus wealth, but also aims to stop inequality-reinforcing consumer behaviour.

25
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

CONCLUSION

T rying to apply just one of the existing principles of Distributive Justice to arrange a more
equal and just world has turned out not to be enough. If only Sufficientarianism is applied,
the extreme wealth that can emerge after reaching a minimum level will jeopardize sufficiency
and can cause harm in many ways. If only Limitarianism is applied, many people will still
continue to live below a bearable minimum level and will not have the chance to a proper life
prospect. And if the first principle would solely be applied on a local level, it will not only
jeopardize sufficiency, but can even cause direct harm. For instance, when Sufficientarianism
would be fully implemented in Western Europe, the European resource-usage – especially of
those most well-off - will (still) have a big effect on climate change and can therefore harm the
least well-off who are not equipped with the protection of a bare minimum.
Following on this, if we want at least some of the Egalitarian goals to be reached for all
humans, both principles have to be combined; on a global level to be precise. Therefore, I have
argued for a new principle of Distributive Justice called Realistic Egalitarianism that tries to fix
the problems listed above. The general aim of Realistic Egalitarianism is to be of moral guidance
for new global policies, but also to be an actual contender for existing global structures. At the
same time, the principle does not only consider large, overarching changes, but also addresses
individual consumer behaviour that can affect and even reinforce extreme inequality.
I have grounded the arguments for Realistic Egalitarianism in the existing principles of
Egalitarianism, Sufficientarianism and Limitarianism, and also by acknowledging the severe
harmful implications of extreme inequality. After all, it has become clear in this paper that
extreme inequality is directly harming people all over the world and that it will continue to do
so if no intervention is made.
To evaluate the strength of Realistic Egalitarianism, I discussed the possible Feasibility and
Demandingness objections against this principle. I counter-argued the first objection by
determining how redistribution within Realistic Egalitarianism should take place; not by merely
redistributing money (i.e. foreign aid), but by making larger changes to the global system of
distribution. Some examples of these changes that I have given are forced higher wages for the
least well-off or existing models for a fairer redistribution, such as Pogge’s GRD model.
I argued against the second objection by explaining how education and empathy
development are important pillars within Realistic Egalitarianism, which would make changes
in individual consumer behaviour possible. Only by creating awareness on how individual
well-off people are influencing inequality, while simultaneously trying to enforce empathy via
education, a real change can be made. The latter is probably the most important pillar of Realistic
Egalitarianism, as I indeed believe in certain forms of moral (or sentimental) development that
have been so accurately put forward by Richard Rorty.

26
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

At the same time, to help people change their individual behaviour, I have claimed that
governments, on the one hand, should be much stricter towards companies that use exploitative
industries to sell their products, and, on the other hand, be much more supportive towards fair-
trade companies and other institutions that take fair wages, good working conditions and
human rights into consideration. Via this way, Limitarianism can be implemented by not only
taxing surplus-money, but also by redistributing money via fairer market-mechanisms. Thus,
both consumer attitudes as governmental interventions need to be altered in order to prevent
extreme inequality from increasing.
Even though I think that I have effectively argued against the objections to Realistic
Egalitarianism, there are future considerations left that will need to be addressed. For instance,
the public acceptance of the changes that I have suggested need to be accurately considered, as it
will be a challenge to convince people of the (moral) necessity to create a more equal, global
distribution. Rorty may well have provided a strong direction to focus on – education in moral
development -, but for the current generation it will be hard to change common beliefs. Related
to this, it has to be considered to which extent human-beings are capable of broadening their
empathy to people that are physically and mentally far away from them. Even though that
certain forms of education will be of help, it has to be taken into account that one may always
care more for the people that are closest to her or him. For instance, an often-heard argument
for not spending more tax-money on aid to other countries is that “we should help the people
in our own country first”, a line that is often repeated by the popular Dutch right-wing leader
Geert Wilders (77). This is an important concern, as even in the Netherlands - one of the richest
countries in the world - long-term poverty is increasing, which makes such a claim an
understandable appeal. However, in the Netherlands, one is considered to be in poverty when
she or he has an income of 1.030 euro or less per month (78), which is still a significant amount
of money compared to the incomes in other parts of the world. How do we accurately focus on
different forms of global injustice, while we prevent regional feelings of injustice when trying
to reach a more just world?
At the same time, the question of which minimum and maximum thresholds to use is one of
the most important and difficult questions to be answered. As described in Part II, there already
have been attempts to create specific minimum thresholds, but to actually bring these ideas intro
practice is a challenging task. After all, in the introduction we have seen how the existing
‘poverty line’ does not seem very realistic to offer a decent life prospect. On the other hand,
when the bar for the minimum threshold is put too high, the feasibility might be jeopardized.
And from the other perspective, which goes back to the first future consideration, a very low
bar for limiting wealth might by hard to justify to the public, taking the fact into account that
many people in for instance Europe belong to the richest 1% of the world. Thus, effective
research on both the minimum and maximum threshold is highly necessary.

27
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

While keeping such future questions in mind, the final goal of the principle of Realistic
Egalitarianism is to tackle extreme global inequalities, by redistributing wealth via changes in
global structures and specific interventional methods. I believe that only via this way we are
capable of improving the lives of many people living below bearable minimum thresholds. As
Mandela has stated, we are not allowed to rest before poverty, injustice and gross inequality
have been eliminated, as we are capable of actions that can indeed change and prevent such
phenomena. Because of this, we need to take Pogge’s negative duty and positive duty of helping
those of in need very seriously. Realistic Egalitarianism can be the key to feasible initiatives that
can mobilize those duties.

28
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

BIBLIOGRAPHY
1. Alvaredo, Facundo, et al. World Inequality Report. WID. [Online] World Inequality Lab, 2018. [Cited: 7 April 2018.]
http://wir2018.wid.world/files/download/wir2018-summary-english.pdf.

2. Metcalf, Tom and Witzig, Jack. World's Wealthiest Became $1 Trillion Richer in 2017. Bloomberg. [Online] 27
December 2017. [Cited: 7 April 2018.] https://www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2017-12-27/world-s-wealthiest-gain-
1-trillion-in-17-on-market-exuberance.

3. Kooiman, Joris. De rijken werden zo’n 1.000 miljard rijker in 2017. NRC.nl. [Online] 27 December 2017. [Cited: 7
April 2018.] https://www.nrc.nl/nieuws/2017/12/27/de-rijken-werden-zon-1000-miljard-rijker-in-2017-a1586306.

4. Pimentel, Diego Alejo Vázquez, Aymar, Iñigo Macías and Lawson, Max. Reward Work, Not Wealth. Oxfam.
[Online] 2018. [Cited: 7 April 2018.] https://www.oxfam.org/sites/www.oxfam.org/files/file_attachments/bp-reward-
work-not-wealth-220118-en.pdf.

5. Vandemoortele, Jan. Are we really reducing global poverty? Worldbank. [Online] 2002. [Cited: 8 April 2018.]
http://web.worldbank.org/archive/website00801/WEB/PDF/ARE_WE_R.PDF.

6. Vincent, James. World's first trillionaire is alive today. The Independent. [Online] 6 May 2014. [Cited: 7 April 2018.]
https://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/worlds-first-trillionaire-is-alive-today-9326532.html.

7. Forbes. Jeff Bezos. Forbes. [Online] 2018. [Cited: 7 April 2018.] https://www.forbes.com/profile/jeff-bezos/.

8. Hardoon, Deborah. An economy for the 99%. Oxfam. [Online] 2017. [Cited: 7 April 2018.]
https://www.oxfam.org/sites/www.oxfam.org/files/file_attachments/bp-economy-for-99-percent-160117-
en.pdf?cid=aff_affwd_donate_id78888&awc=5991_1512988629_160de80d90809b3c5275391e26594cac.

9. Kurt, Daniel. Are You in the Top One Percent of the World? Investopedia. [Online] 2 February 2018. [Cited: 8 April
2018.] https://www.investopedia.com/articles/personal-finance/050615/are-you-top-one-percent-world.asp.

10. World Bank. Taking on Inequality. The World Bank. [Online] 2016. [Cited: 7 April 2018.]
https://openknowledge.worldbank.org/bitstream/handle/10986/25078/9781464809583.pdf.

11. —. While Poverty in Africa Has Declined, Number of Poor Has Increased. The World Bank. [Online] March 2016.
[Cited: 7 April 2018.] http://www.worldbank.org/en/region/afr/publication/poverty-rising-africa-poverty-report.

12. Fox Business. How Much is a Trillion dollars? What a Trillion Can Buy. Fox Business. [Online] 6 March 2016. [Cited:
7 April 2018.] https://www.foxbusiness.com/features/how-much-is-a-trillion-dollars-what-a-trillion-can-buy.

13. Mandela, Nelson. In full: Mandela's poverty speech. BBC News. [Online] 2005. [Cited: 7 April 2018.]
http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/uk_news/politics/4232603.stm.

14. Ferrer-i-Carbonell, Ada and Ramos, Xavier. Inequality and Happiness: A Survey. GINI. [Online] May 2012. [Cited:
13 April 2018.] http://www.gini-research.org/system/uploads/374/original/DP_38_-_Ferrer-i-Carbonell_Ramos.pdf.

15. Messias, Erick, Eaton, William W. and Grooms, Amy N. Income inequality and depression prevalence across the
United States: An ecological study. Johns Hopkins University. [Online] Bloomberg School of Public Health, Jule 2011.
[Cited: 13 April 2018.] https://jhu.pure.elsevier.com/en/publications/income-inequality-and-depression-prevalence-
across-the-united-sta-3.

16. Buttrick, Nicholas R. and Oishi, Shigehiro. The psychological consequences of income inequality. Social and
Personality Psychology Compass. [Online] Wiley Online Library, 8 March 2017. [Cited: 13 April 2018.]
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1111/spc3.12304.

29
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

17. Wilkinson, Richard and Pickett, Kate. How Inequality Endangers Our Mental Health. Inequality.org. [Online] 2017 4
2017. [Cited: 13 April 2018.] https://inequality.org/research/inequality-endangers-mental-health/.

18. Dorling, Danny. How the super rich got richer: 10 shocking facts about inequality. The Guardian. [Online] 14
September 2014. [Cited: 13 April 2018.] https://www.theguardian.com/society/2014/sep/15/how-super-rich-got-richer-
10-shocking-facts-inequality.

19. Goleman, Daniel. Rich People Just Care Less. The New York Times. [Online] 5 October 2013. [Cited: 13 April 2018.]
https://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2013/10/05/rich-people-just-care-less/.

20. Senate approves most drastic changes to US tax code in 30 years. The Guardian. [Online] 20 December 2017. [Cited:
13 April 2018.] https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2017/dec/19/donald-trump-tax-bill-plan-house-approves-
senate.

21. Alexander, Dan. President Trump Could Save $11 Million A Year From New Tax Bill. Forbes. [Online] 18 December
2017. [Cited: 16 April 2018.] https://www.forbes.com/sites/danalexander/2017/12/18/president-trump-could-save-11-
million-a-year-from-new-tax-bill/#81256e72337b.

22. Salter, Lamar. Here are all the big banks that paid Hillary Clinton for speeches in 2013. Business Insider. [Online] 26
May 2016. [Cited: 14 April 2018.] http://www.businessinsider.com/big-banks-paid-hillary-clinton-speeches-bernie-
sanders-2016-5?international=true&r=US&IR=T.

23. BBC News. Clinton: Half of Trump supporters 'basket of deplorables'. BBC News. [Online] 10 September 2016.
http://www.bbc.com/news/av/election-us-2016-37329812/clinton-half-of-trump-supporters-basket-of-deplorables.

24. The Washington Post. How much money is behind each campaign? The Washington Post. [Online] 31 December
2016. [Cited: 16 April 2018.] https://www.washingtonpost.com/graphics/politics/2016-election/campaign-finance/.

25. Sanders, Bernie. On the Issues. Bernie Sanders. [Online] 2018. [Cited: 16 April 2018.]
https://berniesanders.com/issues/.

26. Pavli, Darian. Berlusconi’s Chilling Effect on Italian Media. Open Society Foundations. [Online] 30 March 2010.
[Cited: 14 April 2018.] https://www.opensocietyfoundations.org/voices/berlusconi-s-chilling-effect-italian-media.

27. Hooper, John. Silvio Berlusconi's media reach. The Guardian. [Online] 8 November 2010. [Cited: 17 April 2018.]
https://www.theguardian.com/media/2010/nov/08/silvio-berlusconi-media.

28. Christiano, Thomas. Money in politics. The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy. [Online] Oxford University
Press, 2012. [Cited: 14 April 2018.] https://philpapers.org/rec/CHRMIP-2.

29. Elgar, Frank. Inequality And The Dark Side Of Politics. Huffington Post. [Online] 17 March 2017. [Cited: 14 April
2018.] https://www.huffingtonpost.ca/frank-elgar/inequality-in-politics_b_15427678.html.

30. Welch, Craig. Why Cape Town Is Running Out of Water, and Who’s Next. National Geopgrahic. [Online] 5 March
2018. [Cited: 14 April 2018.] https://news.nationalgeographic.com/2018/02/cape-town-running-out-of-water-drought-
taps-shutoff-other-cities/.

31. Powell, Anita. Cape Town Water Crisis Highlights Deep-Running Inequality. VOA News. [Online] 20 February
2018. [Cited: 14 April 2018.] https://www.voanews.com/a/south-africa-cape-town-water-crisis/4262500.html.

32. Janssen, Bram. 'Day Zero': What Cape Town's water crisis says about inequality. USA Today. [Online] 3 February
2018. [Cited: 14 April 2018.] https://www.usatoday.com/story/news/world/2018/02/03/day-zero-what-cape-towns-
water-crisis-inequality-south-africa/303542002/.

33. Cities around the world should prepare for running out of water, experts say. CNBC. [Online] 11 April 2018.
[Cited: 14 April 2018.] https://www.cnbc.com/2018/04/11/cape-town-water-crisis-cities-should-prepare-for-water-
scarcity.html.

30
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

34. BBC News. The 11 cities most likely to run out of drinking water - like Cape Town. BBC News. [Online] 11
February 2018. [Cited: 14 April 2018.] http://www.bbc.com/news/world-42982959.

35. Mead, Nick van and Kommenda, Niko. Living on the edge: São Paulo’s inequality mapped. The Guardian. [Online]
27 November 217. [Cited: 19 April 2018.] https://www.theguardian.com/cities/ng-interactive/2017/nov/27/living-edge-
sao-paulo-inequality-mapped.

36. Ranade, Ajit. How unequal are we? Bangalore Mirror. [Online] 3 December 2016. [Cited: 19 April 2018.]
http://bangaloremirror.indiatimes.com/opinion/views/how-unequal-are-we/articleshow/55757544.cms.

37. Ma, Jing, et al. Inequality in Beijing: A Spatial Multilevel Analysis of Perceived Environmental Hazard and Self-
Rated Health. Annals of the American Association of Geographers. [Online] Taylor & Francis Online, 30 September 2016.
[Cited: 19 April 2018.] https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/24694452.2016.1224636.

38. Pile, Time. The good, bad and ugly sides to Dubai. Post Magazine. [Online] 5 January 2017. [Cited: 14 April 2018.]
http://www.scmp.com/magazines/post-magazine/travel/article/2058979/good-bad-and-ugly-sides-dubai.

39. International Labour Organization. Marking Progress Against Child Labour. International Labour Office. [Online]
2013. [Cited: 17 April 2018.] http://www.ilo.org/wcmsp5/groups/public/---ed_norm/---
ipec/documents/publication/wcms_221513.pdf.

40. Moulds, Josephine. Child labour in the fashion supply chain. The Guardian. [Online] UNICEF, 2013. [Cited: 17 April
2018.] https://labs.theguardian.com/unicef-child-labour/.

41. Amnesty International. A Criminal Enterprise? Shell's Involvement in Human Rights Violations in Nigeria in the
1990's. Amnesty. [Online] 2017. [Cited: 26 April 2018.] https://www.amnesty.nl/content/uploads/2017/11/A-criminal-
enterprise.pdf?x56589.

42. Lamont, Julian. Distributive Justice. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. [Online] 22 September 1996. [Cited: 14 April
2018.] https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-distributive/.

43. Arneson, Richard. Egalitarianism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. [Online] 16 August 2002. [Cited: 14 April
2018.] https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/egalitarianism/.

44. —. Equality of Opportunity. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. [Online] 8 October 2002. [Cited: 14 April 2018.]
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/equal-opportunity/.

45. Navin, Mark. Equality of opportunity. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. [Online] 2017. [Cited: 14 April 2018.]
https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/equality-of-opportunity/v-1.

46. Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Harvard University Press. [Online] 1971. [Cited: 14 April 2018.] Page 73.
http://www.consiglio.regione.campania.it/cms/CM_PORTALE_CRC/servlet/Docs?dir=docs_biblio&file=BiblioContenu
to_3641.pdf.

47. Scanlon, T.M. Equality of Opportunity: A Normative Anatomy. NYU Law. [Online] December 2013. [Cited: 14
April 2018.] Page 2-4.
http://www.law.nyu.edu/sites/default/files/upload_documents/Scanlon%20Equality%20of%20Opportunity%20NYU3.
pdf.

48. Frankfurt, Harry. Equality as a Moral Ideal. Ethics. [Online] The University of Chicago Press, October 1987. [Cited:
19 April 2018.] Page 1-2.
https://www.law.upenn.edu/institutes/cerl/conferences/prioritarianism_papers/Session3Frankfurt.pdf.

49. Popper, Karl. The Open Society and its Enemies. George Routledge & Sons, LTD. [Online] 1943. [Cited: 19 April
2018.] Page 570-71.
https://monoskop.org/images/4/42/Popper_Karl_The_Open_Society_and_its_Enemies_The_Spell_of_Plato_Vol_1_1st_
ed.pdf.

31
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

50. Casal, Paula. Why Sufficiency Is Not Enough. Ethics. [Online] The University of Chicago Press, 2007. [Cited: 19
April 2018.] Page 297-299. https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/abs/10.1086/510692.

51. Universitat Bayreuth. Sufficientarianism – Can Justice Get Enough? PhilEvents. [Online] 2015. [Cited: 21 April
2018.] https://philevents.org/event/show/17803.

52. Saxena, Richa. Amartya Sen: A Biography. Rajpal & Sons. [Online] 1 January 2011. [Cited: 21 April 2018.] Page 143.
https://goo.gl/Bqyvnb.

53. Anderson, Elizabeth. Fair Opportunity in Education: A Democratic Equality Perspective. Ethics 117. [Online] The
University of Chicago, July 2007. [Cited: 21 April 2018.] http://www.mit.edu/~shaslang/mprg/AndersonFOE.pdf.

54. Frankfurt, Harry. Equality as a Moral Ideal. Ethics. [Online] The University of Chicago Press, October 1987. [Cited:
19 April 2018.] Page 38-39.
https://www.law.upenn.edu/institutes/cerl/conferences/prioritarianism_papers/Session3Frankfurt.pdf.

55. Studebaker, Benjamin. Why the Welfare State? Benjamin Studebaker. [Online] 20 November 2012. [Cited: 19 April
2018.] https://benjaminstudebaker.com/2012/11/20/why-the-welfare-state/.

56. McIntyre, Niamh. Which countries are the most (and least) committed to reducing inequality? The Guardian.
[Online] 17 July 2017. [Cited: 04 19 2018.] https://www.theguardian.com/inequality/datablog/2017/jul/17/which-
countries-most-and-least-committed-to-reducing-inequality-oxfam-dfi.

57. Scanlon, Thomas. What We Owe to Each Other. Harvard University Press. [Online] 1998. [Cited: 19 April 2018.] Page
244. http://www.hup.harvard.edu/catalog.php?isbn=9780674004238&content=reviews.

58. Robeyns, Ingrid. Having Too Much. SSRN. [Online] 22 February 2016. [Cited: 20 April 2018.]
https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2736094.

59. Scanlon, T. M. The 4 biggest reasons why inequality is bad for society. Ted Ideas. [Online] TED, 3 June 2014. [Cited:
26 April 2018.] https://ideas.ted.com/the-4-biggest-reasons-why-inequality-is-bad-for-society/.

60. Rorty, Richard. Achieving our Country. Harvard University Press. [Online] 1997. [Cited: 26 April 2018.] Page 47.
http://www.hup.harvard.edu/catalog.php?isbn=9780674003125.

61. Carey, John. The 9 limits of our planet … and how we’ve raced past 4 of them. Ted Ideas. [Online] TED, 5 March
2015. [Cited: 26 April 2018.] https://ideas.ted.com/the-9-limits-of-our-planet-and-how-weve-raced-past-4-of-them/.

62. Loh, Jonathan and Wackernagel, Mathis. Living Planet Report 2004. WWF. [Online] World Wildlife Fund, 2004.
[Cited: 3 May 2018.] http://www.panda.org/downloads/general/lpr2004.pdf.

63. Juffermans, Jan. Nut & Noodzaak van de Mondiale Voetafdruk. Lemniscaat. [Online] 2006. [Cited: 3 May 2018.]
http://www.janjuffermans.nl/publicaties/boekvoetafdruk.pdf.

64. The Economist. Climate change and inequality. The Economist. [Online] 13 July 2017. [Cited: 26 April 2018.]
https://www.economist.com/news/finance-and-economics/21725009-rich-pollute-poor-suffer-climate-change-and-
inequality.

65. Parijs, Philippe van. A Capitalist Road to Communism. Basic Income Studies. [Online] June 2006. [Cited: 25 April
2018.] https://www.researchgate.net/publication/24015173_A_Capitalist_Road_to_Communism/.

66. Pogge, Thomas. Eradicating Systemic Poverty: Brief for a global resources dividend. University of Essex. [Online]
Journal of Human Development, 2001. [Cited: 27 April 2018.] http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/14649880120050246.

67. Rajan, Raghuram G. and Subramanian, Arvind. Aid and Growth: What Does the Cross-Country Evidence Really
Show? The Review of Economics and Statistics. [Online] MIT Press, 2008. [Cited: 29 April 2018.]
https://piie.com/publications/papers/subramanian0707.pdf.

32
A PRAGMATIC APPROACH OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE

68. Sumner, Andy. The $138.5 Billion Question: When Does Foreign Aid Work? Center for Global Development. [Online]
12 September 2014. [Cited: 29 April 2018.] https://www.cgdev.org/blog/1385-billion-question-when-does-foreign-aid-
work.

69. Oxfam. Does aid work? Oxfam International. [Online] Health and Education For All Campaign, 28 April 2010.
[Cited: 1 May 2018.] https://www.oxfam.org/en/multimedia/video/2010-does-aid-work.

70. Buchanan, Allan. Rawls's Law of Peoples: Rules for a Vanished Westphalian World. Ethics. [Online] The University
of Chicago Press, Jule 2000. [Cited: 2 May 2018.] Page 710-711.
http://philosophyfaculty.ucsd.edu/faculty/rarneson/phil267fa12/Required%20readings/Week%202/AllenBuchananON
Rawls.pdf.

71. Gindling, T. H. Does increasing the minimum wage reduce poverty in developing countries? IZA - World of Labor.
[Online] University of Maryland Baltimore County, May 2014. [Cited: 1 May 2018.] https://wol.iza.org/articles/does-
increasing-the-minimum-wage-reduce-poverty-in-developing-countries/long.

72. Delaney, Brigid. Philosopher Roman Krznaric: 'we are in more urgent need of empathy than ever before'. The
Guardian. [Online] 19 February 2016. [Cited: 1 May 2018.] https://www.theguardian.com/books/2016/feb/19/empathy-
expert-roman-krznaric-on-shifting-away-from-20th-century-individualism.

73. Rorty, Richard. Human Rights, Rationality, and Sentimentality. Truth and Progress. [Online] Stanford University,
1998. [Cited: 5 May 2018.] Page 133-134. http://ieas.unideb.hu/admin/file_6249.pdf.

74. Mandela, Nelson. A Long Walk To Freedom. Little Brown & Co. [Online] 1994. [Cited: 16 May 2018.] Page 42.
https://goo.gl/JLojSn.

75. Wong, Julia Carrie. You want fries with your poverty wages and exploited McDonald's workers? The Guardian.
[Online] 15 May 2014. [Cited: 5 May 2018.] https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2014/may/15/poverty-
wages-exploited-workers-mcdonalds-protests.

76. How China is Screwing Over Its Poisoned Factory Workers. Wired. [Online] 4 June 2015. [Cited: 5 May 2018.]
https://www.wired.com/2015/04/inside-chinese-factories/.

77. den Hartog, Tobias and van Soest, Hans. 'Ik kies voor eigen land eerst, dat is politiek'. Algemeen Dagblad. [Online] 5
November 2016. [Cited: 18 June 2018.] https://www.ad.nl/nieuws/ik-kies-voor-eigen-land-eerst-dat-is-
politiek~ae1cab1f/.

78. Vriesema, Ingmar. Langdurige armoede neemt toe. NRC. [Online] 17 Janury 2018. [Cited: 24 May 2018.]
https://www.nrc.nl/nieuws/2018/01/17/langdurige-armoede-neemt-toe-a1588651.

79. Dowdey, Sarah. How Dubai Works. How Stuff Works. [Online] 5 November 2007. [Cited: 14 April 2018.]
https://adventure.howstuffworks.com/dubai-uae3.htm.

80. Mehta, Seema, et al. Who gives money to Bernie Sanders? Los Angeles Times . [Online] 3 June 2016. [Cited: 16 April
2018.] http://www.latimes.com/projects/la-na-pol-sanders-donors/ .

81. McDougall, Dan. The hidden face of Primark fashion. The Guardian. [Online] 22 June 2008. [Cited: 1 May 2018.]
https://www.theguardian.com/world/2008/jun/22/india.humanrights.

82. Data 360. Average Water Usage Per Person Per Day. Data 360. [Online] 2014. [Cited: 19 April 2018.]
http://www.data360.org/dsg.aspx?Data_Set_Group_Id=757.

83. Thrush, Glenn. Trump Signs Order to Require Recipients of Federal Aid Programs to Work. The New York Times.
[Online] 10 April 2018. [Cited: 6 May 2018.] https://www.nytimes.com/2018/04/10/us/trump-work-requirements-
assistance-programs.html.

33

View publication stats

You might also like