You are on page 1of 4

Downloaded from jme.bmj.com on October 20, 2010 - Published by group.bmj.

com

Payment for participation in research: a pursuit


for the poor?
M Stones and J McMillan

J Med Ethics 2010 36: 34-36


doi: 10.1136/jme.2009.030965

Updated information and services can be found at:


http://jme.bmj.com/content/36/1/34.full.html

These include:
References This article cites 13 articles, 4 of which can be accessed free at:
http://jme.bmj.com/content/36/1/34.full.html#ref-list-1

Email alerting Receive free email alerts when new articles cite this article. Sign up in the
service box at the top right corner of the online article.

Notes

To request permissions go to:


http://group.bmj.com/group/rights-licensing/permissions

To order reprints go to:


http://journals.bmj.com/cgi/reprintform

To subscribe to BMJ go to:


http://journals.bmj.com/cgi/ep
Downloaded from jme.bmj.com on October 20, 2010 - Published by group.bmj.com

Research ethics

Payment for participation in research: a pursuit for


the poor?
M Stones,1 J McMillan2
1
Hull York Medical School, ABSTRACT questions about the appropriateness of paying
University of Hull, Hull, UK; Poor people predominate as a subgroup of those who participants, given that they are likely to be receiving
2
School of Medicine, Flinders
University, Adelaide, Australia
take part in healthy volunteer research. They are care at the same time as they are taking part in
subjected to minimised but unknown risks and unpleasant research. We are also not considering research that is
Correspondence to: burdens so that the safety of new medicines can be negligently dangerous, scientifically invalid or other-
Associate Professor J McMillan, evaluated. This is prima facie unfair especially given that wise obviously non-ethical studies such as those
Faculty of Health Sciences, considered by Beecher.6
STURT GENERAL, Flinders the poor are often unable to access expensive medicines.
University, GPO Box 2100, Although participants in this kind of research often do
Adelaide, Australia; john. receive compensation for their time, these payments are
mcmillan@flinders.edu.au INDUCEMENT AND CONSENT
usually capped at a very low level. This paper defends a
Many ethics committees and professional bodies
version of a reimbursement model for the payment of
Received 7 May 2009 warn against payments that might induce research
Revised 22 July 2009 research subjects. This model is practical, would benefit participants into taking part in research because it
Accepted 24 July 2009 those without an income who take part in research, and might encourage them to enrol even if it is contrary
would make it possible for those in regular work to take to their best interests.
part in phase 1 research. In their 1997 paper Wilkinson and Moore2 argue
that the prima facie case for permitting payment
for research participation is that both parties
Poor people predominate as a subgroup of those
benefit from the contract. Researchers offer money
who take part in healthy volunteer research.1 They
to participants for taking part in their research,
are subjected to minimised but unknown risks and
thereby recruiting research participants, whereas
unpleasant burdens so that the safety of new
research participants are made better off by the
medicines can be evaluated. When shown to be
money. In Wertheimer’s terms,7 8 payment for
effective new medicines will be used to combat research participation appears to be a mutually
disease, but access to new medicines is often advantageous transaction in that both parties are
limited to those who can afford them. Successful likely to be made better off. A common objection
medicines grow the coffers of private industry and to this claim is that undue inducements invalidate
their shareholders. Although participants in this informed consent. Some worry that financially
kind of research often do receive compensation for induced participants will not consider the risks
their time these payments are usually capped at a involved carefully and are likely to agree to do
very low level. Given the profits that drug something that they otherwise would not and
companies make and the importance of wealth which might be contrary to their interests.9
for access to many medications, is there a case for However, as Wilkinson and Moore2 point out,
permitting higher levels of payment to those who people often do things for money that they would
take part in this kind of research? otherwise not do, for example unpleasant work.
One common objection to allowing significant Unpleasant work can often be riskier than other
payments for research participation is that they jobs, yet we do not assume that people are
mean that participants are induced into participating rendered incapable of misjudging whether or not
in research. After examining arguments developed by it is in their interests to accept this level of risk.
Wilkinson and Moore,2 3 McNeill4 and Titmuss5 we Nonetheless, when research participants are
will argue that the principal reason to be concerned harmed it raises important questions about the level
about inducement is because it might result in of risk they agreed to and whether they were
participants being subjected to unacceptable levels adequately informed. In The TeGenero (TGM1412)
of risk. However, rather than not allowing payments incident some healthy volunteers were seriously
to subjects, ethics committees and regulatory agen- injured during a first-in-man study of a biological
cies are more effective ways to ensure that risk is agent.10 Media reports after the event discussed the
minimised and that consent is of the highest quality. levels of payment that these subjects received and
We will argue that payment at levels that might be whether they compromised their understanding of
considered to be ‘‘inducing’’ can be acceptable and the potential side effects.11 The poor level of under-
suggest a suitable model for these payments. standing among research participants is well docu-
It is important to clarify that the type of research mented.12 One important difference between
under discussion here is first-in-man clinical trials payment for research participation and being paid
(phase 1, healthy volunteer). There are a number of for risky employment is that in the latter case the
reasons for this. Phase 1 trials are often the riskiest employee might have a fairly good understanding of
type of trial, largely because much less is known the risks involved and thereby be able to make a
about the effects of the trial medication. Research reasonable judgement about whether or not it is in
involving patients (phases 2, 3 and 4) raises other their interests. The primary reason why many
Downloaded from jme.bmj.com on October 20, 2010 - Published by group.bmj.com

Research ethics

research participants struggle to give adequately informed consent We think that there are some parallels between research
is because the relevant information is so difficult to understand participation and blood donation. To that end it is worth briefly
and in the case of phase 1 trials, which aim at quantifying risk, the reminding ourselves of the arguments of Titmuss in ‘‘The gift
risks are necessarily unknown. relationship: from human blood to social policy’’ (1970).5
Steinbrook13 emphasises that, at least in the UK and USA, the Titmuss5 makes a number of useful and important points. First,
consent process should ensure that participants understand that market-driven systems redistribute blood from the poor to the
there may be certain side effects/injuries and as such are not rich, this is exploitative and unjust. Payment for research
entitled to compensation if they should occur. It is their (the participation will often produce knowledge that is exploited by
research subject’s) responsibility to make their own healthcare pharmaceutical companies for the benefit of shareholders and
provision. In the UK that provision would fall to the National those who can afford the medication, this too appears exploita-
Health Service. No compensation is due although the Association tive. However, there does appear to be an important difference
of the British Pharmaceutical Industry recommend that compen- with research participation: whether or not participants are paid is
sation is provided.13 In France, Germany and Spain clinical trial not likely to have any bearing on whether or not companies,
insurance is mandatory whatever the cause. In our view it seems shareholders and rich patients benefit. In fact, it appears worse
ethically problematical not to provide such protection. Although that participants do not benefit financially when so many others
participants might know that they are signing away their right to can because they are only permitted to act on altruistic motives.
compensation, this seems unfair if they commonly do not Titmuss’s main worry is that a paid market in blood is
understand the risks that they are taking.14 imperialistic and will win out over an altruistic system.
While the general difficulties about participant understanding Margaret Radin16 has developed this line of thinking and argued
would appear to raise serious difficulties for a more permissive that once commodification has taken place and blood has a
approach to payment, we think that there is a solution that is market value it can no longer be seen as a gift but only for its
better than disallowing those who could benefit financially by monetary value. When the blood is no longer seen as a gift, the
taking part in research. In our view, the most morally motivation to give will be lost.
significant question to ask of the TeGenero study is not: did This appears to be, at least partly, an empirical argument and
all participants understand the risks of the study? but rather: evidence is needed really to settle this point. We are sceptical
did those designing and conducting the trial do all that they about whether payment that is inducing but not exhorbitant
could to manage and minimise any potential risks, as well as would actually have this effect. The amount paid for a pint of
ensuring that the level of risk was not unacceptably high? blood is relatively small but enough to encourage the poor to
choose to give. Those who are better off are able to give
independently of the financial incentive as it is relatively
INDUCEMENT AND RISK insignificant to them (their motivations lie elsewhere). We are
Paul McNeill4 gives an account of a moral test that many would not convinced that unpaid purely altruistic and paid blood
find plausible for weighing up whether or not research donation cannot take place in parallel as is the case in the USA.
participation is acceptable. He describes how he gave his However, there is something right about Titmuss’s observation
daughter money while she was travelling in England so as to that altruism may not come naturally and is something to be
persuade her against taking part in a phase 1 trial. Whether or nurtured by the institutions of society. Nonetheless, we remain
not we would be happy for one of our loved ones to take part in unconvinced that this is a reason against payment.
research for money seems like a relevant test for whether or not Many of us have donated blood regularly and are happy to do
we should expect other people to do this. McNeill4 says that she this as long as it is convenient to do so. There are minimal risks
had been unduly influenced to ignore the potential risk of the associated with giving blood and it takes less than half an hour.
study because of the money offered by the trial company. It is The costs to the donor are low and the benefits to society
hard not to empathise with this position: who would not be (which may include the donor or his family) are high.
concerned for the welfare of their child when they were Blood donation in terms of burden may be compared with
desperate for money and touring a foreign country. small-scale research studies in which the demand is not too
Nonetheless, it might be that McNeill4 thinks that the risks great upon time. Many of us will take part in research of this
inherent in trials are higher than they are. kind and be permitted to do so during working hours,
Wells15 summarises compensation claims made using the particularly those of us who work in health care. However,
Association of the British Pharmaceutical Industry compensa- this kind of research demands much less time than some phase 1
tion scheme. Of the 415 000 participants in studies during the research, which requires that people altruistically give up 1, 2 or
period 1990–5, only 21 made claims. In half of the cases claims 3 weeks of their lives. It is hard to imagine any employers giving
were for less than £1000. Although it is possible there have been their workers this amount of time off work or employees giving
additional private claims that were not been picked up by the up their vacation time to do this. It seems impractical and
survey, the numbers are low, which suggests that it is unlikely that anyone would do this unless they are paid. One of
surprisingly rare for people to be harmed during research. If us has visited clinical trials units in the UK, and typically
research is typically not very risky then why should we be volunteers are not in full-time employment, they tend to be
concerned about people being induced by payments? In the next medical students, back-packers taking a year out or unemployed
section we will consider whether there is something different people. Because of the importance of these trials there is a
about the nature of research participation that might make strong argument in favour of payment. To say that payment
payments wrong even when research is not risky. cannot be permitted is to say that these trials cannot run, which
is not something that we should accept.
INDUCEMENT, ALTRUISM AND COMMODIFICATION
It might be that there is something about the nature of research HOW MUCH SHOULD PARTICIPANTS BE PAID?
that is different from work, which makes it unacceptable to be Rhodes17 and Harris18 both argue that we have a moral duty to
paid for the former but not for the latter. take part in clinical research in return for the benefits we receive
Downloaded from jme.bmj.com on October 20, 2010 - Published by group.bmj.com

Research ethics

from previous medical advances that we now enjoy (and future CONCLUSIONS
medicines that we will enjoy from current research). Not to Payment to take part in research should be permitted as it
reciprocate by taking part in research (with all the inherent increases the options and freedom of poor people to make money
risks) is free-riding and unfair. Rhodes17 imagines a jury process and increases the number and variety of potential participants
in which citizens are periodically called upon to take part in available. It may or may not influence the quality of their
trials. They would be given the opportunity to decide what kind informed consent (autonomy) as may other factors. In our view
of trial they take part in, which would allow them to avoid this makes it imperative that risks are fully minimised and
research that they strongly disagreed with. This suggestion is an accounted for but does not constitute a reason to ban payment.
interesting thought experiment but it is very hard to see how Paying research participants is not the same as other kinds of
this could work, particularly in a country such as the UK, work: it has more in common with paid blood donation. The
where, post-Creutzfeldt–Jakob disease, people tend to be very risks in phase 1 research are different because they are not
cautious about reassurances from the state. Given that there are known in advance. However, like work, effort is made to
no significant problems with recruitment to phase 1 trials at mitigate and predict risk and to manage harms if they do occur.
present there does not appear to be any need to move to such a The empirical evidence suggests that approved clinical research
system. If there was a desperate need to recruit research is not that risky, although there have been some high-profile
participants and a pressing need for a particular kind of research, exceptions. When you compare this to very risky jobs such as
this kind of measure might be worth considering, but it does not deep sea diving or being a member of the armed services,
seem relevant to our present situation. What is good about research is not risky enough to justify banning payment.
Rhode’s proposal is that avoids the present injustice in A modified version of the reimbursement model was
recruitment to clinical trials: the burdens of research tend to considered in which the employer rather than the employee
be carried by the poor. While her scheme is unlikely to work we was reimbursed by the study organiser. This compromise allows
believe that there is another fair way to make it possible for for altruistic volunteering in exchange for time off work.
others in society, especially those in full-time employment, to It seems unacceptable that a person in dire circumstances
take part in research. should accept very high levels of payment from a researcher.
There are some good reasons for thinking that it is acceptable However, the bottom line is: could an unscrupulous researcher
to offer payments to research participants but that there should persuade a potential research participant to undertake a
be some upper limit on what is an acceptable level of payment. dangerous study in exchange for a large sum of money? The
Following Dickert and Grady19 we think that a reimbursement answer is no, not unless they were prepared to act illegally. The
model in which participants are paid according to their income bona fide ethics committee would not allow a dangerous study
is appropriate. Participants should be allowed to take paid leave to take place. That said, the ethics committee and regulatory
from work in order to volunteer to take part in research. When agencies are only as good as their component parts, and
the study is carried out by a commercial drug company, the however good are not infallible.
volunteer’s employer could be reimbursed their salary by the Competing interests: None.
drug company. This model has some similarities to those of the
Provenance and peer review: Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.
volunteer Reservist Armed Forces in the UK. Employers are
encouraged to give volunteers paid time off from work. One
initial problem is that this system might mean that those who REFERENCES
1. Elliott C, Abadie R. Exploiting a research underclass in phase 1 clinical trials.
were being given time off work were being paid while the N Engl J Med 2008;358:2316–17.
unemployed were not. Perhaps those who are not in employ- 2. Wilkinson M, Moore A. Inducement in research. Bioethics 1997;11:373–89.
ment could be paid in line with what those who were given 3. Wilkinson M, Moore A. Inducements revisited. Bioethics 1999;13:114–30.
4. McNeill P. Paying people to participate in research: why not? Bioethics
time off work would get, perhaps the unskilled salary. Ideally, 1997;11:390–6.
the appropriate reimbursement would be at a level that the non- 5. Titmuss R. The gift relationship: from human blood to social policy. London: Allen and
economically disadvantaged would consider fair and would be Unwin, 1970.
6. Beecher H. Ethics and clinical research. N Engl J Med 1966;274:1354–60.
prepared to participate in exchange for. This approach also has 7. Wertheimer A. Exploitation. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996.
the potential to reduce inequity between rich and poor taking 8. Wertheimer A. Exploitation in health care. In: Ashcroft R, Dawson A, Draper H,
part in research. Some disadvantages of this model are that the McMillan J, eds. Principles of healthcare ethics. Chichester: John Wiley, 2007.
employer is inconvenienced and costs may be increased to the 9. Faden R, Beauchamp T. A history and theory of informed consent. New York: Oxford
University Press, 1986.
drug company, presumably costs that could be passed on to the 10. Goodyear M. Further lessons from the TGN 1412 tragedy. BMJ 2006;333:270–1.
final purchaser. However, it should be noted that phase 1 trials 11. Stobbard L, Murtagh M, Rapley T, et al. We saw human guinea pigs explode. BMJ
are not a particularly costly part of the drug development 2007;334:566–7.
12. Dawson A. The normative status of the requirement to gain informed consent in
process as numbers of participants are small. clinical trials: comprehension, obligations and empirical evidence. In: Corrigan O,
The participant pay rates should be pro-rata so that McMillan J, Liddell K, Richards M, Weijer C, eds. The limits of consent: a socio-ethical
participants still get paid for their efforts even if they need to approach to human subject research in medicine. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2009.
drop out of a study. Completion bonuses should be small so 13. Steinbrook R. Compensation for injured research subjects. N Engl J Med
that the participant is not induced to mask adverse reactions. 2006;354:1871–3.
It is possible that payment might encourage participants to 14. Dyer O. Payment offered to injured trial participants has strings attached. BMJ
2006;332:990.
mask pre-existing medical conditions in order to gain access to 15. Wells F. Clinical trial compensation. Lancet 1995;346:1164.
studies. However, unpaid participants are also unable to declare 16. Radin M. Contested commodities: the trouble with trade in sex, children body parts,
a pre-existing condition if it were undiagnosed. This should be and other things. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001.
overcome by prestudy screening and access to medical records, 17. Rhodes R. Rethinking research ethics. Am J Bioethics 2005;5:7–28.
18. Harris J. Scientific research is a moral duty. J Med Ethics 2005;31:242–8.
which should also be useful in detecting cases in which people 19. Dickert N, Grady C. What’s the price of a research subject? Approaches to payment
have not mentioned known conditions. for research participation. N Engl J Med 1999;341:198–203.

You might also like