You are on page 1of 16

ANGEL AK I

journal of the theoretical humanities


volume 10 number 1 april 2005

1 introduction
erificationism, in the strictest sense, is the
V doctrine that the truth or falsity of every
cognitively meaningful statement can be decided
by finitely many possible observations. The system
of Carnap’s Aufbau1 is verificationist. It is also
reductionist, and the two characteristics are con-
nected: verificationism implies that any meaning- abraham D. stone
ful statement could in principle be replaced with
a finite set of predictions about possible observa-
tions. What, in Carnap’s opinion, was the point of
this reductionist, verificationist system? A correct THE CONTINENTAL
interpretation of the Aufbau itself obviously ORIGINS OF
requires a satisfactory answer. But the question
also casts long historical shadows in both VERIFICATIONISM
directions.
To take the forward direction first: Carnap, as natorp, husserl and carnap
we all know, was soon to give up on strict on the object as infinitely
verificationism. But that was not the end of its
influence on his thought, and thus on the whole determinable x
development of analytic philosophy of science.
For one thing, even in much later works he
continues to impose a roughly verificationist knowing what he thought he was doing in the
condition on the so-called observation language.2 first place. And to understand that, we need to
Even more importantly, however: his verifica- understand the context in which he was at first
tionist beginnings defined for him the main operating. If we get that wrong, thus placing
problem about scientific progress. If we begin by the Aufbau in the wrong historical context, we
realizing that finite data are not, in principle, will not understand the later works, either. On
enough to decide the truth or falsehood of our Quine’s account, for example, Carnap is placed in
hypotheses, our attention naturally turns to the a (somewhat odd, and predominantly anglo-
problem of induction: namely, the question of how phone) historical sequence which includes
finite data can support statements which they Hume, Bentham, Frege, and Russell.3 Without
fall short of deductively implying. That was indeed going into details: the upshot of this historical
the central problem for later Carnap. Might contextualization is an interpretation in which
other beginnings, however, have focused attention reductionism – replacing suspicious theoretical
elsewhere? concepts with ‘‘innocent’’ observational ones – is
That last question leads from the forward understood to be the goal of the Aufbau, and
historical direction to the backward one. Under- verificationism a means to that end (74–75).
standing Carnap’s later reactions depends on But this leaves it incomprehensible why Carnap

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/05/010129^15 ß 2005 Taylor & Francis and the Editors of Angelaki
DOI: 10.1080/09697250500225800

129
origins of verificationism

is still interested in some form of verificationism be meant by this terminology in Carnap’s histor-
after the strict version fails (77), and moreover ical context. We will see that it can have quite
makes Carnap’s later concern with ‘‘inductive different implications in the mouths of different
logic’’ look like the arbitrary, unmotivated sub- thinkers. Thus although both Natorp and his
stitution of an imaginary logical procedure for our contemporary, Edmund Husserl, describe the
actual psychological process of learning about object of scientific knowledge in these terms,
the world (78). their meaning and motivations are vastly different.
Of course, Quine’s once-standard account has Not to be mysterious: my ultimate contention
now already been discredited in some circles. More will be that, despite Carnap’s explicit claim, in
recent accounts of Carnap’s motivations in the the passage in question, that he is responding to
Aufbau place him against the very different Natorp, his real target is Husserl. I will close,
historical backdrop of Marburg neo-Kantianism.4 therefore, with suggestions as to what it was in
But such an account, whatever its advantages, is Husserl’s system which prompted that attack,
worrying from our point of view because the thus giving rise to Carnap’s long flirtation with
central problems about scientific progress, for the verificationism in its various forms. But first, and
Marburg neo-Kantians, were far removed from for the most part, I will focus on the doctrines
the problem of induction. I will say more about of Husserl and Natorp, respectively.6
that in a moment. For now, though, and again
without going into details: it is not surprising that
II early twentieth-century
these accounts, while making the Aufbau period
quasi-kantian hierarchical systems of
look more interesting, have at the same time
knowledge: two ways to proceed
tended both to de-emphasize the role of verifica-
tionism in that period and to emphasize the German epistemology in the early twentieth
discontinuity between it and what followed. century – the milieu from which Carnap’s early
Perhaps there is such a radical discontinuity. writings emerged – has in general two salient
But we should be cautious, if only because characteristics.
Carnap himself maintained that the project of First, the dominance of Kant, or of self-styled
the Aufbau and his later projects were essentially inheritors and interpreters of Kant. That charac-
the same – namely, that both were concerned with terization applies, of course, to the thinkers
‘‘rational reconstruction.’’5 generally called ‘‘neo-Kantian,’’ including
All this suggests that, if we want to understand Natorp and his fellow Marburgers (most impor-
both the Aufbau and Carnap’s later works, we tantly, Hermann Cohen and Ernst Cassirer), as
ought to take another look at the ‘‘Continental’’ well as the so-called ‘‘Southwest School’’ (espec-
background of his thought, and in particular to ially Wilhelm Windelband and Heinrich Rickert).
look for an aspect of it which raises different issues But the dominance of Kantianism in this period
about scientific progress and provides its own extends well beyond that. In particular, Husserl,
strong motives for verificationism. Here I will try whose roots were in Franz Brentano’s openly
to identify such a background, in a preliminary anti-Kantian thought and who initially felt closer
way, by exploring one particular question: to British empiricism, was by this time also
whether, and in what sense, the object of scientific portraying himself as a Kantian. This was clear
knowledge is an ‘‘infinitely determinable X.’’ in Ideen I,7 with its frequent explicit mentions
This question is relevant because when Carnap, of Kant and heavy use of Kantian terminology.
in the Aufbau, presents verificationism as a It became clearer still in 1924 – one of the years
response to Marburg neo-Kantianism he does so during which, according to Ludwig Landgrebe,
by presenting it, in particular, as a rejection of Carnap participated in Husserl’s advanced
Paul Natorp’s doctrine that the object of scientific seminar.8 In that year Husserl delivered the
knowledge is ‘‘the eternal X,’’ i.e., that ‘‘its memorial address at the Kant-Feier of the
determination is an unfinishable task’’ (x 179L, University of Freiburg, in honor of the 200th
253). It is therefore worth examining what might anniversary of Kant’s birth. At the same time he

130
stone

prepared a version for publication in his Jahrbuch time and place? In the most general terms, it may
für Philosophie und phänomenologische simply have been a matter of philosophical
Forschung.9 The text opens with the statement fashion, though the increasingly complex hier-
that an observation of Kant’s birth is appropriate archy of the modern sciences may also have played
to a phenomenological yearbook because ‘‘in a role. As for the more detailed content of
the principled continuing development which the systems in question, however, there were
phenomenology has received in my life’s work apparently two distinct and independent sources.
[. . .] there has emerged a manifest essential First, and most obvious, is post-Kantian
affinity between that phenomenology and Kant’s idealism, especially Hegel. The well-known
transcendental philosophy.’’ formula ‘‘thesis–antithesis–synthesis,’’ which is
Second, the prevalence of open-ended, stepwise not Hegel’s own, and is in fact even rather
hierarchical systems. Once again, this clearly misleading, is nevertheless accurate in one respect:
applies to the neo-Kantians, especially to the every stage of Hegel’s method is understood
later Marburgers.10 But, once again, it applies by Hegel to involve something like Kantian
also to Husserl’s systems of the Ideen period and synthesis.12 A second, less obvious, source,
later, and, once again, it extends well beyond however, is revived interest in ancient and
that.11 Typically, moreover (including in Natorp medieval doctrines of the orders or modes of
and Husserl), this second characteristic is being. Such interest is perhaps most evident in
presented as a corollary of the first, in that the Brentano and those influenced by him (e.g.,
repeated operation which generates the hierarchy Husserl and Meinong).13 The original versions
is identified with the Kantian operation of of such systems were metaphysical hierarchies in
synthesis: the act by which thought ‘‘unifies the which the lower modes or orders of object
manifold of sense,’’ supplying a necessary connec- depended upon the higher ones as mere images
tion where sense itself would yield only contin- (phenomena). But after a certain inversion (an
gently connected data. Thus these systems were interpretation of Kant’s ‘‘Copernican revolution
not just supposed to be Kantian and hierarchical; in philosophy’’), the ‘‘lower’’ sensibilia or sensible
their hierarchies are themselves supposed to be representations could reappear as the founda-
Kantian. tions, on the basis of which higher orders might
To maintain this required considerable inge- be erected by thought – that is, by a repeated
nuity, however, because Kant himself doesn’t process of synthesis.
envision any such hierarchy. There are many These two sources are associated with different
important and familiar hierarchies in Kant: understandings of the function of synthesis, and
understanding–judgment–reason, for example, hence with different types of epistemological
or apprehension–reproduction–recognition. But system and different interpretations of Kant.
those hierarchies are not stepwise – they do not In the first case, synthesis generates categories:
result from the repeated application of a single pure a priori concepts which make possible an
operation – and are therefore also not open ended. object, and an objective (knowing) consciousness,
If one wanted to extend them further, there as such. The object and the consciousness remain
would be no obvious next step. In many important at each stage the same: in Hegel’s system, they are
respects, moreover, Kant’s system is non- the absolute and spirit, respectively, and the
hierarchical, as is particularly apparent from his system as a whole is supposed to demonstrate
characteristic two-dimensional presentations, for that the absolute is spirit, i.e., to overcome
example of the table of judgments and the table of (or ‘‘sublate’’) the subject–object dichotomy.
categories. By spreading the elements out on the In the second type of system, on the other hand,
page in that way, Kant expressly avoids arranging the pure a priori concepts at work in synthesis
them in any hierarchical order. remain the same as the process continues (at least
If stepwise hierarchical systems must be in an analogous sense). What synthesis achieves
imposed on Kant, however, rather than deriving at each stage is the knowledge or cognition of
from his works, why were they so popular in this a new, higher order of object. And although there

131
origins of verificationism

is no hierarchy of either type in Kant’s own work, immediately given. To the would-be hierarchy
the two different understandings of synthesis do builder, the thought naturally suggests itself that
each have their basis in Kant’s transcendental this operation could be repeated to yield further
deduction. Only, as we will see, the main basis types of object – ones which are, so to speak, even
for each is not to be found in the same version of more external (higher ‘‘above’’ the ultimate
Kant’s text. Thus we will find that Natorp, whose foundation of sense).
system is of the first type, prefers the B-edition In the B edition, in contrast, Kant takes
version, whereas Husserl prefers the A edition. vigorous steps to displace the temporal order
from any fundamental role. The objective, neces-
III natorp’s b-edition ‘‘object V x’’ sary ‘‘combination’’ (Verbindung) which is to be
supplied by the understanding in synthesis is now
To give an accurate account of either the A- or opposed not to the merely temporal order of
B-edition transcendental deduction, let alone of inner sense but to any form of sensible intuition
the differences between them, would be an in general (B129–30). Such a combination is
enormous task – far too large for me to attempt needed by any being whose intuition is sensible
here. Given that we are really interested in Kant’s rather than intellectual, or in other words by any
text as an anchor or jumping-off point for finite (discursive) rational being, whether or not its
fundamentally un-Kantian ideas, a more super- sensibility has the forms of time and space (B135);
ficial reading may, in any case, actually be of more the pure concepts of the understanding are thus
use than a deeper and more comprehensive one.
valid for any such being in general (B148, 150).
And, at least on such a superficial reading, the main
As a consequence we can no longer get a clear
difference between the two editions lies in the role
picture of the uncombined manifold to which the
of the time series of conscious representations.
understanding brings its necessity: certainly we
In the A edition, the deduction proper begins
are not entitled to assume that it has a serial order.
with the observation that, since all our representa-
From a Hegelian point of view, however, this
tions belong, as ‘‘modifications of the mind,’’ to
absence of a picture is a sign that we have moved
inner sense, all our Erkentnisse – all our cognitions
from the level of representation (Vorstellung) to
or items of knowledge – ‘‘are ultimately subject to
the higher or purer level of the concept (Begriff).
the formal condition of inner sense, namely
Furthermore, the B edition contains another
time, as that in which they must all collectively
be ordered, connected, and brought into relation- hopeful sign for the would-be Hegelian system
ships.’’14 There follows a description of the three builder. For, although the three stages of
stages of synthesis mentioned above (apprehen- synthesis have disappeared from the deduction,
sion, reproduction, and recognition), which synthesis now pops up in a different and more
appear to be three stages in that ordering process. interesting place: within the table of categories
Thus Kant’s problem of empirical synthesis seems itself. In that table, recall, the categories are
to flow in a natural way from a problem already organized under four headings: quantity, quality,
raised by Hume. Roughly speaking: to consider a relation, and modality. In the B edition, Kant
given time series of representations as representa- draws attention to the fact that there are three
tions of one single external object, I must suppose categories in each of these ‘‘classes,’’ and adds that
necessary connections between them. Any true the third is always a ‘‘combination’’ (again:
experience (Erfahrung) must therefore contain Verbindung) of the first two (B110–11). Hence
such necessity. But – Kant and Hume agree – such we see, first, that there is indeed some hierarchy
necessity is never to be found in the data of within the categories, at least on a local scale, and,
sense themselves. Hence the synthetic function second – given that all ‘‘combination’’ results
of thought will be to supply the missing from synthesis as an act of the understanding
necessity, thus building a new, external, spatio- (B130) – that synthesis is or can be a transition
temporal object on the basis of the temporally between pure concepts, rather than between
ordered sensible representations which are different kinds of object.

132
stone

Interpreters of Kant (and of Hegel) might well from one point of view, with Kant’s table of
disagree about the significance of all this, but judgments, and, from another point of view, with
Natorp understands matters as follows. It is, his table of categories.18
he says, wrong to imagine a temporal order of In developing this system of logical
representations preceding the work of synthesis, Grundfunktionen, Natorp takes his cue from
‘‘as if the external, spatial world left over an inner, Kant’s remark that the third category in each
nonspatial, merely temporal world of psychic class is a combination or synthesis of the first two.
being.’’15 When we consider any ordered manifold But he goes beyond his Kantian basis in three
or series, we are already considering an object of respects. (1) Where Kant merely opposes the first
experience (Erfahrung), and thus presupposing two categories of each class to the third, Natorp
synthesis, the contribution of thought without puts all three into a single three-step order, and
which all experience is impossible. According to moreover maintains, explicitly against Kant,
Natorp, this was always Kant’s view: the priority that the three steps within each class can be
of time in the A deduction is not metaphysical/ matched up to the three steps of the others: such a
epistemic, but merely logical, and it is ‘‘not correspondence will appear as ‘‘indispensably
actually Kant’s fault’’ if people have gone astray necessary’’ to anyone who understands the origin
on this point (ibid.). Still, the B deduction is of the categories in the ‘‘fundamental process of
superior, because it eliminates all ambiguity synthetic unity.’’19 (2) Natorp sees the exact same
about this and related matters (275–76). process at work in the transition from one class
If any order of representations is already the to another. The class of relation, in particular, is
result of synthesis, then the pure Urerlebnis – i.e., represented as resulting from the synthesis of the
primordial ‘‘experience’’ considered as purely two previous classes, which are quantity and
passive and (therefore) as purely subjective, pure quality (in that order) (66). As for the fourth
sense without thought – is as such the purely class, Kant himself says that it is special: that
‘‘undetermined,’’ a pure ‘‘chaos.’’16 It is therefore the categories of modality are determinations, not
not a realm of objects of some fundamental of the object but of its relationship to our cognitive
type, which could serve as the foundation for a faculties. Natorp takes this to mean that modality
hierarchical system of such types. One ought not is a third, synthetic step in a series whose first two
to think of inner and outer sense ‘‘as if we had to steps are the original Grundakt and the prior
do [here] with two realms of objects lying next to three classes (quantity, quality, and relation) taken
one another’’ (70). The foundation of Natorp’s as a whole.20 (3) The three-part series which is
system therefore lies not in the most immediate established and repeated, on different levels,
objects but in the most immediate concepts: within the system of categories is not confined to
in logic, ‘‘as ‘transcendental’ logic in Kant’s that system; rather, a repeated application of the
sense.’’17 It begins with the ‘‘fundamental act of same method leads, in the remainder of Natorp’s
knowing,’’ which Natorp identifies with Kant’s book, to a further series of pure concepts: those of
supreme act of synthetic unity, i.e., with the pure arithmetic (including transfinite and complex
transcendental unity of apperception, but which arithmetic), geometry, kinematics, dynamics, and
he also explains, in more Hegelian fashion, as ‘‘the energetics.
fundamental correlation of separation and That the spatial and temporal orders themselves
uniting’’ (44). This is the fundamental act of appear within this hierarchy of pure concepts
determination, ‘‘in which there first comes to be seems to put Natorp in opposition to Kant. Kant
any determinateness whatsoever for thought’’ does emphasize, in the B edition, that the temporal
(39); as such it is the source both of all concepts order is not fundamental, but he does so by stres-
and of all judgments, since ‘‘every judgment is the sing that the categories are valid even for rational
originary positing of a concept in relation to a beings whose intuition does not, like ours, have the
something which is to be conceived’’ (42). What form of time and space. This makes it seem, if
follows from it first – the system of ‘‘fundamental anything, even clearer that the pure form of our
logical functions’’ – is therefore to be identified, intuition is an independent factor which enters

133
origins of verificationism

(via the Schematism) into an explanation of how between good and bad infinities.24 Most funda-
we can apply the categories to experience. Natorp mentally: if we ask what the series of pure logical
is well aware of this difficulty. He responds, first, determinations are supposed to determine, then,
that he and his fellow neo-Kantians have been recall, Hegel can answer either ‘‘the absolute’’ or
forced to abandon this two-factor view by Kant ‘‘spirit.’’ The good infinity of the system means
himself: the very principle of Kant’s transcen- that, in its final moment, logic is the pure idea
dental philosophy demands that these supposedly both in and for itself – the idea both of the
different factors be understood as a single unity, absolute object and of the absolute subject.
which may as a whole be called ‘‘pure thought’’ Natorp agrees that if ‘‘the work of knowledge’’
(2–3). Second, he claims that Kant himself was could be ‘‘closed off’’ then ‘‘the opposing relation-
guilty more of misleading presentation than of real ship of the subjective and the objective would be
confusion on this, and that, in particular, the entirely sublated’’;25 the characterization of the
B-edition deduction makes it unambiguously ultimately concrete subject, ‘‘universal spirit,’’
clear that all spatio-temporal order is a result of would at the same time include the complete
synthesis, rather than an independent factor which characterization of its object.26 As it stands,
could co-determine it (275–76). This, however, is however, the tasks of subjectivization and objec-
a very strained reading of Kant: there is every tivization are both open ended and uncompletable,
reason to think of Natorp more as a neo-Hegelian and logic has to do unambiguously with the
than a neo-Kantian. latter: not with thinking, but with ‘‘the thought’’
There is, nevertheless, an important disagree- (das Gedachte).27
ment between Natorp and Hegel – one which For Natorp, therefore, the hierarchy of pure
clearly marks him, at least in his own mind, as a a priori concepts is a hierarchy of determinations
Kantian. Hegel famously distinguishes between of the object. But the object so determined is not
two kinds of infinite: ‘‘good’’ and ‘‘bad.’’ The good some individual object – a tree, say, or a house.
infinite is without limit because it closes in on itself. Indeed, the determinations necessary to think
The final stage of Hegel’s logic, for example, is the an individual as distinct from others (that it is
absolute idea, whose moments are the absolute idea one, of a certain kind, etc.) are only developed as
as such, method, and system: Hegelian logic, in the process continues. Logic, according to Natorp,
other words, ‘‘concludes [. . .] by grasping the is rather characterized by a turn away from
concept of itself, as the pure idea for which the idea ‘‘objects’’ to ‘‘the object’’ (34). As in Hegel, that
is.’’21 The infinite series of pure a priori concepts in is, we are talking about the one object of the
Natorp’s stepwise and open-ended hierarchical one unified experience – ultimately, in the ideal
system, in contrast, is a prime example of the bad limit, about a single, absolutely necessary connect-
infinite, in which ‘‘something becomes another, edness which embraces all experience and comple-
but the other is itself something, and so equally tely determines it (69, 277). But since, for Natorp,
becomes another, and so on in infinitum.’’22 this is merely an ideal limit, we are not entitled
Natorp, in fact, explicitly associates the infinity to call it ‘‘the absolute’’ (if we want to use that term
of his own method with Hegel’s bad infinite, and for something, Natorp suggests, we could apply
identifies the latter with the infinity of Kantian it to the logical method itself (218)). If we call it
idea as merely regulative: as an infinite task or ‘‘the object,’’ indeed, then we should understand
‘‘ought’’ for the merely finite understanding.23 objectum here as equivalent to Greek problēma
Thus Natorp’s Kantianism amounts, in his own and hence to the German Vorwurf – a problem,
eyes, to a rejection of the Hegelian absolute idea in task, or project that is ‘‘thrown before’’ us – rather
favor of the Kantian regulative one, or of a closed than as a determinate something which stands over
system of determinations in favor of an open-ended against us (an antikeimenon or Gegenstand).28
series of them. But, better still, we should let the infinite series of
This one disagreement has far-reaching conse- determinations themselves tell us what is deter-
quences, as we might expect, given Hegel’s own mined: in itself, before any determination, it is a
emphasis on the importance of the distinction mere X.29 This is what it means to say, for Natorp,

134
stone

that the object is an infinitely determinable X, Kant misunderstood his own discovery and made
which corresponds – but always only a terrible mistake. ‘‘The transcendental deduction
inadequately – to a Kantian idea. of the first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason
But Natorp further associates his bad-infinite, actually already moves on phenomenological
Kantian logical process with a view of scientific ground’’ – which is to say on the correct ground
progress as open ended: even though science at for philosophy – ‘‘but Kant misinterpreted that
every stage discovers a priori concepts, which are ground as psychological, and therefore himself
secure against any future revolution,30 still there again relinquished it.’’32
are always further such concepts to be discovered, It is not surprising that Husserl would say this
and hence further such revolutions to come. about Kant, considering the way he sees the
The series of determinations of the X are thus givenness of external objects. His picture in
not only the stages of Natorp’s stepwise system but Ideen I (and note that we are back with a structure
also the stages of scientific progress: a scientific of which one could easily draw a picture) is
revolution is always a philosophical discovery, in essentially the very one Natorp rejects as absurd.
which further a priori determinations of the object The fundamental process is the ‘‘constitution’’ of
of experience come to light. All great scientific something external – in the most basic case,
Forscher, from Plato on, have been ‘‘philosophi- of a Ding, i.e., a sensible object in the realm
cally disposed’’ (366).31 In this way of under- of nature – by means of time series of conscious
standing our epistemic task, in other words – this states, which Husserl calls Erlebnisse.33 Imagine,
way of understanding our progressive determina- for example, that the Ding being constituted is
tion of the object ¼ X – the main question will be a tree. Although there are various indirect ways
not how experience can build up support for our in which such an external object can be given
hypotheses (judgments) but rather how it can lead or ‘‘posited’’ (for example, one might guess or
us to recognize more objective and determinate a deduce or remember that it is or was present),
priori concepts. To find a historical background these all rest, according to Husserl, on the
against which Carnap’s motivations make sense, possibility of an ‘‘originary’’ or ‘‘in-person’’ kind
we will have to look elsewhere. of positing, which in the case of Dinge is
perception.34 So for the sake of simplicity we
may think of the series of positing Erlebnisse as
IV husserl’s a-edition ‘‘object V x’’
a series of tree-perceptions. The two most impor-
We have seen, in Natorp, a certain diagnosis of tant components of such a perceptual Erlebnis
the relationship between the A- and B-edition are the noesis, which is, roughly speaking, an
versions of the transcendental deduction. The A act of consciousness – in this case, and an act
edition, according to Natorp, gives the misleading of tree-perception – and the noema, which is
impression that there is a special realm of a kind of proper object of the noesis: in this case,
temporally ordered psychic objects (the realm of the tree-percept as such.35 The noema, here,
inner sense), presupposed before thought begins can be thought of as the claim that a certain
its work of synthesis. But Kant could never have object (this tree here) is present. Or that, rather,
meant that – after all, an inner, psychic object describes the central component of the noema,
would be an object of experience no less that an the noematic ‘‘core’’ or ‘‘sense’’:36 the noema as a
external, physical one, and so already a result of whole also makes further, ‘‘subjective’’ claims, for
synthesis. Thus Natorp prefers the clearer example that the tree is at a certain distance, seen
formulation of the B deduction. from a certain point of view, etc. The noesis, on the
Broadly speaking, Husserl agrees. He agrees, other hand, consists of sense data and something
that is, that Kant abandoned the A deduction like an interpretation of those data.37 In effect, the
because it seemed to presuppose a special realm of noesis is an act of making the claim of the noema
objects which, from Kant’s own point of view, by so interpreting the data. The positing is
could only be understood as psychic objects of rational if the data ‘‘fulfill’’ the noematic
inner sense. According to Husserl, however, sense – that is, justify its claim.38 It is when

135
origins of verificationism

I carry out such a rational, originary positing Husserl calls the way a Ding like the tree is
that the tree is actually given: a ‘‘positing ray’’ given – in stages, each of which is
then leaves my pure or transcendental ego and inadequate – ‘‘adumbration’’ (Abschattung).
travels through the noesis and the noematic sense For objects so given, there is a Humean,
to reach the transcendent object (in our case, A-edition problem of synthesis. The determina-
the tree).39 tions contained in a perceptual Erlebnis, or in
The problem of empirical synthesis arises a closed series of Erlebnisse, are never sufficient
because such perceptual positing is always ‘‘inade- to posit the transcendent object. In positing
quate,’’ in two ways. First, the data never that object, in other words, I must always posit
completely fulfill the noema. When I see a tree, a further series of such determinations which is
for example, I see only the side facing me; there necessarily coming. In positing the tree, for
are no data corresponding to the other side. What I example, I posit not only the presence of this
see, however – what the noema claims is present – is tree-side (what is ‘‘properly’’ seen), but also that,
not merely a seen-tree-side, but a tree. Thus, if I walk around the tree, and all goes well, the
the noema always makes a claim beyond what the other side will necessarily appear. But, since
data can support; the noesis is always an over- the determinations which attach to the tree in
interpreting of the data. Second, the noema itself my present Erlebnis are not sufficient to require
never even makes a complete claim about the this series, I seem to have no grounds for positing
object. Suppose, for example, that I have never its necessity.
seen the other side and have no idea what it looks Husserl’s solution to this problem is at the
like. The noema claims (i.e., I am certain, on the same time his version of the A-edition deduction.
basis of the data) that there is another side, but What Kant noticed in the A edition, according to
makes no detailed claims about its appearance. Husserl, but himself failed to understand, is that
I might, moreover, turn out to be wrong about a certain kind of object is not given to us
the details of even the side I can see: when I get inadequately: namely, the pure Erlebnisse
closer, for example, I might realize that it looks themselves. ‘‘We perceive the Ding by virtue of
different than I thought. I will then say that I did the fact that it is ‘adumbrated’ according to all
see this tree before – that is, that the central claim the determinations which ‘actually’ and properly
of my old noema was correct, and was justified [eigentlich] ‘fall’ within the perception in a given
by the data in my old noesis – but that that claim case,’’ but ‘‘an Erlebnis is not adumbrated ’’ (x 42,
was in detail incorrect. Even the claims which are 77). Erlebnisse, that is, are given in intellectual
actually present in the noematic sense, and even intuition. Kant rejected the A-edition approach as
the justified or ‘‘fulfilled’’ ones, in other words, psychologistic because he failed to appreciate
are provisional, and require further observation this point. Representations conceived as percep-
to back them up. tible (objects of inner sense), would, as Natorp
says, already presuppose synthesis, and Kant was
Positing on the ground of the in-person
appearance of a Ding is indeed rational, but confused into believing that representations could
the appearance is nevertheless a one-sided, only be given in some kind of sensible intuition
‘‘imperfect’’ appearance; what stands there as because he blamed the inadequate givenness of
consciously known in-person is not only what external objects on our defectiveness as knowers.
‘‘properly [eigentlich]’’ appears, but rather In fact, however, according to Husserl, the defect
simply this Ding itself, the whole, according lies in the mode of being of those objects
to the entire, although only one-sidedly intui- themselves. Dinge, and everything that depends
tive and moreover multiply undetermined, on them, are not fully true beings; there is no
noematic sense.
complete adaequatio between them and their
A Ding-reality, a being in such a sense, can cause of being – which, Husserl claims, is my
in principle appear only ‘‘inadequately’’ in a rational positing. ‘‘Therein is manifested
closed appearance. (x 138, 286) a difference-in-principle of modes of being: the

136
stone

most cardinal such difference which there is at all, which alone is true in the higher sense, the world
that between consciousness and reality’’ (ibid.). of absolute spirit.’’42
This version of Kant’s Copernican revolution, Having, however, construed the relationship
in which the realm of my consciousness replaces between consciousness and its objects in this way,
the intelligible realm (the realm of true beings, of as the ‘‘most cardinal’’ difference in mode of
Dinge an sich), and my pure ego replaces God as being, it is natural to recognize other, lesser
cause of being of the world, suggests a solution differences, and thus to erect something like a
to the problem of empirical synthesis which is classical Aristotelian/Neoplatonic metaphysical
both an interpretation of the A deduction and an hierarchy. In Husserl’s system, the device which
inverted Neoplatonism. The disunity of sensible generates that hierarchy is ‘‘founded positing.’’43
objects, on this view – their dispersal into stages, Roughly speaking: while a direct interpretation
none of which contains the necessity required of sense data always yields Dinge, further inter-
to connect it to the others – is a sign of their pretations can be built on top of that one. Thus, for
dependency on a higher realm of being. For the example, a Ding in its changes can be taken as
series of all my Erlebnisse is essentially and standing for a psychological object (a soul).44
necessarily unified: each Erlebnis contains Further layers of interpretation (together with the
components (outside its noesis and noema) incorporation of emotional and volitional data)
which serve as retrospective and anticipatory then yield ‘‘higher-order’’ objects in the realms
‘‘halos’’ of those that precede and follow it. of culture or spirit (Geist). A hierarchy of found-
Hence the ever-present possibility of pure ing within the positing noeses thus gives rise to a
reflection: that any Erlebnis might, at any time, hierarchy of modes of being in the transcendent
become the object of a completely adequate world. This hierarchy, like Natorp’s, is stepwise
positing.40 But that necessary unity is itself a and, apparently, open ended: though Husserl
consequence of Kant’s transcendental unity of never, to my knowledge, actually says that it is
apperception: i.e., of the absolute unity of my ego, infinite, nothing in the system prevents its being
and the fact that the Erlebnisse are all mine.41 so. But the levels in this A-edition system are
From that absolute unity (the One Beyond Being) not categories, not levels of a priori determination
emanates the essential and necessary unity of of the object. They are, rather, different orders of
the intelligible world, and the lesser unity and object: different modes of being, to each of which
being of sensible things depend, in turn, on that the same logical categories (analogously) apply.
essential unity of the Erlebnisstrom. The necessity So when Husserl says that the object is an infinitely
which is missing from the Ding-as-posited (from determinable X, he is not referring to the
the positing noeses and noemata as such) is to be potential infinity of this constitutional hierarchy.
found in the full Erlebnisse of which those To see what he does mean, notice first that
positings are components, in their essential the (‘‘immanent’’) time sequence of the pure
relation to all future and past Erlebnisse. Thus Erlebnisse is not to be identified with the
the necessity I posit in the future series of tree- transcendent time of events in the external
appearances, for example, is nothing that is world. When the tree turns out, on closer inspec-
found in the tree-itself-as-appearing; it is, rather, tion, to look different than I originally thought,
the necessary unity of my own consciousness. Erlebnisse at earlier and later immanent times
Husserlian phenomenology is supposed to lead me each posit the same tree as having been different
to recognize this: that my consciousness is a realm throughout transcendent or cosmic time (the tree
of necessity and truth, compared to which every- always really looked different than it at first
thing external is relative, contingent, and depen- seemed to look). Every Ding, and in general every
dent. Thus, unlike Kantian critique, it is transcendent object – every object given by
redemptive. It speaks with the voice of the adumbration – is constantly, with respect to
Gnostic paraclete: it ‘‘redeems us theoretically immanent time, in a state of flux: the determina-
from the absolutizing of this world and opens for tions with which it is posited (components of the
us the only scientific entry-gate into the world noematic sense) constantly change, and all are in

137
origins of verificationism

principle changeable and replaceable. It follows Under Husserl’s interpretation of Kant, moreover,
that that within the sense which claims the the connection is natural. That a Ding, or any
existence of this object (for example, of this tree transcendent object, always allows and indeed
here) is not to be identified with any of them. requires further determinations beyond what are
Rather, it is something different from all determi- found in any positing of it is a consequence of the
nations, which always allows and indeed requires fact that the object itself – the subject of all its
further ones – in principle, an infinite series of predicates – is a mere X: i.e., a consequence of
them. What is posited in it is a mere infinitely the object’s materiality. Material beings, which
determinable X: are always in flux, which become and pass away,
are not fully true beings, but mere phenomena,
We say that the intentional object is constantly
and such being and unity as they possess is due
in conscious awareness in the continuous or
synthetic progress of consciousness, but is the presence in the Erlebnisstrom of a necessary
always again ‘‘otherwise given’’ therein; it is law to which they inadequately correspond.
‘‘the same’’; it is merely given with other That law is itself something like a concept which
predicates, with another determination- can never be exemplified in experience. Husserl
content; ‘‘it’’ merely shows itself from different says: adequate Ding-givenness is ‘‘an idea in
sides, whereby the predicates which remain the Kantian sense.’’48
undetermined have been further determined Husserl thus uses the exact same Kantian
[. . .] the identical intentional ‘‘object’’ is terminology as Natorp, and also intends to
evidently distinguished from the changing interpret (and correct) Kant. But their Kants,
and alterable ‘‘predicates.’’ It is distinguished
and therefore the meanings of their terms, are
as the central noematic moment: the ‘‘object,’’
[. . .] the ‘‘identical,’’ – the pure X in abstrac-
different. If a hierarchy proceeds from bottom
tion from all predicates.45 to top, then Natorp’s infinite series of determina-
tions is vertical: it is identical to the series of
This fits in with inverted Neoplatonism. It is, hierarchical levels, each of which involves a
in fact, a Neoplatonist version of the passage in further a priori concept to which the object must
which Aristotle introduces matter: because a conform. For Husserl, in contrast, the infinite
physical substance receives opposite determina- series of determinations is horizontal: what is
tions successively, there must be some third thing determined is a particular object at a particular
(a tertium quid) which receives them, and the level in his hierarchy; it has nothing directly to
physical substance is essentially just this third do with the generation of the hierarchy itself.
thing, prime matter, which is without any deter- This lends itself to a rather different picture of
minations of its own.46 But it is also an interpreta- scientific progress, and of the problems involved
tion of the passage where the ‘‘object ¼ X’’ first
in its open-endedness. The problem of induction –
turns up in the A deduction:
which in Natorp’s Grundlagen is nowhere to be
What, then, does one understand, if one speaks found – now takes on great significance: Husserl
of an object which corresponds to knowledge, claims, in fact, that it can be solved (non-
and thus also is different from it? It is easy skeptically) only by a phenomenological idealism
to see that this object must be thought like his own (x 20, 37; x 79, 159). If that solution
merely as a something in general ¼ X, because looks unattractive, however, then verificationism
we have nothing outside our knowledge might well present itself as an alternative.
against which we could set this knowledge as
corresponding.47
V carnap’s response to husserl
Kant, in the introduction to the A edition, seems
to make this connection himself. A synthetic The system of the Aufbau follows that of Husserl’s
judgment, he says, in connecting a subject to Ideen. That is true on the level of terminology
a predicate not contained in it (and possibly (e.g., Erlebnis, Ding) and of gross structure
even opposed to it), implicitly bases itself on (e.g., nature, soul, Geist). But we are now in a
some third thing, which Kant calls an ‘‘X’’ (A8). position to see that the resemblance is far deeper.

138
stone

The Aufbau hierarchy is, as Carnap explicitly that Carnap gives for rejecting the doctrine of
says, a hierarchy of ‘‘modes of being.’’49 It begins infinite determinability is that a finite number
with a temporal series of fundamental objects, of ‘‘indicators’’ (Kennzeichen) are always suffi-
and the problem is, given objects of that kind, cient, given a proper constitutional definition, to
how to get to further kinds at higher levels. determine whether an object is present. ‘‘If such
In other words, it is an A-edition system of the a designation [Kennzeichnung] is in place, then
same kind as Husserl’s, not a B-edition system the object is no longer an X, but rather some-
like Natorp’s. thing univocally determined, whose complete
Not that Carnap has been reading only Husserl, description then still remains, to be sure, an
of course: as the bibliography makes clear, he has unfulfillable task’’ (x 179L, 253). What is meant
been reading many things, Natorp among them. by a Kennzeichen here is something like a mark
And, Carnap being who he is, there are attempts in or feature by which a particular object can
the Aufbau to treat Natorp tolerantly – to find an be identified – for example, the identification
interpretation of him according to which Carnap of a cobra (Brillenschlange) by the pattern of
can agree with much of what he says and disagree broken eyeglasses (Brillen) on its head, or of the
politely with the rest. In particular, and as others Feldberg by its height and position (x 49, 69;
have noted, the attempt to show that scientific x 13,16). But such identifying marks or features
statements are ‘‘structural’’ does bear some have nothing in common with Natorp’s series
relationship to neo-Kantian projects.50 Moreover, of a priori determinations of the absolute object.
Carnap maintains that his constitutional system They do, however, have everything in common
is neutral on the distinction between systems of with Husserl’s ‘‘determinations,’’ which are
concepts and systems of objects (x 5, 5), which precisely marks or features of the posited object.
sounds like (and is probably intended to sound According to Husserl, a finite series of them is
like) a declaration of neutrality on the A vs. B never sufficient to establish that a given transcen-
dichotomy we have explored above. Nevertheless, dent object is present; what is ‘‘properly’’
I think such nods towards neo-Kantianism are (eigentlich) seen always falls short of what is
superficial. Without going into the details here, posited. To this Carnap replies that, however
we can at least see a good indication of that much beyond mere perception we may use in
from Carnap’s treatment of the issue at hand, identifying an object, it must be the case, if we are
namely the infinitely determinable object ¼ X. using language scientifically and responsibly, that
Recall that Carnap presents his view as a we can go back and give a finite basis for our
rejection of Natorp’s. That is puzzling on two identification. A botanist, like the rest of us, will
accounts. First, if we were to take seriously the likely establish the presence of a certain tree – say,
idea that the Aufbau system is supposed to a tree of a certain species – ‘‘intuitively,’’ which is
parallel Natorp’s, we should understand the to say: the botanist’s actual psychological process
constitutional levels of the system as progressive does not involve first recognizing the indicators
determinations of the object. But there is no of a certain species, then deducing that
indication that the series of such levels must come (by definition) it must be present. But
to an end, and, indeed, there is good reason to
think that it does not. Michael Friedman, noticing the intuitive recognition [. . .] can be of use in
this, has remarked that, on the Aufbau system further scientific development [Verarbeitung]
carefully considered, ‘‘the Marburg doctrine of only because it also is possible to state the
the never completed ‘X’ turns out to be correct, indicators [. . .] explicitly, to compare them
after all, at least so far as physical [. . .] objects with the perception, and thus to justify the
are concerned.’’51 Second, however, and more intuition rationally. (x 100, 139)52
fundamentally, this identification of the series
In order to isolate such indicators,
of constitutional levels with the series of deter-
minations of the X is incorrect, as is especially The botanist must ask himself, in reconstruct-
clear in the passage in question. For the reason ing the recognition of the plants: what in the

139
origins of verificationism

experienced [erlebte] recognition was the found in the data. The point, in other words, is
properly [eigentlich] seen, and what in it to show that the object is not, in Husserl’s sense,
was apperceptive processing [Verarbeitung]? a mere infinitely determinable X, which is in
(Ibid.) principle only ever posited inadequately and
The constitutional system is supposed to accom- provisionally, i.e., as in inadequate correspon-
plish this same task on a grander scale: it is dence with a Kantian idea found in the realm
of pure consciousness.
‘‘a rational reconstruction of the entire, for the
Given the details of Husserl’s system, it is
most part intuitively performed, construction
relatively easy to see why Carnap would want
[Aufbau] of science’’ (ibid.). Hence the fiction
to refute his view on this particular point.
involved in rational reconstruction is not supposed
If objects of any level can in principle be
to be an arbitrary one – not, as Quine puts it, mere
adequately given, then the difference in mode of
‘‘make-believe.’’53 The system does not, of course,
being between pure consciousness and external
aim ‘‘to reproduce the cognitive process in all its
objects is no longer particularly fundamental.56
parts’’: just as the botanist would not include every
If the verificationist principle is correct, however,
mark by which a species can be recognized, it
then it must be the case that every object can be
includes only so many of the relationships among
adequately given, because we cannot even
experiences ‘‘as are required for one to be able, in
meaningfully refer to something for which we
principle, to constitute actuality from them.’’54
are in principle unwilling to produce finite
That selection is indeed arbitrary (it makes no
indicators. But note that the strict form of
sense to ask whether the right indicators have been
verificationism – the form which is tied to strict
chosen, out of the many possibilities). But that
reductionism – is not central to this motivation.
much, also, is mere selectiveness, not fiction. The
The key is ‘‘rational reconstruction’’: that is, the
fiction – the deviation of the reconstructed story
demonstration that finite, discursive knowers,
from the actual psychological process – is not
who – in a context of justification, at least –
arbitrary at all: it is precisely the fiction that,
ought in principle to begin with a finite series
in recognizing the object, we begin with what we
of data, with a finite stretch of the eigentlich
really, actually, ‘‘properly’’ see: with a closed finite
Gesehene, can nevertheless have a right to all
series of the eigentlich Gesehene. The rational
our scientific positings, without recourse to
reconstruction is supposed to show that, under
any supersensible idea of necessity. Thus when
that fictional assumption, it would still be possible
Carnap comes, later, to feel that the strict
to erect the whole structure of actuality, and to do
verificationist principle has failed, he turns natu-
so rationally: in the constitutional system, in
rally to a consideration of less strict ways in which
other words, ‘‘intuitive knowledge is replaced by
such a discursive knower might
discursive reasoning’’ (x 54, 74).
gain a right to posit determinate
But what is the point of showing this, given
objects of experience: he turns,
that, as is clear even in the Aufbau, we do not
that is, to a consideration of
normally have the whole series of indicators in
inductive logic.
hand to make some identification with absolute
certainty?55 To explain the full significance of
notes
this would take us too far afield into Carnap’s
motivations, but it is easy enough to see the 1 Rudolf Carnap, Der logische Aufbau der Welt, 4th
immediate point: namely, that if a finite series ed. (Hamburg: Meiner, 1974) x 179L, 253.
of determinations – one I can in principle expect (This edition is identical to the original one of
1928 except for a new foreword added in 1961
to check for during my finite future – is sufficient,
and a new note and supplemental bibliography
in principle, to establish the presence of some
added in 1966.)
external object, then I am entitled now to claim
(or ‘‘posit’’) the presence of that object without 2 See the conditions on LO in‘‘The Methodological
relying on some necessity which is never to be Character of Theoretical Concepts,’’ Minnesota

140
stone

Studies in the Philosophy of Science 1 (1956): 41^ 42: Philosophie: Erster Teil: Kritische Ideengeschichte,
observability of primitives, explicit definability of Husserliana 7, ed. Rudolf Boehm (The Hague:
other terms, existence of a finite model, construc- Nijhoff,1956) 230 ^ 87.
tivism, extensionality.
10 Cf. Friedman, Parting of theWays 72, where the
3 ‘‘Epistemology Naturalized’’ in Ontological ‘‘serial or stepwise methodological sequence’’ of
Relativity and Other Essays (New York: Columbia the Aufbau is taken as evidence of its Marburg
UP,1969) 71^72. roots.

4 See Michael Friedman, A Parting of the Ways: 11 Including to many lesser known figures who get
Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger (Chicago and La mentioned in the Aufbaue.g., Theodor Ziehen
Salle, IL: Open Court, 2000); ‘‘Carnap’s Aufbau and Hans Driesch (see x 3, 3). Cf. C. Ulises
Reconsidered’’ in Reconsidering Logical Positivism Moulines, ‘‘Hintergru«nde der Erkenntnistheorie
(New York: Cambridge UP, 1999) 89^113; des fru«hen Carnap,’’ Grazer philosophische Studien
‘‘Epistemology in the Aufbau’’ in idem 114 ^ 62; 23 (1985):10.
Alan Richardson, Carnap’s Construction of the World:
The Aufbau and the Emergence of Logical Empiricism 12 See, for example, Enzyklopa«die der philoso-
(New York: Cambridge UP, 1998); Werner Sauer, phischen Wissenschaften (1830) (Hamburg: Meiner,
‘‘Carnaps Aufbau in kantianischer Sicht,’’Grazer phi- 1991) x 239A,195.
losophische Studien 23 (1985):19^35.
13 See especially Brentano’s Von der mannigfachen
5 See Aufbau, Foreword to 2nd ed., x. Bedeutung des Seienden nach Aristoteles (Freiburg:
Herder,1862).
6 For more discussion of Carnap’s response to
Husserl, see also, in addition to my own 14 Kritik der reinen Vernunft, ed. Raymund Schmidt,
‘‘Heidegger and Carnap on the Overcoming of 3rd ed., Philosophische Bibliothek, vol. 37a
Metaphysics’’ (forthcoming), Verena Mayer, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1990) (henceforth KrV).
‘‘Carnap und Husserl’’ in Science and Subjectivity: A99.
The Vienna Circle and Twentieth Century Philosophy,
eds. David Bell and Wilhelm Vossenkuhl (Berlin: 15 Natorp, Die logischen Grundlagen der exakten
Akademie, 1992) 185^201; Alan Richardson, ‘‘The Wissenschaften (Leipzig and Berlin: Teubner,
Geometry of Knowledge: Lewis, Becker, Carnap 1910) 292.
and the Formalization of Philosophy in the 1920s,’’ 16 Natorp, Allgemeine Psychologie nach kritischer
Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 34 Methode, Erstes Buch: Objekt und Methode der
(2003): 175; and ‘‘Conceiving, Experiencing, and Psychologie (Tu«bingen: Mohr-Siebeck, 1912) 78, 80.
Conceiving Experiencing: Neo-Kantianism and Both Erfahrung and Erlebnis are normally
the History of the Concept of Experience,’’ Topoi
translated as ‘‘experience.’’ But Kant exclusively
22 (2003): 66, n. 5; Sahorta Sarkar,‘‘Husserl’s Role
uses the first term (and in fact the noun Erlebnis is
in Carnap’s Der Raum’’ in Language, Truth and
apparently not attested until after Kant: for some
Knowledge: Contributions to the Philosophy of Rudolf
discussion of its history, see Hans-Georg
Carnap, ed. Thomas Bonk (Boston: Kluwer, 2003);
Gadamer, Wahrheit und Methode: Grundzu«ge einer
Jean-Michel Roy, ‘‘Carnap’s Husserlian Reading of
philosophischen Hermeneutik, 3rd ed. (Tu«bingen:
the Aufbau’’ in Carnap Brought Home, eds.
Mohr-Siebeck, 1975) 60 ^ 66). Natorp uses
Steve Awodey and Carsten Klein (Chicago: Open
Erlebnis in approximately the way indicated in the
Court, 2004) 41^ 62.
text; Husserl, as we will see, uses it in a
7 Ideenzu einerreinen Pha«nomenologie und pha«nome- different sense.
nologischen Philosophie [1922], 2nd ed. (reprint,
Tu«bingen: Niemeyer,1993). 17 Grundlagen iv.

8 See Karl Schuhmann, Husserl Chronik 18 For the system of logical Grundfunktionen as the
(The Hague: Nijhoff,1977) 281. ‘‘development’’ (Entwicklung) of the primordial
Grundakt, see 49^52. (Entwicklung is a characteris-
9 The intended publication never took place. tically Hegelian term in this context.)
The text has since appeared as ‘‘Kant und die Idee Kant’s procedure in the metaphysical deduction
der Transzendentalphilosophie,’’ appendix to Erste (in which he takes a traditional classification of

141
origins of verificationism

judgments for granted and derives the categories 33 I will leave both of these terms untranslated.
from it) is criticized, but dismissed as inessential The English word ‘‘thing’’ is unsuited to such a
to his method, on 43^ 44. limited technical role: it sounds incoherent to say
‘‘not everything is a thing.’’ (Cf. the confusion
19 Grundlagen 63^ 64.The three-step process sup-
caused by this in Russell, Our Knowledge of the
posedly at work here is to all intents and
External World as a Field for Scientific Method in
purposes the three-step method of Hegelian
Philosophy (Chicago: Open Court, 1915) 89, 213.)
logic.The first demand of thought is, in each case,
On Erlebnis, see above, n.16.
‘‘that one must in any case say A,’’ but the second is
that ‘‘because one says A, one must then also 34 See Ideen I, x136, 282^ 85.
say B’’ ^ a B which is not simply other to the A,
but rather ‘‘its other’’ (55). There then follows 35 See Ideen I, x 88, 213^16; x 96, 199^200. For a
a third demand, for a ‘‘continuity of thought, in somewhat more detailed discussion of the
which the cases formerly distinguished as A and components of the Erlebnisse and their role in
non-A again unite under a higher point of view empirical synthesis, see my ‘‘On Husserl and
[Betrachtung]’’ (218). But the ‘‘appearance of a Cavellian Scepticism,’’ Philosophical Quarterly
closed connected whole’’ (Schein des geschlossenen 50 (2000): 11^18. A much more detailed discussion
Zusammenhanges) which arises in this way is to be found in my dissertation, ‘‘On Husserl
‘‘is always again sublated’’ (hebt sich immer wieder and Cavellian Skepticism, With Reference to the
auf) (93). Thus the process of thought itself is Thomistic Theory of Creation’’ (Harvard, 2000):
superordinate to its ‘‘individual stations’’; ‘‘every see especially x 3.3, 63^ 81.
posited endpoint becomes again the starting
36 For ‘‘sense’’ and ‘‘core’’ (which are technically
point of a new [. . .] step along the way of thought’’
not quite the same) see Ideen I, x130, 269^70;
(50). The primordial law of logic is the law of
this ‘‘process’’ or ‘‘method’’ (14 ^15). x 132, 273; and cf. x91,189.

20 See especially Grundlagen 86 ^ 87. For Kant’s 37 Often (e.g., x 85, 171^75), Husserl uses ‘‘noesis’’
statement in this respect, see KrV A219/B266 more narrowly, to refer specifically to the second,
(to which Natorp alludes at Grundlagen 84). interpretative subcomponent. See also Husserl’s
marginal note to x 88, published as Appendix 51
21 Enzyklopa«die x 243,196. to the Husserliana edition of Ideen I, ed. Karl
22 Ibid. x93,112. Schuhmann, and (in English) in Ideas Pertaining to a
Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological
23 Grundlagen 166,168, 51, 69. Philosophy: First Book, trans. F. Kersten (Boston:
24 ‘‘The fundamental concept of philosophy [. . .] Kluwer,1982) 213, n. 2.
depends on it’’ (Enzyklopa«die x 95A,114). 38 See again Ideen I, x136, 282^ 85.
25 Allgemeine Psychologie 62. 39 For the correlation of rationality and actuality
26 Ibid. 227. or being, see x135, 280 ^ 81; x 142, 295^97; for the
positing ray, see x 92,192.
27 Ibid.; Grundlagen 40 ^ 42, 36.
40 See x 38, 68 ^ 69; x 45, 83; x 83,167; x 144, 298.
28 Grundlagen 32^33; Allgemeine Psychologie 1, 66.
41 See x 78,150.
29 See especially Grundlagen 41; see also
Grundlagen 15, 33, 47, 96; Allgemeine Psychologie, loc. 42 ‘‘Kant und die Idee der
cit. Transzendentalphilosophie’’ 283.
30 See Grundlagen v. 43 There are actually various kinds of founded
positing, only one of which is directly relevant
31 See especially Natorp’s description of Galileo’s
here. This is not the place to go into all the
work (358 ^ 60); also, what he says about the
details of Husserl’s very complex system.
‘‘a priori character’’ of the principle that ‘‘every
See Ideen I, x93, 193^94; x x 116 ^19, 238 ^ 49 (note
event in nature must be represented as a mere
the reference to the Logische Untersuchungen 248,
transfer [Wanderung] of ‘energy’’’ (354).
n. 1); x 148, 308; also, Ideen zu einer reinen
32 Ideen I, x 62,119. Pha«nomenologie und pha«nomenologischen Philosophie,

142
stone

zweites Buch: Pha«nomenologische Untersuchungen zur


Konstitution, ed. Marly Biemel, Husserliana 4
(The Hague: Nijhoff,1952) x x 4 ^9, 4 ^21.
44 Ideen I, x17, 32; Ideen II, x14, 32.
45 Ideen I, x131, 271.
46 See Aristotle, Ph. 1.6.189a21^26; Plotinus,
Enn. 6.8.3.12^20.
47 KrVA104.
48 Ideen I, x143, 297^98.
49 Aufbau x 42, 57.
50 See especially x16, 20 ^21 and x x153^55,
204 ^ 09.
51 Parting oftheWays 84.
52 The sense of Verarbeitung here is difficult to
reproduce in English. Carnap uses the same term,
in the following quotation, for the ‘‘processing’’
of the given into objects by the synthetic
components of consciousness. Carnap is suggest-
ing, or rather taking for granted, that the use
of observations about plants, say, in the develop-
ment of higher level scientific classifications
and theories is similar to, or is a continuation of,
that ‘‘processing.’’
53 ‘‘Epistemology Naturalized’’ 75.
54 Aufbau x101,140.
55 This is clear because the constitutional defini-
tions of the Aufbau are all based on the fiction of
‘‘temporal separation of the given from its proces-
sing [Verarbeitung]’’ (x101, 139), i.e., on the fiction
that all of the data (the entire finite series corres-
ponding to the subject’s finite lifetime) are already
in. (Eigentlichkeit requires being-towards-death.)
56 In fact, from a certain technical point of
view there is then really only one realm of objects.
See Aufbau x 4, 4, and see my dissertation,
‘‘On Husserl and Cavellian Skepticism’’ 191, n. 272;
also my ‘‘Heidegger and Carnap’’ (forthcoming).

Abraham D. Stone
Department of Philosophy
University of California Santa Cruz
1156 High Street
Santa Cruz, CA 95064
USA
E-mail: abestone@ucsc.edu

You might also like